A Review of Donaldson and Dunfee s Ties That Bind: A Social Contracts Approach to Business Ethics

Similar documents
Philosophy Courses Fall 2016

2018 Philosophy of Management Conference Paper submission NORMATIVITY AND DESCRIPTION: BUSINESS ETHICS AS A MORAL SCIENCE

A Framework for Thinking Ethically

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

CHAPTER 5. CULTURAL RELATIVISM.

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

Worksheet for Preliminary Self-Review Under WCEA Catholic Identity Standards

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

Making Decisions on Behalf of Others: Who or What Do I Select as a Guide? A Dilemma: - My boss. - The shareholders. - Other stakeholders

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

PROFESSIONAL ETHICS IN SCIENCE AND ENGINEERING

In this set of essays spanning much of his career at Calvin College,

Section 1 of chapter 1 of The Moral Sense advances the thesis that we have a

How to Live a More Authentic Life in Both Markets and Morals

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

Care of the Soul: Service-Learning and the Value of the Humanities

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Other Recommended Books (on reserve at library):

Course Coordinator Dr Melvin Chen Course Code. CY0002 Course Title. Ethics Pre-requisites. NIL No of AUs 3 Contact Hours

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

NEW FRONTIERS ACHIEVING THE VISION OF DON BOSCO IN A NEW ERA. St. John Bosco High School

Argumentation and Positioning: Empirical insights and arguments for argumentation analysis

Journal Of Contemporary Trends In Business And Information Technology (JCTBIT) Vol.5, pp.1-6, December Existentialist s Model of Professionalism

Human Nature & Human Diversity: Sex, Love & Parenting; Morality, Religion & Race. Course Description

Guidelines on Global Awareness and Engagement from ATS Board of Directors

MINISTRY LEADERSHIP. Objectives for students. Master's Level. Ministry Leadership 1

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

To the familiar jibe that business ethics is an oxymoron

4 Liberty, Rationality, and Agency in Hobbes s Leviathan

Ethics Handout 19 Bernard Williams, The Idea of Equality. A normative conclusion: Therefore we should treat men as equals.

The Role of the Library in the Character Formation of the Christian College Student

Module 7: ethical behavior 1. Steps in this module: 2. Complete the case study Framework for Ethical Decision Making

Templeton Fellowships at the NDIAS

Policies and Procedures of the Evangelical Lutheran Church in America for Addressing Social Concerns

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

U.S. Bishops Revise Part Six of the Ethical and Religious Directives An Initial Analysis by CHA Ethicists 1

Feedback Constitutional Law 312 Applied Assignment 2017 Application B

Theology and Ethics: Reflections on the Revisions to Part Six of the ERDs

APPENDIX A NOTE ON JOHN PAUL II, VERITATIS SPLENDOR (1993) The Encyclical is primarily a theological document, addressed to the Pope's fellow Roman

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

Should We Assess the Basic Premises of an Argument for Truth or Acceptability?

24.03: Good Food 3 April Animal Liberation and the Moral Community

Virtue Ethics. A Basic Introductory Essay, by Dr. Garrett. Latest minor modification November 28, 2005

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition

Principles of a Regnum Christi School

CGSC 281/PHIL 181: Phil&Sci Human Nature Gendler/Yale University, Spring Reading Guide The Ring of Gyges: Morality and Hypocrisy

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Hume's Is/Ought Problem. Ruse and Wilson. Moral Philosophy as Applied Science. Naturalistic Fallacy

Master of Arts in Health Care Mission

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

JUDICIAL OPINION WRITING

GUIDELINES FOR ESTABLISHING AN INTERFAITH STUDIES PROGRAM ON A UNIVERSITY OR COLLEGE CAMPUS

404 Ethics January 2019 I. TOPICS II. METHODOLOGY

Ethics in a Historical View & A Framework for Ethical Decision Making

CHAPTER ONE What is Philosophy? What s In It For Me?

