Harman s Moral Relativism

Similar documents
Two Kinds of Moral Relativism

Moral Relativism Defended

METAETHICAL MORAL RELATIVISM AND THE ANALOGY WITH PHYSICS

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

2013 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved. 1

Citation for the original published paper (version of record):

Zimmerman, Michael J. Subsidiary Obligation, Philosophical Studies, 50 (1986):

Forms of Relativism. Wong [1993] recognises two forms of relativism:

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises



A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Can moral facts be an explanation? naturalism and non-naturalism is whether or not there are any moral explanations

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

Are Practical Reasons Like Theoretical Reasons?

Moral dilemmas. Digital Lingnan University. Lingnan University. Gopal Shyam NAIR

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January

Philosophical Review.

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

The unity of the normative

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

Presupposition and Accommodation: Understanding the Stalnakerian picture *

Virtue Ethics without Character Traits

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

Historic Roots. o St. Paul gives biblical support for it in Romans 2, where a law is said to be written in the heart of the gentiles.

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

Should We Assess the Basic Premises of an Argument for Truth or Acceptability?

Reply to Gauthier and Gibbard

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and. Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xvi, 286.

SOCRATES, PIETY, AND NOMINALISM. love is one of the most well known in the history of philosophy. Yet some fundamental

Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Ethical universal: An ethical truth that is true at all times and places.

Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument

Henrik Ahlenius Department of Philosophy ETHICS & RESEARCH

In his book Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, J. L. Mackie agues against

James Rachels. Ethical Egoism

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

The Department of Philosophy and Classics The University of Texas at San Antonio One UTSA Circle San Antonio, TX USA.

Julius & Aleks 03/27/2014

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

Is Morality Rational?

Am I free? Freedom vs. Fate

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

The Power of Critical Thinking Why it matters How it works

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation. Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Love and Duty. Philosophic Exchange. Julia Driver Washington University, St. Louis, Volume 44 Number 1 Volume 44 (2014)

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

Q2) The test of an ethical argument lies in the fact that others need to be able to follow it and come to the same result.

How to Write a Philosophy Paper

A Case for Dispositional Innatism

Did Marc Hauser's Moral Minds Plagiarize John Mikhail's Earlier Work?

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Bayesian Probability

Lecture notes, Phil 4830, spr 03. Anti-Realism

World-Wide Ethics. Chapter Two. Cultural Relativism

Bayesian Probability

Relativism and Subjectivism. The Denial of Objective Ethical Standards

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

Bombs and Coconuts, or Rational Irrationality

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Smith s Incoherence Argument for Moral Rationalism

7 Essential Universal Laws for Creating a Successful, Fulfilling and Happy Life

Kant. Deontological Ethics

Deontological Ethics. Kant. Rules for Kant. Right Action

Comments on Lasersohn

In his paper Internal Reasons, Michael Smith argues that the internalism

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

In his celebrated article Toward a Reconstruction of Utility and Welfare Economics,

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

On the Origins and Normative Status of the Impartial Spectator

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

BRITISH PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION AQA PHILOSOPHY UNIT 3: MORAL PHILOSOPHY

Hume s emotivism. Michael Lacewing

MORAL CONCEPTS AND MOTIVATION 1. Mark Greenberg UCLA

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

Transcription:

Harman s Moral Relativism Jordan Wolf March 17, 2010 Word Count: 2179 (including body, footnotes, and title) 1

1 Introduction In What is Moral Relativism? and Moral Relativism Defended, 1 Gilbert Harman, unsurprisingly, defends moral relativism. His relativism has two components: a substantive claim that different people are subject to different ultimate moral demands (what Harman calls normative moral relativism) and a semantic claim about the logical properties of moral judgments (what Harman calls moral judgment relativism). In this paper I describe Harman s argument for normative moral relativism and then describe how his analysis of certain moral judgments what he calls inner judgments follows from it. I then examine two objections one from David Lyons and another from Betsy Postow which I believe call for the same type of response from Harman. Ultimately, I think their criticisms do damage to Harman s view, but not an overwhelming amount. 2 Two Components of Harman s View In Moral Relativism Defended, Harman presents an argument for normative moral relativism, which he believes follows from three plausible assumptions about morality: moral internalism, motivational internalism, and Humean moral psychology. Here s the argument. 1. Moral Internalism. In order for X to be subject to an ultimate moral demand D, X must have a practical reason to act in accord with D. 2. Motivational Internalism. In order for X to have a practical reason to act in accord with D, X must be motivated or capable of being motivated, to act in accord with D, barring some cognitive defect such as mental illness or ignorance. 3. Humean Moral Psychology. An agent can only be motivated to act in accord with his current desires, or the desires he would have after engaging in a conservative type of practical deliberation. There could be two agents, one which is motivated to perform some action and another which is not. 1 Hereafter cited as (Harman What) and (Harman MRD) respectively. See the bibliography for the full citations. 1

