Reflections on the Ontological Status

Similar documents
IA Metaphysics & Mind S. Siriwardena (ss2032) 1 Personal Identity. Lecture 4 Animalism

The Ontological Status of Persons. Lynne Rudder Baker

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

The Ontological Status of Persons*

William Hasker s discussion of the Thomistic doctrine of the soul

Noonan, Harold (2010) The thinking animal problem and personal pronoun revisionism. Analysis, 70 (1). pp ISSN

The Zombies Among Us. Eric T. Olson To appear in Nous.

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

Rejoinder to Zimmerman. Dean Zimmerman defends a version of Substance Dualism Emergent Dualism

5 A Modal Version of the

Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory of the Self Locke, The Prince and the Cobbler Reid, Of Mr. Locke's Account of Our Personal Identity

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

An Alternative to Brain Death

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

Curriculum Vitae. Other Areas of Interest: Epistemology, Philosophy of Mind, and History of Philosophy.

Personal Identity and the Jehovah' s Witness View of the Resurrection

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Experiences Don t Sum

Joseph Kahiga Kiruki, Moi University Jason T. Eberl, IUPUI

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Meaning and Privacy. Guy Longworth 1 University of Warwick December

Locke s Essay, Book II, Chapter 27: Of Identity and Diversity

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Philosophy Courses Fall 2016

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

AQUINAS S FOURTH WAY: FROM GRADATIONS OF BEING

On An Alleged Non-Equivalence Between Dispositions And Disjunctive Properties

Brain Death and Irreplaceable Parts Christopher Tollefsen. I. Introduction

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

The Resurrection of Material Beings: Recomposition, Compaction and Miracles

Behavior and Other Minds: A Response to Functionalists

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas

IN THIS PAPER I will examine and criticize the arguments David

A note on Bishop s analysis of the causal argument for physicalism.

Aristotle and Aquinas

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

Intrinsic Properties Defined. Peter Vallentyne, Virginia Commonwealth University. Philosophical Studies 88 (1997):

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Today we re gonna start a number of lectures on two thinkers who reject the idea

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and. Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xvi, 286.

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Persons: Natural, Yet Ontologically Unique. Lynne Rudder Baker University of Massachusetts Amherst

The Mind/Body Problem

The Biological Foundation of Bioethics

Why Counterpart Theory and Three-Dimensionalism are Incompatible. Suppose that God creates ex nihilo a bronze statue of a

On the Prospects of Confined and Catholic Physicalism. Andreas Hüttemann

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 4 : I M M A T E R I A L I S M, D U A L I S M, & T H E M I N D - B O D Y P R O B L E M

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Dualism: What s at stake?

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

Against the Vagueness Argument TUOMAS E. TAHKO ABSTRACT

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

APA PANEL TALK ON ORGANISMS, PERSONS AND BIOETHICS

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

1. The narrow criterion Derek Parfit endorses a view of personal identity over time that he puts like this:

Aquinas 5 Proofs for God exists

QUESTION 47. The Diversity among Things in General

Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, Pp $90.00 (cloth); $28.99

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Higher-Order Approaches to Consciousness and the Regress Problem

SWINBURNE ON SUBSTANCES, PROPERTIES, AND STRUCTURES

THE PROBLEM OF PERSONAL IDENTITY

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Creation & necessity

Fictional Exemplars. 1 Practical benefits 1 of fictional exemplars

STILL NO REDUNDANT PROPERTIES: REPLY TO WIELENBERG

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

SWINBURNE ON SUBSTANCE DUALISM

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

Panpsychism and the Combination Problem. Hyungrae Noh. A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts

Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM. Section III: How do I know? Reading III.

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Am I free? Free will vs. determinism

The Question of Metaphysics

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

Philosophy 1100 Introduction to Ethics. Lecture 3 Survival of Death?

Logical behaviourism

Overcoming Cartesian Intuitions: A Defense of Type-Physicalism

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

Ethics Handout 19 Bernard Williams, The Idea of Equality. A normative conclusion: Therefore we should treat men as equals.

1/9. Leibniz on Descartes Principles

Does Personhood Begin at Conception?

Prentice Hall Biology 2004 (Miller/Levine) Correlated to: Idaho Department of Education, Course of Study, Biology (Grades 9-12)

A Moorean Argument for the Full Moral Status of those with Profound Intellectual Disability. Introduction

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

Transcription:

Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXV, No. 2, September 2002 Reflections on the Ontological Status of Persons GARY S. ROSENKRANTZ University of North Carolina at Greensboro Lynne Rudder Baker s The Ontological Status of Persons is a sophisticated attempt to answer the difficult, perennial philosophical question, What is the relationship of human beings to the natural world? According to Baker s double-stranded answer, our having reflective consciousness implies that we are not identical with our bodies, yet we are physical beings who are united with our bodies in a strong metaphysical sense. This answer combines dualistic and materialistic elements in an extremely interesting and novel way. Baker calls the view that we are essentially animals Animalism. The animalist maintains that each of us is identical with a human animal. Baker argues that if Animalism is correct, then we have ontological significance in virtue of our being human animals or organisms, but not in virtue of our being persons. Baker opposes Animalism with the Constitution View. This view implies that we are essentially persons, but only accidentally animals. A further implication is that none of us is identical with a human animal; rather each of us is constituted by a human animal. According to the Constitution View, we have ontological significance in virtue of being persons, but not in virtue of being animals. On the plus side, Baker s metaphysical theory that some physical objects constitute others accommodates our intuitive or folk-ontological beliefs about the existence and persistence conditions of statues and statue-shaped pieces of bronze, credit cards and credit card-shaped pieces of plastic, and so on. On the minus side, as Baker acknowledges, there is a worry that this metaphysical theory multiplies physical objects unnecessarily. According to Baker s Constitution View, person is a primary-kind. Such a kind, she says, need not be a kind of a broader kind such as animal. I m not sure exactly what Baker means by this. In particular, I wonder if she doubts Chisholm s view that, necessarily, a person is a kind of substance. Baker defends the view that there are primary-kind properties that m essential to one thing and accidental to another. Baker s view is illustrated by SYMPOSIUM 389

her claim that personhood is essential to persons, yet accidental to human animals. I do not accept this view. A primary-kind is what a thing most fundamentally is. How, then, can a thing have a primary-kind property accidentally? The answer seems to be that in such a case the thing has the primary-kind property only derivatively. But something has a primary-kind property, F-ness, derivatively, only if the primary-kind property of a nonderivative F, i.e., the property that determines what a nonderivative F mostfundamentally is, is nonderivutive F-ness (rather than F-ness). After all, such a determination relation is an entailment relation; yet on Baker s assumptions, a nonderivative F is most fundamentally a nonderivative F, and having F-ness does not entail being a nonderivative F. It follows that nonderivutive F-ness cannot be had accidentally. Thus, a primary-kind property cannot be had accidentally or derivatively. This, I believe, amounts to a reductio ad absurdurn of the view that a primary-kind property can be had accidentally or derivatively. Baker argues that person is a primary-kind on the grounds that reflective consciousness is a salient property of persons, that this property is very unlike every other property in nature, and that what a thing most fundamentally is, is a matter of what is distinctive about it. According to Baker, when reflective consciousness arose, it was sufficiently different from every other property in the natural world that it ushered in a new kind of being. I shall critically assess this argument in what follows. Baker s claim that reflective consciousness is very unlike every other property in the natural world may be appealing. Yet, there are good reasons to be hesitant about accepting this claim. For one thing, two very dissimilar forms may be connected by a graduated series of forms such that each form is similar to its neighbors in the series. According to evolutionary biology, of course, there are series of biological forms of this sort. There also appear to be such series connecting biological and psychological forms. For instance, even an ameba has a salient biological quality which to some extent resembles a person s reflective consciousness, namely, a tendency to respond to external stimuli so as to maintain itself, and this biological quality can be augmented through the gradual addition of the following psychological or proto-psychological qualities, in this order: first, intelligent behavior of an instinctive nature, second, learned behavior, third, transfer of acquired information between members of the same species, fourth, consciousness, fifth, emotions, moods, and personality traits, sixth, communication of beliefs or desires between members of the same species, seventh, language-use, and eighth, reflective consciousness. (Note that there may be significant stages other than the ones I ve mentioned, and that within each significant stage, various further sub-stages or degrees of development can be distinguished.) To the extent that gradations of mentality are found in nature, the justification 390 GARY R. ROSENKRANTZ

for Baker s premise that reflective consciousness is very unlike every other property in the natural world is weakened. Although Baker does not deny that gradations of mentality are found in nature, I worry that she underestimates the extent of these gradations. Moreover, the dissimilarity between conscious living things which are non-reflective, e.g., dogs, and living things which are non-conscious, e.g., amebas, appears to be at least as great as that between conscious living things which are reflective, e.g., humans, and conscious living things which are not. Thus, consciousness seems to be no less distinctive to the beings that enjoy it than rejective consciousness. (Of course, Descartes s notion that all non-human animals are nonconscious beings is implausible in the light of the total physiological and behavioral evidence available.) So, on Baker s principles, it appears to follow that conscious being (or more precisely, being with an appropriate capacity for consciousness) is a primary-kind, and that a living organism may constitute such a conscious being. In that case, it appears that a human person is co-located not only with a diverse human organism, but also with a conscious human that is diverse from both the human organism and the human person. An account that posits three such things in the same place at the same time is neither intuitive nor parsimonious. (Note that such a trinitarian account of human existence bears some resemblance to Aquinas s doctrine of the vegetative, sensitive, and rational souls of a human organism.) In the light of the foregoing considerations, I do not find Baker s argument that person is a primary-kind persuasive as it stands. Baker suggests that animalists would be inclined to hold that human organism is a primary-kind property. But many contemporary philosophers of biology reject the notion that biological species are natural kinds, along with the related notion that biological species properties are essences. For example, Elliot Sober has written as follows. If species have essences, it is surprising that evolutionary biology has not only failed to find them but shown scant interest in doing so... Two organisms are in the same species in virtue of their genealogical relatedness, not in virtue of their similarity; they are kin, but do not thereby comprise a natural kind. Even if two organisms are in the same species in virtue of their similarity, it can be argued that for any species, S, there could be a transitional organism, 0, such that 0 marginally belongs to S, 0 does not belong to S derivatively, and 0 possibly does not belong to S due to the occurrence of a mutation. (What I have in mind is the possibility of a genetic mutation occurring when 0 is generared, so that 0 would be a mutant and not in S.) But on Baker s view, whatever is nonderivatively of a primary-kind is essentially of that primary-kind. So, This quotation is from Sober s entry on natural kinds in A Companion to Metaphysics, ed. Jaegwon Kim and Ernest Sosa (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1995). p. 346. SYMPOSIUM 391

