Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Similar documents
Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Intuitive evidence and formal evidence in proof-formation

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Mathematical Existence and Consistency (1950b) Paul Bernays

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Basic Considerations on Epistemology (1937) Paul Bernays

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

Philosophy (PHILOS) Courses. Philosophy (PHILOS) 1

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Kant s Critique of Pure Reason1 (Critique) was published in For. Learning to Count Again: On Arithmetical Knowledge in Kant s Prolegomena

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

Varieties of Apriority

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

In The California Undergraduate Philosophy Review, vol. 1, pp Fresno, CA: California State University, Fresno.

Ethical non-naturalism

Comments on Ludwig Wittgenstein s Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics (1959) Paul Bernays

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

1/12. The A Paralogisms

THE ROLE OF APRIORI, EMPIRICAL, ANALYTIC AND SYNTHETIC IN PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS.

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Bayesian Probability

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

The Basic Thoughts of Friesean Philosophy in Its Relation to the Present-Day State of Science (1930) Paul Bernays

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Mathematics as we know it has been created and used by

Religion and Science: The Emerging Relationship Part II

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

International Phenomenological Society

FIL 4600/10/20: KANT S CRITIQUE AND CRITICAL METAPHYSICS

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

METHODENSTREIT WHY CARL MENGER WAS, AND IS, RIGHT

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

K.V. LAURIKAINEN EXTENDING THE LIMITS OF SCIENCE

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Topics and Posterior Analytics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

Ch V: The Vienna Circle (Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, and Otto Neurath)[title crossed out?]

Kant and the natural numbers

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Analytic Philosophy IUC Dubrovnik,

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

I Don't Believe in God I Believe in Science

Kant and his Successors

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Epistemology Naturalized

Our Knowledge of Mathematical Objects

The Coherence of Kant s Synthetic A Priori

On Naturalism in Mathematics

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions.

Why Rosenzweig-Style Midrashic Approach Makes Rational Sense: A Logical (Spinoza-like) Explanation of a Seemingly Non-logical Approach

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

First- or Second-Order Logic? Quine, Putnam and the Skolem-paradox *

to Frege's Philosophy

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Putnam on Methods of Inquiry

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Carnap s notion of analyticity and the two wings of analytic philosophy. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Potentialism about set theory

Pictures, Proofs, and Mathematical Practice : Reply to James Robert Brown

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

Metaphysical Problems and Methods

COMPOSITIO MATHEMATICA

On the hard problem of consciousness: Why is physics not enough?

A Problem for the Kantian-style Critique of the Traditional Metaphysics By Eugen Zelenak

Early Journal Content on JSTOR, Free to Anyone in the World

Mathematical Ontology and Epistemology: An Analysis of Quine s and Maddy s Unique Arguments. Luke B. D. Quigley

This is a repository copy of Does = 5? : In Defense of a Near Absurdity.

Completeness or Incompleteness of Basic Mathematical Concepts Donald A. Martin 1 2

Class #17: October 25 Conventionalism

semantic-extensional interpretation that happens to satisfy all the axioms.

TRUTH IN MATHEMATICS. H.G. Dales and G. Oliveri (eds.) (Clarendon: Oxford. 1998, pp. xv, 376, ISBN X) Reviewed by Mark Colyvan

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

Brief Remarks on Putnam and Realism in Mathematics * Charles Parsons. Hilary Putnam has through much of his philosophical life meditated on

Transcription:

Bernays Project: Text No. 26 Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays (Bemerkungen zur Philosophie der Mathematik) Translation by: Dirk Schlimm Comments: With corrections by Charles Parsons (6/7/02). When we compare mathematics with logic in regard to the role assigned to these two domains of knowledge within philosophical thinking, we find a disagreement among philosophers. For some logic is singled out; for them, logic in the broader sense is the λóγoς, that what is rational, and logic in the narrower sense is the inventory of elementary insights which should lie beneath all considerations, i.e., the inventory of those truths that hold independently of any particular factual content. Thus, logic in the narrower sense ( pure logic ) has a primary epistemological status. A different starting point takes the method of mathematics as exemplary for all scientific thinking. While for the first point of view the logical is re- [1] garded as the obvious and unproblematic, for the second point of view the mathematical is epistemologically unproblematic. Accordingly, understanding is ultimately mathematical understanding. The idea that all rational 1

