Dumitrescu Bogdan Andrei - The incompatibility of analytic statements with Quine s universal revisability

Similar documents
Conceptual Analysis meets Two Dogmas of Empiricism David Chalmers (RSSS, ANU) Handout for Australasian Association of Philosophy, July 4, 2006

Constructing the World, Lecture 4 Revisability and Conceptual Change: Carnap vs. Quine David Chalmers

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

Defending A Dogma: Between Grice, Strawson and Quine

On Quine, Grice and Strawson, and the Analytic-Synthetic Distinction. by Christian Green

Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism. The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which asserts that the meaning of a

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #10]

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

ETHOS: Felsefe ve Toplumsal Bilimlerde Diyaloglar // Sayı: 4 (1) Ocak 2011

WILLARD VAN ORMAN QUINE

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Quine on Holism and Underdetermination

Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory

37. The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction

ON QUINE, ANALYTICITY, AND MEANING Wylie Breckenridge

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

Ever since W. V. O. Quine wrote his famous Two Dogmas of

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Putnam on Methods of Inquiry

Quine on the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic?

Lecture 1 The Concept of Inductive Probability

The Philosophy of Language. Quine versus Meaning

Philosophical Review.

DAVIDSON AND CONCEPTUAL SCHEMES PAUL BROADBENT. A thesis submitted to The University of Birmingham for the degree of MASTER OF PHILOSOPHY

Wolfgang Spohn Fachbereich Philosophie Universität Konstanz D Konstanz

Indeterminacy, A Priority, and Analyticity in the Quinean Critique

A Defence of Kantian Synthetic-Analytic Distinction

Varieties of Apriority

The Coherence of Kant s Synthetic A Priori

IT is frequently taken for granted, both by people discussing logical

Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori

Carnap s notion of analyticity and the two wings of analytic philosophy. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Constructing the World

Nature and its Classification

PHILOSOPHY EPISTEMOLOGY ESSAY TOPICS AND INSTRUCTIONS

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

CHAPTER IV NON-EMPIRICAL CRITIQUE OF A PRIORI AND A POSTERIORI

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

CRITIQUE OF THE ANALYTIC/SYNTHETIC DISTINCTION. by Marty Fields

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Time travel and the open future

Philosophy of Logic and Language (108) Comprehensive Reading List Robert L. Frazier 24/10/2009

APRIORISM IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

Alternative Conceptual Schemes and a Non-Kantian Scheme-Content Dualism

Could i conceive being a brain in a vat? John D. Collier a a

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

145 Philosophy of Science

Although Quine is widely known as an influential critic of logical positivism, there is now a

THE IDEA OF A PRIORI REVISITED* SANJIT CHAKRABORTY

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Wittgenstein s Logical Atomism. Seminar 8 PHIL2120 Topics in Analytic Philosophy 16 November 2012

David Lewis (1941 ) Introduction

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll

Classical Theory of Concepts


Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism

Junior Research Fellow and Lecturer in Philosophy Worcester College, University of Oxford Walton Street Oxford OX1 2HB Great Britain

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Is There a Priori Knowledge?

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

One Notion of Religious Truth? Hilary Putnam s Conceptual Truth and the Justification of Religious Propositions

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

* I am indebted to Jay Atlas and Robert Schwartz for their helpful criticisms

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Introduction. Bernard Williams

Free will and the necessity of the past

The Legacy of 'Two Dogmas'

Two Dogmas of Analytical Philosophy

Quine and the Vienna Circle

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

A Distinction between Science and Philosophy

Emotivism. Meta-ethical approaches

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

Transcription:

Dumitrescu Bogdan Andrei - The incompatibility of analytic statements with Quine s universal revisability Abstract: This very brief essay is concerned with Grice and Strawson s article In Defense of a Dogma which was a response to Quine s influential paper Two Dogmas of Empiricism. The two authors argue that the analytic/synthetic distinction is compatible with Quine s revisability thesis. I will attempt to criticize their argument for the compatibility between the two doctrines and show that they are indeed incompatible as Quine argued. 1. Introduction One can argue that Quine s most important idea expounded in Two Dogmas of Empiricism (1951) is, what I shall call, the revisability thesis. It is the idea that any statement can be revised if we make sufficient changes in our system of beliefs or, rather, if we make drastic enough changes in our body of knowledge (which includes all the established sciences). We can give up any statement or belief in the face of contradictory experiences. However, Quine maintains that the revisability thesis is incompatible with the analytic/synthetic distinction. Any analytic statement being true by definition is not consistent with his holistic view of knowledge. But the authors Grice and Strawson disagree with this contention. In their article, In Defense of a Dogma (1956), they maintain that Quine s doctrine that no statement is unrevisable is not incompatible, but quite consistent with the analytic/synthetic distinction. They argue that if we can make sense of the idea that the same form of words (having a certain meaning) can be true at one time and at another time (having a different meaning) they can be false, then we can understand what conceptual revision means. If this kind of conceptual revision is intelligible, then even analytic statements can be revised and thus, Quine s views can be compatible with the analytic/synthetic distinction. 1

