Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Similar documents
Introduction to Philosophy. Spring 2017

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

The Concept of Testimony

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

G.E. Moore A Refutation of Skepticism

The Rejection of Skepticism

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Ayer on the argument from illusion

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis

Skepticism and Internalism

What God Could Have Made

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

The free will defense

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Introduction: Paradigms, Theism, and the Parity Thesis

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

In this paper I will critically discuss a theory known as conventionalism

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Introduction to Philosophy

what makes reasons sufficient?

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Finite Reasons without Foundations

INTRODUCTION. This week: Moore's response, Nozick's response, Reliablism's response, Externalism v. Internalism.

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Some Templates for Beginners: Template Option 1 I am analyzing A in order to argue B. An important element of B is C. C is significant because.

Common Sense: A Contemporary Defense By Noah Lemos Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. xvi

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011.

Sentence Starters from They Say, I Say

DANCY ON ACTING FOR THE RIGHT REASON

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

How and How Not to Take on Brueckner s Sceptic. Christoph Kelp Institute of Philosophy, KU Leuven

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

MOORE, THE SKEPTIC, AND THE PHILOSOPHICAL CONTEXT * Wai-hung Wong

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

Introducing Our New Faculty

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Behavior and Other Minds: A Response to Functionalists

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

Higher-Order Epistemic Attitudes and Intellectual Humility. Allan Hazlett. Forthcoming in Episteme

Appendix: The Logic Behind the Inferential Test

By submitting this essay, I attest that it is my own work, completed in accordance with University regulations. Minh Alexander Nguyen

Reid Against Skepticism

Chapter 1. What is Philosophy? Thinking Philosophically About Life

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

5 A Modal Version of the

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

DEFENDING KLEIN ON CLOSURE AND SKEPTICISM

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological

PLANTINGA ON THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. Hugh LAFoLLETTE East Tennessee State University

The Skeptic and the Dogmatist

On A New Cosmological Argument

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Klein on the Unity of Cartesian and Contemporary Skepticism

Coordination Problems

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

Huemer s Clarkeanism

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Berkeley, Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous focus on p. 86 (chapter 9) to the end (p. 93).

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

Templates for Research Paper

Warrant, Proper Function, and the Great Pumpkin Objection

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

A Priori Bootstrapping

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

Are There Moral Facts

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Moore s paradoxes, Evans s principle and self-knowledge

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University

Crawford L. Elder, Familiar Objects and Their Shadows, Cambridge University Press, 2011, 222pp., $85.00 (hardback), ISBN

Reality. Abstract. Keywords: reality, meaning, realism, transcendence, context

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

Transcription:

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore I argue that Moore s famous response to the skeptic should be accepted even by the skeptic. My paper has three main stages. First, I will briefly outline G. E. Moore s proof for the existence of the external world in response to the skeptic. Moore s argument will serve to illustrate three of the methodological elements essential to Moore s response the Moorean Shift, Moorean Facts, and common sense which I will explore in the second section. With a clearer understanding of these methodological elements in hand, I argue that Moore s use of them ensures that his response to the skeptic is in no way dialectically inappropriate, and moreover gives him the dialectical upper hand. I. Moorean Methodology In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows: (1) If there is one hand here, then there is an external world. (2) Here is a hand, and here is another (ostensibly gesture toward one s own hands). (3) Therefore, there is an external world. The success of this argument, according to Moore, depends crucially on whether we can know and not merely believe that the major premise premise (2) is true. 1 Although Moore concedes that we cannot prove that we can know the world exists, Moore insists that we can know things that one cannot prove. And so Moore takes the argument to prove the existence of an external world, not that he has knowledge of the existence of an external world. That is not to say, however, that Moore lacks knowledge that there is an external world. 1. The Moorean Shift A fuller treatment of Moore s response to the reveals a number of interesting methodological elements at work, the primary one being what has come to be called The G. E. Moore Shift, or the Moorean Shift. A Moorean Shift occurs when one counters an argument by denying its conclusion and shifting its form to a modus tollens from a modus ponens (or vice versa). Moore s example is as good as any other. Confronted with skeptical arguments of the form 1 I.e., whether the argument constitutes a proof of its conclusion depends on its meeting this condition. There is no need here to consider whether the argument so-outlined meets the other conditions for a proof that Moore considers (i.e., that the argument s main premise has to be different from the conclusion, and that the premise has to follow logically from the conclusion), because it does. But I suppose this, too, could always be disputed. 1