insight must be of a mathematical kind plays a fundamental role particularly also in the arguments of David Hume. For this point of view Euclid s Elements counted for a long time as a paradigm of the mathematical method. But often it was not sufficiently clear that from the standpoint of axiomatics the Euclidean axiom system is special (the fact that early commentators had already come up with suggestions for replacing axioms by equivalent ones was an indication of this). Obviously many were of the opinion although probably not the authors of the Greek work that the possibility of a strict and successful proof in geometry is based on the evidence of the axioms. Those who philosophized according to the axiomatic method, in particular in the school of Christian Wolff, at times understood evidence as conceptual evidence, so that they did not distinguish between the logical and the mathematical. The principle of contradiction (which mostly included the principle of excluded middle) was regarded as a magic wand so to speak, from which all scientific and metaphysical knowledge could be obtained with the help of suitable concept formations. As you know, Kant has emphasized in opposition to this philosophy the moment of the intuitive in mathematics in his theory of pure intuition. But also for Kant the possibility of geometry as a successful deductive science is [2] based on the evidence of the axioms, that is in his case, on the intuitive clarity and certainty of the postulates of existence. That the discovery of non- Euclidean, Boyai-Lobatschefskian geometry had such a revolutionary effect on philosophical doctrines is explained by the unclarity in epistemological judgment about Euclid s geometry. 2

But a fundamental change of aspect resulted also for the first of the two mentioned points of view from the development of mathematical logic. It became clear that logic as a discipline (which it was already with Aristotle) does not consist directly in establishing singular logical facts, but rather in investigating the possibilities of proofs in formally delimited domains of deduction, and should better be called metalogic. Furthermore, the method of such a metalogic is typically mathematical. Thus it might seem appropriate to classify logic under mathematics. The fact that this has mostly not been done is explained by the lack of a satisfactory epistemological view of mathematics. The term mathematical was not, so to speak, a sufficiently familiar philosophical term. One tried to understand mathematics itself by classifying it under logic. This is particularly true of Gottlob Frege. You surely know Frege s definition of cardinal number in the framework of his theory of predicates. The method employed here is still important today for the classification of number theory under set theory. [3] Various objections (which might be discussed in a group of those interested) can be raised against the view that hereby an epistemological reduction to pure logic has been achieved. A different way of approaching the question of the relation between mathematics and logic is as is done in particular by R. Carnap to regard both as being analytic. Thereby the Kantian concept of analyticity is fundamentally extended, which has been pointed out especially by E. W. Beth. For the most part the same character of obviousness that is ascribed to analytic sentences in the Kantian sense is attributed to analyticity in this extended sense. 3

As you know, W. V. Quine has fundamentally opposed the distinction between the analytic and the synthetic. Although his arguments contain much that is correct, they do not do justice to the circumstance that by the distinction between the analytic in the wide sense and the synthetic, a fundamental distinction is hit upon, namely the distinction between mathematical facts and facts about natural reality. Just to mention something in this regard: Mathematical statements are justified in a different sense from statements in physics. The mathematical magnitudes of analysis are relevant for physics only approximately. For example, the question whether the speed of light is measured in the centimeter-second-system by a rational or an irrational number has hardly any physical sense. To be sure, the fundamental difference between what is mathematical [4] and natural reality is not a sufficient reason to equate mathematics with logic. It appears natural to count as logic only what results from the general conditions and forms of discourse (concept and judgment). But mathematics is about possible structures, in particular about idealized structures. Herewith, on the one hand the methodical importance of logic becomes apparent, but on the other hand also that its role is in some sense anthropomorphic. This does not hold in the same way for mathematics, where we are prompted to transcend the domain of what is surveyable in intuition in various directions. The importance of mathematics for science results already from the fact that we are concerned with structures in all areas of research (structures in society, structures in the economy, structure of the earth, structures of plants, of processes of life, etc.). The methodical importance of mathematics is also due to the fact that a kind of idealization [5] 4