arguably, no species is a primary-kind. For parallel reasons, it is not clear that every member of a higher-order taxon such as animal or plant essentially belongs to it. Baker acknowledges that there are controversies in biology about individuating species. Still, the foregoing doubts about whether biological species are primary-kinds undermine Baker s basic assumption that every being has a primary-kind. (But these doubts do not undermine the apparently plausible idea that there are nonmurginal or paradigm members of higher-order taxa that essentially belong to them.) Even if biological species are not primary-kinds, an animalist can plausibly argue that carbon-based living organisms, e.g., living human animals, have persistence conditions. In particular, a carbon-based living organism, 0, possibly undergoes only a limited range of changes in structural or compositional properties, PI, Pz, P3,.. P,, reflecting lawfully interrelated requirements such as (i) 0 s having a certain compositional nature, one which apparently includes liquid water, proteins, and self-replicable organic macromolecules, (ii) 0 s having a narrowly defined capacity for certain basic biological activities, e.g., metabolic ones, (iii) 0 s having a master-part, i.e., a vital proper part which regulates or controls the biological activities of 0 s parts, and (iv) 0 s having a hereditary-type which is molecularly e n d in its master-part right from the start. So, arguably, the persistence conditions of a carbonbased organism are more a matter of its original genotype or hereditary-type than its species. Even if a marginally human living animal, H, were accidentally human, H s having such persistence conditions would ensure that H could not become an oak tree, an ameba, a tiger, or a thing composed of aluminum, silicon, plastic, and gold. Baker claims that Animalism is incompatible with Chisholm s requirement that a person is necessarily such that it is physically possible that it consciously thinks. Baker assumes that in some possible world there is a living human animal, H, which never develops a cerebral cortex because Hs mother was exposed to a toxic chemical. Baker argues that in such a possible world H consciously thinks would be physically impossible. I do not find this argument persuasive. By physically possible, Chisholm means consistent with the laws of nature. Since the laws of nature are physically necessary, something s being physically possible cannot hinge upon anything that is physically contingent, i.e., such that both it and its negation are consistent with the laws of nature. Of course, it is physically possible that Hs mother undergoes a toxic exposure of the sort that Baker envisions, in which case H would never develop the ability to consciously think. But it is also physically possible that Hs mother does not undergo such a toxic exposure, with the result that H eventually develops conscious thought. Thus, whether H is ever able to consciously think hinges upon something that is physically contingent, i.e., Hs mother being exposed to a toxin of the sort in question. 392 GARY R. ROSENKRANTZ

It follows that even if H were never to develop a cerebral cortex for the reasons that Baker envisions, H consciously thinks would not be physically impossible. (Notice that this seems to be consistent with H s consciously thinking without a cerebral cortex being physically impossible.) I conclude that Animalism is compatible with the aforementioned Chisholmian requirement; Baker is wrong to suppose otherwise. Baker defends her Constitution View of human persons by arguing that a thing s nature is more a matter of what it can do than what it is made of. In contrast, Joshua Hoffman and I have def& a substance ontology that implies that a physical thing s essential nature is a nurural kind, and hence more a matter of what it is made of (and of how its parts are united) than of what it can do: This substance ontology does not assume that there are physical objects that are constituted by other cdocated physical objects. Person does not qualify as a natural substance-kind because some possible persons are not similar in make-up to others, as illustrated by the possibilities of a reflective thinker who is carbon-based, a reflective thinker who is physical but not carbon-based, and an altogether nonphysical reflective thinker. The animalist claim that human personhood is a phase, and hence an accident, of certain carbon-based living organisms fits comfortably within our ontology of natural substance-kinds; but the Constitution View does not. Joshua Hoffman and Gary S. Rosenluantz, Substance: Its Nature and Existence (London: Routledge, 1997). SYMPOSIUM 393