Thinking Ethically: A Framework for Moral Decision Making

The Biological Foundation of Bioethics

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

Equality of Capacity AMARTYA SEN

A Statement of Seventh-day Adventist Educational Philosophy

We recommend you cite the published version. The publisher s URL is:

The unity of the normative

PROVOCATION EVERYONE IS A PHILOSOPHER! T.M. Scanlon

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation. Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Virtual Mentor American Medical Association Journal of Ethics May 2007, Volume 9, Number 5:

A Framework for the Good

New people and a new type of communication Lyudmila A. Markova, Russian Academy of Sciences

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Attfield, Robin, and Barry Wilkins, "Sustainability." Environmental Values 3, no. 2, (1994):

PROSPECTIVE TEACHERS UNDERSTANDING OF PROOF: WHAT IF THE TRUTH SET OF AN OPEN SENTENCE IS BROADER THAN THAT COVERED BY THE PROOF?

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

David Copp, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory, Oxford: Oxford University

Annotated List of Ethical Theories

Critical Reasoning and Moral theory day 3


A Statement of Seventh-day Adventist Educational Philosophy* Version 7.9

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

Common Morality Approaches for Ethics of Environmental Health

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

Plato and the art of philosophical writing

Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, Pp $90.00 (cloth); $28.99

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

As part of their public service mission, many colleges and

ANALOGIES AND METAPHORS

PHILOSOPHY-PHIL (PHIL)

Reply to Gauthier and Gibbard

Towards Guidelines on International Standards of Quality in Theological Education A WCC/ETE-Project

Philosophy HL 1 IB Course Syllabus

Handout 2: The Ethical Use of PEDs

WILLIAM JESSUP UNIVERSITY COMMUNITY COVENANT

A Social Practice View of Natural Rights. Word Count: 2998

Transcription:

A Review of Donaldson and Dunfee s Ties That Bind: A Social Contracts Approach to Business Ethics Timothy L. Fort ABSTRACT. This article reviews Thomas Donaldson and Thomas Dunfee s new book Ties That Bind. The article argues that the book is a helpful elaboration of Donaldson and Dunfee s Integrative Social Contracts Approach, particularly with regard to their specification of hypernorms. The article also presents Donaldson and Dunfee s argument with regard to how the hypernorm of necessary social efficiency applies to bribery and raises questions about the extent to which human moral behavior might be hardwired. I picked up my copy of Thomas Donaldson and Thomas Dunfee s new book, Ties That Bind: A Social Contracts Approach to Business Ethics, the day that tickets went on sale for The Phantom Menace. The two events have some similarities. Although George Lucas is not likely to become envious of Donaldson and Dunfee s merchandising spin-offs resulting from the book, Ties That Bind has been eagerly awaited by the business ethics community for several years. The book does not disappoint. It is a thorough, provocative, and well-written book, which will spur even more commentary on ISCT. Because the basics of Integrative Social Contracts Theory ( ISCT ) are now wellknown, I do not want to dwell on them at great detail in this review except in brief in order to provide context for the reader to appreciate what new ground the book breaks in terms of the depth by which Donaldson and Dunfee elaborate their approach. Their elaboration is the distinctive mark of the book. In addition, I want to focus, somewhat arbitrarily, on two special points of interest. I. Introduction Timothy L. Fort is an Assistant Professor of Business Law and Business Ethics at the University of Michigan. His work focuses primarily on the corporate structures necessary to foster ethical business behavior. The Academy of Legal Studies in Business gave him its Junior Faculty Award of Excellence in 1998. II. Overview of the book A. The background of ISCT The history of Donaldson and Dunfee s collaboration is well known in the field. Donaldson was one of the pioneers of contemporary business ethics through the publication of Corporations & Morality. (Donaldson, 1982) His social contract approach to business ethics drew upon classic social contract approaches to moral philosophy. Dunfee meanwhile, relied upon his jurisprudential background to argue that extant social contracts provide a source for moral guidance. (Dunfee, 1991) In their joint work, they have integrated these two kinds of social contracts to accord a significant degree of deference to the norms local communities determine are appropriate while keeping those norms subject to philosophical understandings of moral appropriateness. One of the reasons deference is necessary is because of bounded rationality. In addition to the notions of bounded rationality propounded by economists such as Herbert Simon and Oliver Journal of Business Ethics 28: 383 387, 2000. 2000 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.