of objects is applied in most sciences, in particular the theoretical ones. In this sense F. Gonseth speaks of the schematic character of the scientific description. What differentiates the theoretically exact from the concrete is emphasized especially also by Stephan Körner. As you know, science has succeeded in understanding the connections in nature largely structurally, and the applicability of mathematics to the characterization and explanation of the processes in nature reaches much further than humanity had once anticipated. But the success and scope of mathematics is something entirely different from its so-called obviousness. The concept of obviousness is philosophically questionable in general. We can speak of something being relatively obvious in the sense in which, for example, the mathematical facts are obvious for the physicist, the physical laws for the geologist, and the general psychological properties of man for the historian. It may be clearer to speak here of the procedurally prior (according to Gonseth s expression préalable ) instead of the obvious. At all events mathematics is not obvious in the sense that it has no problems, or at least no fundamental problems. But consider for instance, that there was no clear method for analysis for a long time despite its great formal success, but the researchers had to rely more or less upon their instinct. Only in the 19th century precise and clear methods have been achieved here. Considered from a philosophical point of view the theory of the continuum of Dedekind and Cantor, which brought the justifications of these methods to an end, is not at all simple. It is not a matter of the bringing to consciousness of an apriori cognition. One might rather say that here a compromise between 5

the intuitive and the demands of precise concepts has been achieved which succeeded very well. You also know that not all mathematicians agree with this theory of the continuum and that the Brouwerian Intuitionism advocates a different description of the continuum of which one can surely find that it overemphasizes the viewpoint of strict arithmetization at the expense of the geometrically satisfying. The problems connected with the antinomies of set theory are especially well known and often discussed. As you know, different suggestions have been brought forward to repair the antinomies. In particular, axiomatic set theory should be mentioned, which shows that such a small restriction of the set theoretic procedure suffices to avoid the antinomies that all of Cantor s proofs can be maintained. Zermelo s original axiom system for set theory has been, as you surely know, on the one hand extended, on the other hand made formally sharper. The procedure of solving the antinomies using axiomatic set theory can be interpreted philosophically as meaning that the antinomies are taken as an indication that mathematics as a whole is not a mathematical object and therefore mathematics can only be understood as an open manifold. The application of the methods of making formally precise to set theory resulted in a split of the set theoretic considerations into the formulation and deductive development of formal systems, and a model theory. As a result of this split the semantic paradoxes, which could be disregarded at first for the resolution of the purely set theoretic paradoxes, received new formulation and importance. So today we face a new set of fundamental problems, which, to be sure, does not bother mathematics in its proper research, just as the 6

set-theoretic antinomies did not earlier. Rather, [mathematics] unfolds in the different disciplines with great success. The above remarks suggest the following viewpoints for philosophy of mathematics, which are also relevant for epistemology in general: 1. It appears appropriate to ascribe to mathematics factual content, which is different from that of natural reality. That other kinds of objectivity are possible than the objectivity of natural reality is already obvious from the objectivity in the phenomenological regions. Mathematics is not phenomenological insofar, as has been said before, it is about idealized structures on the one hand, and on the other hand it is governed by the method of deduction. With idealization, intuitiveness comes into contact with conceptualization. (Therefore, it is not appropriate to oppose intuitiveness and conceptualization so heavily as it is done in Kantian philosophy). The significance of mathematics for theoretical physics consists in the fact that therein the processes of nature are represented approximatively by mathematical entities. 2. It does not follow from the difference between mathematics and empirical research that we have knowledge in mathematics that is secured at the outset (apriori). It seems necessary to concede that we also have to learn in the fields of mathematics and that we here, too, have an experience sui generis (we might call it intellectual experience ). This does not diminish the rationality of mathematics. Rather, the assumption that rationality is necessarily connected with certainty appears to be a prejudice. We almost nowhere have certain knowledge in the simple, full sense. This is the old Socratic insight which is emphasized today especially also in the philosophies 7

of F. Gonseth and K. Popper. We have certainly to admit that in mathematical considerations, in particular in those of elementary mathematics, we possess a particular kind of security, because on the one hand the objects are intuitively clear and, on the other hand, almost everything is stripped off by the idealization of the objects that could lead to subjectivity. But when we talk about the certainty of 2 2 = 4 in the popular sense, we think at the concrete applications of this statement. But the application of arithmetical statements to the concrete is based on empirical conditions, and for their compliance we only have an empirical, even if practically sufficient certainty. By dropping the coupling of rationality and certainty we gain, among other things, the possibility to appreciate the heuristic rationality, which plays an essential role for scientific inquiry. The acknowledgment of heuristic rationality provides in particular the solution to the epistemological difficulty that has been made a problem by David Hume: we can acknowledge the rational character of the assumption of necessary connections in nature, without having to claim that the basic approach of [assuming] such connections guarantees success; with regard to this success we depend in fact on experience. 8