My aim in this short essay is to analyze and criticize this argument from Grice and Strawson with the help of some of the works of Charles Pigden (1987) and Hilary Putnam (1985). However, I do not intend to defend Quine s view or argue against the existence of analytic statements. My goal is to show that Grice and Strawson s argument for the compatibility between Quine s views and the analytic/synthetic distinction is not satisfactory. 2. The revisability of analytic statements The final part of Quine s article is what concerns Grice and Strawson. It is, of course, the section where he expounds his holistic view of knowledge, an empiricist theory without the use of the analytic/synthetic distinction and reductionism. Total science, as he calls it, is like a field whose center is comprised of pure mathematics and logic. From then on, the empirical sciences comprise the rest of the field and, finally, at the periphery lay the statements of experience. Changes in the interior of the field are thus caused by the conflicts with the observation statements at the periphery. Having established this, he states: Furthermore it becomes folly to seek a boundary between synthetic statements, which hold contingently on experience, and analytic statements which hold come what may. [...] Conversely, by the same token, no statement is immune to revision. Revision even of the logical law of the excluded middle has been proposed as a means of simplifying quantum mechanics [...] (Quine 1951, pp.460) From this, one can argue that a statement such as A bachelor is an unmarried man. is not in fact an analytic statement, but a synthetic one. A sufficient number of experiences, such as the changing of the meaning of bachelor in dictionaries could change the truth value of the above statement. If I were to experience such a change of meaning occurring in a dictionary, then I could say that I have acquired new knowledge based on experience alone. But Grice and Strawson say that analyticity is quite compatible with there being no statement immune to revision. If the meaning of bachelor would be changed to mean overweight man instead of unmarried man, then the statement A bachelor is an overweight man. would become an analytic statement. They state: Acceptance of this doctrine (revisability of all statements) is quite consistent with adherence to the distinction between analytic and synthetic statements. [...] Any form of 2

words at one time held to express something true may, no doubt, at another time, come to be held to express something false. [...] And if we can make sense of this idea, then we can perfectly well preserve the distinction between the analytic and the synthetic, while conceding to Quine the revisability-in-principle of everything we say. (Grice, Strawson 1956, pp. 471) Now, of course, all of this depends on how we define analyticity. I shall make use of the idea that an analytic statement is a statement that is true by definition or true in virtue of the meanings of its terms. In the following section, I will attempt to criticize the argument given by Grice and Strawson and refer to the works of Charles Pigden and Hilary Putnam. 3. Against Grice and Strawson 3.1. The compatibility Why can t analytic statements be true at one time and false at another? After all, if we understand analyticity as being true by definition, then the truth value of an analytic statement must depend solely on the definition in use. But definitions may change and what was true at one time will be false at another. If we don t deny this, then why can t we accept that the revisability-in-principle thesis is compatible with analytic statements? Charles Pigden in Two Dogmatists (1987) argues that if we accept this compatibility then we would obtain a very different version of revisability than Quine advocated for. He states the following: To maintain the distinction in the face of universal revisability, it is necessary to maintain (a) that there is a difference between rejecting a proposition as false and dropping the concepts involved; (b) that whenever a supposed analyticity is rejected, this is because it has either metamorphosed into a synthetic falsehood or because we have ceased to use the concepts in question (it is not so much false as unspoken) and (c) that if the concepts are revived (perhaps embodied in different words) the statement (or its equivalent) would again be true. But this is to deny revisability in Quine s sense. (Pigden 1987, pp.189) Pigden goes on to say that there are statements which, given their meanings, can only be true, even if nobody actually utters them. The revisability thesis that Grice and Strawson 3

maintain would be uncontroversial and distinct from the radical version that Quine was advocating. However, I find their contentions to be problematic. I shall take the three hypotheses laid out by Pigden as true and attempt to show the inconveniences they produce together. Let s take the example of the analytic statement A bachelor is an unmarried man. We ll suppose two cases following the (a) hypothesis: A case where we reject the statement as being false and a case where we drop the concept of bachelor. In my view, both cases should be results of certain experiences. We might reject the statement as false when the meaning of the term bachelor is changed in the dictionaries. As for the second case, we might drop the concept if, over generations, marriages would disappear out of tradition so as to make the use of bachelor obsolete. Hypothesis (b) offers two reasons for the rejection of an analytic statement: if the statement has turned into a false synthetic statement or if we have stopped using the concepts. As Pigden points out, if we have stopped using the concept of bachelor due to the disappearance of marriages, let s say, then the statement A bachelor is an unmarried man. doesn t become false, it becomes rather useless and it would not make sense to integrate it into our system of beliefs. But nonetheless, it does not cease to be an analytic statement. What I find peculiar is the first case: the one in which the statement has metamorphosed into a false synthetic statement. Grice and Strawson would say that after a new meaning is established to the term bachelor, the statement A bachelor is an unmarried man. would cease to be analytic and turn into a false synthetic statement. I suppose then, if the meaning of bachelor would be overweight man, the statement A bachelor is an overweight man. would become analytic. Here, in my opinion, is where Grice and Strawson are mistaken. Usually, when we think of analytic statements we believe that no knowledge can be produced by them. If someone were to tell me that all matter is extended I would not be compelled to say that I have learned something new. I d know by the very definition of matter that it is extended in space. I d know it is true in virtue of the meaning of the term. The term would be reasserting its own meaning. And having this in mind, we can say that a characteristic of analytic 4