384 Timothy L. Fort Williamson, Donaldson and Dunfee argue that moral rationality is strongly bounded in terms of business ethics. This is because business life is artifactual; the rules of business life can vary widely and are not natural. Designing business ethics requires sensitive attention to the rules determined by local communities. Thus, tied to the notion of bounded rationality is the notion of moral free space. Communities are entitled to free space to determine what is appropriate for their time and place. Provided that members of such communities have the capacity to consent to the norms, the community s rules are authentic. Proxies indicating meaningful consent are the rights to exit and voice in the development of the norms. B. The hypernorm question What has generated a good deal of attention since ISCT first debuted is the notion of hypernorms. In order for the local norms to be obligatory (or legitimate), the norms must also be in accord with formal philosophy. Donaldson and Dunfee provide an elaboration of the notion of hypernorms in Ties That Bind. Paralleling Charles Taylor s notion of hypergoods, they define hypernorms as second order moral concepts because they represent norms sufficiently fundamental to serve as a source of evaluation and criticism of community-generated norms. (Donaldson and Dunfee, 1999, p. 50). One of the more interesting aspects of the book is Donaldson and Dunfee s defense of refusing to identify the source of a hypernorm. Several scholars in the field have pushed Donaldson and Dunfee to specify the source of hypernorms. Bill Frederick, for instance, has encouraged Donaldson and Dunfee to locate hypernorms in the processes of nature (Frederick, 1995) while Don Mayer has argued to locate them in reason (Mayer, 1994). In response, Donaldson and Dunfee first rely on the human capacity to recognize a hypernorm. Regardless of the source (reason or nature), a convergence of intellectual thought and the evidence of them as global norms is sufficient to identify them. Second, they are argue that scholars have used ISCT s second-order hypernorms successfully. Thus, unless someone is able to show how such quests to find and apply hypernorms fail in light of the success other scholars have had in finding and applying them, Donaldson and Dunfee remain unconvinced that further specification of the source of hypernorms is necessary (Donaldson and Dunfee, 1999, pp. 74 78). Of course, even the strategy of recognition gets one only so far. If recognition of a hypernorm is central to its status as a hypernorm, how do we recognize them? Donaldson and Dunfee respond to this question quite specifically. They list the following eleven kinds of evidence that suggest the existence of a hypernorm and argue that if two or more of these confirm a widespread recognition of any ethical principle, a decisionmaker should take that as a rebuttal presumption that a hypernorm exists. The eleven kinds of evidence are: 01. Widespread consensus that the principle is universal. 02. Component of well-known global industry standards. 03. Supported by prominent nongovernmental organizations such as the International Labour Organization or Transparency International. 04. Supported by regional government organizations such as the European Community, the OECD, or the Organization of American States. 05. Consistently referred to as a global ethical standard by international media. 06. Known to be consistent with the precepts of major religions. 07. Supported by global business organizations such as the International Chamber of Commerce or the Caux Round Table. 08. Known to be consistent with precepts of major philosophies. 09. Generally supported by a relevant international community of professionals, e.g., accountants or environmental engineers. 10. Known to be consistent with findings concerning universal human values. 11. Supported by the laws of many different