(4) If S doesn t know that S is not dreaming, S does not know there is an external world. (5) S does not know that S is not dreaming. (6) Therefore, S does not know there is an external world. (4, 5 MP) Moore responds by pointing out that belief in the existence of an external world (e.g., Moore s premise here is a hand, and here is another ) is more obviously true, or more reasonable to believe, than the conclusion of the skeptic s argument. 2 Thus, Moore argues instead that (4) If S doesn t know that S is not dreaming, S does not know there is an external world. (5*) S knows there is an external world. (6*) Therefore, S knows that S is not dreaming. (4, 5* MT) And now with the two arguments in hand (pun intended), Moore thinks that the only way of deciding between my opponents argument and mine, as to which is better, is by deciding which premise is known to be true. 3 For reasons I mention below, many think Moore s response to the skeptic is problematic; they say it is in some way dialectically inappropriate or fallacious. But even supposing it is, that is not to say the Moorean shift is no good as a general argumentative strategy. Perhaps a deeper appreciation of the Moorean Shift can be gained by illustrating how it can function in a philosophical context other than in response to the skeptic: Zeno s paradoxes. Where Zeno would argue 4 via modus ponens that (7) If it is impossible to cross an infinitely long distance, then motion is impossible. (8) It is impossible to cross an infinitely long distance. (9) Therefore, motion is possible. (7, 8 MP) In response to Zeno, one might shift the argument into a modus tollens as follows: (7) If it is impossible to cross an infinitely long distance, then motion is impossible. (8*) Motion is possible. (9*) Therefore, it is not impossible to cross an infinitely long distance. (7, 8* MT) 2 G. E. Moore, Philosophical Papers (George Allen & Unwin, 1956), p. 226. 3 ibid., 121-122. 4 My formulation of Zeno s argument is influenced by R. M. Sainsbury, Paradoxes (New York: Cambridge University Press, 3 rd ed. 2009), p.11. In what modal context (logical, metaphysical, physical, etc.) the argument is intended to function is an open question here. 2

and insist that because we have more reason to believe (8*) than (8), Zeno s argument fails (perhaps this is the origin of the phrase one s modus ponens is another s modus tollens?). Thus, a Moorean shift provides a satisfying solution, at least to the philosopher with Moorean sympathies, to philosophical arguments for extraordinarily radical or revisionary conclusions, such as the ones reached by the skeptic and by Zeno. 5 2. Moorean Facts The Moorean Shift highlights other important epistemological notions at work in Moore s thought. One such notion is that of a Moorean Fact. Indeed, The cogency of the Moorean Shift crucially depends on the notion of a Moorean Fact. In the Moorean Shift, Moore shifts the epistemological burden on the skeptic by asserting that (5*) is more reasonable to believe than (5), and so concludes with (6*). Moore s confidence that (5*) is more reasonable to believe than (5) is precisely what is supposed to make the shift cogent. He writes: [W]e may safely challenge any philosopher to bring forward any argument in favor of either of the proposition that we do not know [some common sense belief to be true], of the proposition that it is not true, which does not rest upon some premise which is, beyond comparison, less certain than is the proposition which it is designed to attack. 6 So we might say that, in the most general terms, a Moorean Fact is a claim about which of two beliefs (that serve as major premises in arguments leading to contradictory conclusions) is more reasonable to believe. The Moorean Fact in play in the above arguments therefore is: (10) It is more reasonable to believe (5*) than (5). Obviously there is a bit of epistemic relativity inherent in the concept of a Moorean Fact, so defined. There may be and predictably will usually be disagreement about which premise is more reasonable to believe, depending on which argument one endorses. Simply pulling a Moorean Shift and labeling the new key premise more reasonable to believe than the original argument s key premise doesn t exactly advance the discussion. For example, suppose you re a die-hard scientific realist who sees the Minkowskian model of spacetime geometry as not only the best interpretation of the Special Theory of Relativity, but is the sober truth about the structure of reality itself. You are caught in the throws of a passionate argument with your 5 Though, arguably, the skeptic s argument is perhaps the most radical; for if it is true, then not even the conclusions of other, radically unintuitive arguments such as Zeno s argument can be known. I will return to this important difference below (section III). 6 G. E. Moore, Philosophical Papers, pp. 227-228. 3