statements (as Kant once said) is that they do not produce new knowledge. New knowledge can be produced by synthetic statements. Thus, if I were walking down a street perfectly used to the idea that the meaning of bachelor is unmarried man and somebody would come up to me to inform me that the meaning of bachelor had changed to overweight man, then I d acquire new knowledge. The statement A bachelor is an overweight man. would appear to me to be a true synthetic statement. And if this was so, then the statement A bachelor is an unmarried man. would not cease to be an analytic statement, because, arguably, it was never one to begin with if we accept that these changes in meanings can provide us with new knowledge. Grice and Strawson s argument was that if we could make sense of the idea that a statement taken with a certain meaning can be true at one time and the same statement with a different meaning at another time can be false, then we can make sense of the idea of conceptual revision. And then, if we make sense of conceptual revision we can reconcile Quine s view with the analytic/synthetic distinction. I agree that we can understand conceptual revision and I believe that it is a common occurrence. However, this conceptual revision betrays the fact that the statements that we commonly think of as analytic are in fact, synthetic, due to the realization that a revised analytic statement produces new knowledge. Therefore, we cannot maintain the analytic/synthetic distinction along with universal revisability using Grice and Strawson s hypotheses, because the process of revising analytic statements turns them into synthetic ones, in light of the fact that revised analytic statements produce new knowledge. Lastly, concerning hypothesis (c), I maintain that (in the case of the discontinuation of marriages) if the concept of bachelor would be revived, then the statement A bachelor is an unmarried man. would indeed still be true. But as I said above, it would have never become false in the first place. The terms would have only been unused, unspoken as Pigden suggested. 3.2 Moderate revisability As a closing remark, I will refer to a position maintained by Hilary Putnam that Pigden brought into discussion. A supporter of Grice and Strawson could argue that universal 5

revisability in Quine s sense is false to begin with. Putnam argued in his book Realism and Reason (1983) that we cannot accept an extreme revisability thesis, because there is one statement that is unrevisable: Not every proposition is both true and false. He states: If every statement is such that under some circumstances it might be rational to revise it, then under some circumstances it might be rational to accept that every statement is both true and false. Is this the case? Well, it certainly doesn t seem to be the case. (Putnam 1983, pp. 101) But as Pigden remarks, this does not help Grice and Strawson. Furthermore, their claim was that Quine s views could be reconciled with the analytic/synthetic distinction and not necessarily other weaker forms of revisability. While Grice and Strawson refer mostly to meanings of terms, Putnam seems to be concerned more with aprioricity and necessity than with analyticity. 4. Conclusion In this essay I attempted to criticize Grice and Strawson s argument for the compatibility of Quine s universal revisability thesis and the analytic/synthetic distinction. My intention was not to defend Quine s view or maintain the non-existence of analytic statements, only to show that Grice and Strawson s argument was unsatisfactory. Their argument went as follows: We can accept that no statement is in principle immune from revision and the analytic/synthetic distinction if we can make sense of the idea of conceptual revision. Conceptual revision meant that one form of words with a certain meaning can be true at one time and the same form of words with a different meaning can be false at another time. I argued that this conceptual revision is flawed, because, contrary to what Grice and Strawson believe, it turns analytic statements into synthetic statements. If the meaning of bachelor is changed from unmarried man to overweight man, then upon an utterance of the statement A bachelor is an overweight man. one can argue that this statement produces new knowledge much like any synthetic statement does. Therefore, Grice and Strawson have only succeeded in blurring the lines between analytic and synthetic statements much like Quine intended to in the first place. 6

References Quine, W. V. (1951) Two Dogmas of Empiricism. Cornell University. Philosophical Review 60, pp. 450-462 Grice H. P. And Strawson P. F. (1956) In Defense of a Dogma. Cornell University. Philosophical Review 65, pp. 463-472 Pigden, Charles (1987) Two Dogmatists. Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, 30:1-2, pp. 173-193 Putnam, Hilary (1983) Realism and Reason. Cambridge University Press. Philosophical Papers, Volume 3 7