Review of Donaldson and Dunfee 385 countries (Donaldson and Dunfee, 1999, p. 60). In providing this list, Donaldson and Dunfee thus provide a significant amount of specificity to what a hypernorm is and how we can find it. In a sense, they use these extant manifestations of norms in order to reinforce and perhaps identify philosophical criteria for moral behavior. What is thus has a great deal to do with what ought to be or what is at least points toward what ought to be might look like. This is an interesting phenomenological straddle, which may or may not be intellectually convincing to critics, but which allows them to plausibly argue that the burden of proof ought to be shifted to their critics. In legal terms, they have constructed a prima facie case for hypernorms. In a sense, the argument Donaldson and Dunfee make seems to be most akin to a kind of natural law. To vastly oversimplify natural law, if there is an innate moral sense in every human being, then one would expect to find manifestations of it in every human culture. Moreover, if human beings have the ability to reason about the good, then we may be able to specify the moral goods that are important for human life. (Finnis, 1980) Donaldson and Dunfee do exactly this when they seek to ground the existence of hypernorms in extant norms and do so while maintaining the necessity of formal moral philosophy in examining such norms. This parallel is not to argue that Donaldson and Dunfee should locate their argument in natural law. I would expect that they would respond to such a proposal as they have to the arguments of critics already mentioned. That is, they would probably remain agnostic about the source of hypernorms. It seems, however, that a natural law approach that takes seriously the laws of nature is an approach very compatible with Donaldson and Dunfee s project (Fort, 1999). Donaldson and Dunfee elaborate three kinds of hypernorms: procedural, structural, and substantive. Procedural norms are those conditions essential to support consent in microsocial contracts. These would include notions of exit and voice, which permit Donaldson and Dunfee to characterize a community norm as authentic. Structural hypernorms are those principles that establish and support the essential background institutions in society. This would include a legal system designed to assure fair trials. Substantive hypernorms are fundamental concepts of the right and the good such as promise keeping and respect for human dignity. III. Two special points It is arbitrary to select specific points to discuss. Undoubtedly, scholars in the field will address a variety of topics raised in the book. Two particular points, however, struck me as worth additional attention. The first relates to an application of a hypernorm to the perennial global ethics question concerning bribery. The second relates to Donaldson and Dunfee s comments regarding the extent to which human beings may be hardwired to be ethical. A. Necessary social efficiency and bribery As an example of a hypernorm, Donaldson and Dunfee identify necessary social efficiency. By this they mean that an action or policy is efficient when it contributes toward the provision of necessary social goods sufficient to sustain the least well-off members of society at a level of reasonable possibility concerning liberty, health, food, housing, education, and just treatment. (Donaldson and Dunfee, 1999, p. 119) They establish this hypernorm by arguing that two necessary goods are fairness and aggregate welfare (Donaldson and Dunfee, 1999, p. 121). In order to actualize these goods, one must have institutions such as private property. Following Aristotle s argument against Plato, they argue that private property is more likely to be utilized efficiently and productively for the benefit of all members of society than would be the case if no one had private ownership. Therefore, the economic structure of a society must be organized so that resources in which society has a stake should be efficiently utilized and individuals should discharge their role duties stemming from the economizing parameters of efficiency strategies in which one participates.

386 Timothy L. Fort In other words, the least well-off have the best chance of reaching basic goods if resources are used efficiently, and society should be structured to allocate resources efficiently and individuals should fulfill their roles in such a structure. This sounds abstractly enough like a hypernorm and it also has a practical implication. Focusing on bribery, Donaldson and Dunfee make three arguments against it from the perspective of ISCT. First, bribery may violate a role duty in a principal-agent relationship. An agent may extort a bribe for the benefit of the agent herself rather than for the benefit of the principal. Second, even in those communities in which bribery is accepted Donaldson and Dunfee argue that, in fact, the norm is not authentic. They note that bribery is outlawed in all countries. In addition to this evidence that bribery then is not a community norm, they cite interviews conducted with executives in countries where bribery is frequent and record the disgust of executives at the practice. One may wonder if this reaction was for the benefit of the audience (an ethicist), but Donaldson and Dunfee make their point sufficiently well to conclude that bribery may occur, but that does not mean that it is viewed as moral even by members of communities where it does occur. Third, bribery violates the hypernorm of necessary social efficiency. It does this in two ways. One way is that it harms political participation when governmental officials accept bribes. When a government official makes a decision on the basis of a bribe, he is allocating public resources in a manner not subject to the political control of the public. Accordingly, there is a violation of the norm of a society structured to provide the least well off the possibility of pursuing basic goods. A second way that it violates the hypernorm of necessary social efficiency is that it skews the efficient distribution of resources. A common rationalization for bribery is that no one gets hurt. Under Donaldson and Dunfee s analysis, however, the skewing of resources resulting from bribery may very well hurt the least well off. It would surprise me if this assessment of bribery is not found by most ethicists as a very helpful schema. B. Hardwired human nature? Another issue that Donaldson and Dunfee raise from time-to-time, but do not dwell upon, is the notion that human beings may be hardwired to be ethical. This is view advocated recently by biologists and evolutionary psychologists. James Q. Wilson (1993) and Robert Wright (1994) exemplify the position. Their argument is that there is a moral sense among human beings, a conviction substantiated by economist Robert Frank (1988) who reports that cheaters do not dominate in the long term. Donaldson and Dunfee also consider Bill Frederick s case for grounding ethics in nature and note that ethicists can use the argument that nature requires cooperation as well as competitiveness as a weapon against executives who paint a narrow portrait of Darwinian struggles for survival. For Donaldson and Dunfee, the issue is important because authentic norms are the product of human interactions (Donaldson and Dunfee, 1999, p. 155). Perhaps a better way to tap into the biological human nature would be to characterize human beings as Aristotle and Darwin did. Larry Arnhart (1998) has recently argued that Aristotle and Darwin can be linked because, at least in part, they both carefully considered biological evidence to conclude that human beings are social creatures. By virtue of being social creatures, they must elaborate rules by which they live together. Those rules are the cultural specifications of moral behavior (Arnhart, 1998; Fort and Noone, 1999). Thus, as social creatures, human beings must use their reasoning capacities to figure out what rules are necessary to live together. Human beings must in some sense contract with each other. The basis for this is not so much that there is an instinct toward altruism, but rather simply that human beings are social creatures. The danger in relying on a moral sense is that it suggests that such a sense does not thereafter need cultural cultivation. One could simply advise individuals to tap into their biological instincts. Such an approach would be more therapeutic than moral. A moral sense obtains its ethical character, however, by the reality of