colleague, a Newton-loving proponent of Neo-Lorentzian Relativity. Your colleague presents you with the following argument: (11) If the Minkowskian interpretation of STR is correct, then there are no relations of absolute simultaneity. (12) There are relations of absolute simultaneity. (13) Therefore, the Minkowskian interpretation of STR is not correct (11, 12 MT) Naturally enough, you will see things differently. Accordingly, you will pull a Moorean Shift on your colleague and insist that (12*) The Minkowskian interpretation of STR is correct. and therefore conclude with your good friend modus ponens that (13*) Therefore, there are no relations of absolute simultaneity. (11, 12* MP) Now, it will do no good to simply assert that the following is a Moorean Fact (14) It is more reasonable to believe (12*) than (12). for which premise (12) or (12*) is more reasonable to believe is precisely what s at issue. In other words, nothing would prevent your colleague from either denying (14), or asserting what he takes to be a Moorean Fact of his own: (15) It is more reasonable to believe (12) than (12*). In such a case, Moore s methodology doesn t seem too helpful. And if the cogency of the Moorean Shift depends on Moorean Facts, one might wonder how effective the Moorean Shift is, too. All that is needed to dispel these worries, however, is a little more clarity on what counts as a Moorean Fact. 3. Common Sense The problem above is that the general characterization of Moorean Facts is too general. Not just anything can count as a Moorean Fact. This is where Moore s commitment to common sense comes in. In particular, when a major premise of one of the competing arguments is an item of common sense, one is in a position to state a Moorean Fact. That s why the Moorean Shift seems to be a cogent move in response to, say, Zeno s paradoxes, but not in response to your Neo- Lorentzian colleague: that there is motion is an item of common sense, whereas that the 4

Minkowskian interpretation of STR is correct is not. But this doesn t entirely solve the problem. What exactly is common sense, anyway? And why do some beliefs count as common sense and others not? This is a hard question, and one to which most philosophers even sympathetic to Moore are not prepared to give a definitive answer. 7 But rather than think of common sense beliefs as meeting a rigid set of necessary and sufficient conditions, maybe it s better to think of a continuum of beliefs, on the one end being commonsensical beliefs and on the other end, radical, revisionary beliefs. Examples of beliefs falling on the commonsense side would be beliefs like Here is a hand, and here is another or There is an external world, or motion is possible. In A Defense of Common Sense, Moore lists a host of other beliefs he considers to be items of common sense, among which are: There exists at present a living human body, which is my [Moore s] body. This body [i.e., Moore s body] was born at a certain time in the past, and has existed continuously ever since, though not without undergoing changes;......at every moment since it was born, there have also existed many other things, having shape and size in three dimensions,... from which it has been at various distances...; also there have... existed some other things of this kind with which it was in contact......there have, at every moment since its birth, been large numbers of other living human bodies... the earth... existed also for many years before my body was born... 8 Examples of beliefs on the other end of the continuum might include beliefs like motion is impossible, or all that exists are ideas, or there are no chairs. Of course, some beliefs may be closer to the far ends of the continuum than others. But the point is that the greater the disparity between any two beliefs on the continuum, the stronger the Moorean Fact will be, and hence the more cogent the Moorean Shift. To illustrate: Common Sense Neutral Radically Revisionary p q r s Where p, q, r, and s are beliefs, the strongest Moorean Facts will be ones like It is more reasonable to believe p than s, which might be represented by (10) above, whereas weak or ineffectual Moorean Facts (which are really pseudo-moorean Facts) will be ones like It is more 7 The most detailed analysis of what does and does not count as common sense that I am aware of is William Lycan, Moore Against the New Skeptics, Philosophical Studies 103 (2001), pp. 35-53. 8 Moore, Philosophical Papers, pp. 33-35. 5