Review of Donaldson and Dunfee 387 human sociability. As Frederick argues, a central evolutionary adaptation of human beings is our ability to create culture through natural technosymbolic capacities (Frederick, 1995). I hardly think that Donaldson and Dunfee are prepared to advocate for a view of business ethics absent from this cultural, philosophical explication of moral duties. In raising the notion of human hardwiredness, I simply wish to note that (1) this natural characteristic in fact could be an advantageous recognition by the field (against a narrower notion of Darwinism) while (2) placing the recognition in a human nature of sociability to preserve the necessity of cultural and philosophical specification. The approach of noting human sociability, it seems, fits more easily into Donaldson and Dunfee s framework and does so while doing justice to anthropological studies of human nature. (Fort and Noone, 1999) IV. Conclusion Ties That Bind contains much more than what I have touched upon in this review. Some of the other interesting parts of the book are applications of their rules of thumb, a thoughtful integration of ISCT and stakeholder theory, and several international ethics dilemmas. I dwell on only a few here to highlight some of the book s most interesting aspects. In reading Ties That Bind in the shadow of The Phantom Menace, it strikes me that Donaldson and Dunfee are Jedi Masters from whom everyone in the field can learn a great deal. References Donaldson, T.: 1992, Corporations & Morality (Prentice Hall, Inc., Englewood Cliffs, NJ). Donaldson, T. and T. W. Dunfee: 1999, Ties That Bind: A Social Contracts Approach to Business Ethics (Harvard Business School Press, Cambridge, MA). Donaldson, T. and T. W. Dunfee: 1994, Toward a Unified Conception of Business Ethics: Integrative Social Contracts Theory, Academy of Management Review 19, 252 284. Dunfee, T. W.: 1991, Business Ethics and Extant Social Contracts, Business Ethics Quarterly 1, 23 51. Finnis, J.: 1980, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford University Press, New York). Fort, T. L.: 1999 (in press), A Reconsideration of the Ethics of Mergers and Acquisitions as a New Model for Corporate Governance, Proceedings of the National Academy of Legal Studies in Business (Annual Conference, St. Louis, MO). Fort, T. L. and J. J. Noone: 1999 (in press), Banded Contracts, Mediating Institutions and Corporate Governance, Law and Contemporary Problems. Frank, R.: 1988, Passions Within Reasons: The Strategic Role of Emotions (W.W. Norton & Company, New York). Frederick, W. C.: 1995, Values, Nature & Culture in the AmericanBusiness Corporation (Oxford University Press, New York). Mayer, D.: 1994, Hypernorms and Integrative Social Contracts Theory, Proceedings: International Association for Business and Society (Annual Conference, Hilton Head, SC). Noone, J. J. and T. L. Fort: 1998, Yoda Meets Donaldson and Dunfee: A Naturalist Analysis of Contract Theories of the Firm, Proceedings of the National Meeting of the Academy of Legal Studies in Business (Annual Conference, San Diego, CA). Wilson, J. Q.: 1993, The Moral Sense (The Free Press, New York). Wright, R.: 1994, The Moral Animal; Evolutionary Psychology and Everyday Life (Pantheon Books, New York). University of Michigan Business School, 701 Tappan Street, Ann Arbor, MI 48109 1234, U.S.A. E-mail: timfort@umich.edu