reasonable to believe q than r, which might be represented by either (14) or (15) above. 9 The obvious downside to thinking of common sense this way is that there is a lot of subjectivity about where one will locate a particular belief on the continuum. 10 Nevertheless, a somewhat more clear understanding of a Moorean Fact though admittedly still pretty vague is this: a fact about which of two beliefs (that serve as major premises in arguments leading to contradictory conclusions), is closer to common sense than the other. III. Does the Skeptic Win? Plausibly, the Moorean Shift is most persuasive when you can assert a strong Moorean Fact; i.e., when the premise of your interlocutor s argument is radically revisionary and the premise of your shifted argument is a common sense belief. Thus, everything about Moore s methodology here is fundamentally epistemological in nature common sense beliefs are essential to Moorean Facts, Moorean Facts are essential to the Moorean Shift. This point helps highlight an important difference between the application of the Moorean Shift to the skeptic s argument and to arguments like Zeno s. The difference is that the skeptic s arguments are about the possibility of all knowledge, including any premise Moore thinks is known with certainty to be true. So one might say that the skeptic s argument is metaepistemological in nature. For this reason, many have cast doubt on Moore s response to the skeptic. They say that even if the premise in Moore s shifted argument is true, Moore s response begs the question against the skeptic, or is in some other way dialectically unacceptable. But this can t be said of a Moorean response to Zeno s argument, or some other such argument for a metaphysical, not meta-epistemological, conclusion. So we could say with some plausibility that Moore s strategy is more effective, at least prima facie, against the metaphysical revisionist like Zeno than the epistemological skeptic like Russell. But maybe this is only prima facie the case. Recall that the main premises in the skeptic s and Moore s arguments are, respectively (5) S does not know that S is not dreaming. (5*) S knows there is an external world. 9 For the sake of illustration we might say so. But actually I think the belief that there are relations of absolute simultaneity is solidly on the common sense side and the belief that the Minkowskian interpretation of STR is correct is solidly on the radically revisionary side. In fact, the Minkowskian geometry of spacetime might even be a paradigm radical belief. But to be fair, what s most important is not really a belief s status on the continuum by itself, but the belief s status on the continuum in relation to another. 10 This is admittedly an extremely simplistic way of illustrating the matter. But just because the illustration is simple doesn t mean its would necessarily fall apart during more complicated applications. 6

with the Moorean fact being (10) It is more reasonable to believe (5*) than (5). from which Moore concludes, contra the skeptic, that S knows that S is not dreaming. Those persuaded that Moore s response is dialectically impotent or inappropriate might ask what prevents the skeptic from countering (10) by asserting (16): (16) It is more reasonable to believe (5) than (5*). And the skeptic could assert (16). But the problem is that it, unlike (10), is plainly false; Moore at least has what appears to be swaths of evidence favoring (5*), namely, all appearances of an external world, the least of which being his two hands. Of course Moore can grant the skeptic that such appearances could be deceptive, which is all the skeptical scenarios warrant. And even the skeptic should agree that we at least seem to perceive an external world. But there is no such comparable evidence in favor of (5). It is true that one s evidence would be the same if (5) were true, but it s not like we re having experiences that lead us to believe (5) is true (if the apparent evidence didn t favor (5*), then there would be no point to the skeptic asking how do you know you re not being deceived? ). So the skeptic shouldn t have any problems admitting that (16) is false, unless he is prepared to deny that Moore even seems to be perceiving an external world. But maybe the skeptic can regroup and counter (10) in a different way. Even if the skeptic agrees that (16) is false, i.e., it is true that (16) It is not more reasonable to believe (5) than (5*). the skeptic will be quick to point out that from (16) it does not follow that (10) is true. Indeed, the skeptic can return the complement and say that it is precisely the skeptical scenarios that lead him to think (10) It is not more reasonable to believe (5*) than (5). By countering Moore s (10) with (10), the skeptic avoids having to defend a positive assertion like (16), so in that sense (10) is more modest. However, I don t think this move is any more promising. After all, (10) is not making a claim about what is reasonable to believe at all; it is denying a claim about what is reasonable to believe. And the skeptic denies that of (10) as well. 7

But now consider: if it s not more reasonable to believe (5*) than (5), as (10) says, and it s also not more reasonable to believe (5) than (5*), as (16) says, then the skeptic has just as much reason to believe (5*) as he does (5). But if our two alternatives are knowledge and no knowledge, one wonders why anyone would choose the latter over the former. Surely knowledge has intrinsic epistemic value, such that, all else being equal, it would be better to have than lack. 11 Even if the skeptic prefers no knowledge, he must at least acknowledge that Moore s proof works for him. For if two alternatives A and B are equally reasonable, and George chooses A over B for no other reason than sheer preference, then Bertrand, who for the same reason choses B over A, could hardly criticize George s choice (and vice versa). 11 For defense, see Jonathan Kvanvig, The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2003). 8