Conclusion. Moral demands are relative. There could be two people, one of which is subject to an ultimate moral demand D and another which is not. In plain terms, the argument is this: a moral demand is just a practical reason, but since people differ in their practical reasons, they differ in what moral demands apply to them. Harman s analysis of inner judgments proceeds along similar lines, my thesis is this. Ought (A, D, C, M) means roughly that, given that A has motivating attitudes M and given C, D is the course of action for A that is supported by the best reasons (MRD 10). Again, since moral demands for Harman are just motivating concerns (practical reasons), an inner judgment is just a judgment about what concerns could motivate the agent being judged. Since motivation is relative to the agent being assessed, inner judgments must be agent relative as well. For example, it is false to say of a Muslim that he ought to go to mass because such a judgment does not connect with a motivation he has or could have; a Muslim has no reason to go to mass. Further, if one knew ahead of time that someone was a Muslim, it would not only be false but disingenuous to say that he ought to go to mass. In summary, for a moral demand to in fact apply to an agent is for the agent to be capable of being motivated to act in accord with it and so a moral judgment simply claims that the proper motivation is present. With Harman s view in place, we can now turn to criticisms of it. 3 Postow s Criticism Postow presents a sophisticated argument which is ostensibly directed against moral relativism. I claim that it fails, but not without leaving a residual worry. Postow imagines a situation in which an agent believes that there are many well-grounded but mutually exclusive moral conceptions and yet allies herself with one of them and ignores the rest. The question on Postow s mind is: what does it mean to embrace a particular moral theory if one is swimming in a sea of equally justified alternatives? The answer cannot be that the theory that the agent selected is justified, or even the most justified, because ex hypothesi they are all, in the agent s eyes, equally justified. So, Postow claims that to even have a moral view in the light of equally well-credentialed competitors requires some sort of practical commitment to the view (Dishonest 2

46) that is singled out for adherence. 2 In her mind, this commitment is a disposition to offer advice to others that is consistent with the requirements of the moral view that one accepts. If I believe lying is wrong, then I must be willing to exhort others not to lie in situations where moral advice is appropriate. The problem is that such recommendations cannot be sincerely offered if I know that the person being advised has no reason to heed the recommendation. How could I, in good faith, counsel someone not to lie if I knew he had no reason to follow the recommendation? Here is the argument laid bare. 3 1. Practical Constraint. If an agent A holds that several moral views are equally justified, then holding some moral view Y requires making sincere recommendations based on Y to adherents of other moral views. 2. Sincerity Constraint. A cannot sincerely make a recommendation to someone that A knows has no reason to heed it. 3. Moral Outsiders. B, an adherent of moral view Z, has no reason to act in accord with a contradictory but equally justified moral view such as Y. 4 4. So, A cannot make sincere recommendations to adherents of other equally justified moral views. Conclusion. So, one cannot hold a moral view if he believes that other moral views are equally justified. Before looking at some possible responses to this argument, I want to note one part of the argument that seems strange to me, but can be easily set right. (3) claims that B has no reason to act in accord with a rival but equally well-justified moral view Y, but why not? If Y is just as justified as B s own moral view (Z), then why aren t its reasons just as good as those provided by Z? I think the argument 2 I use (Postow Honest) for Toward Honest Ethical Pluralism. See the bibliography for both of the full citations. 3 This reconstruction is my own attempt, but happily, it looks very similar to Postow s own retrospective interpretation of this argument offered in Toward Honest Ethical Pluralism. 4 Because I go on to criticize this premise, here is Postow s exact language. She writes, But Alice believes that Bob s moral theory, which condones and even commands the use of animal products, is equally well-grounded as her own. Therefore she believes that Bob has no moral reason to abstain from animal products (Postow Dishonest, 47, emphasis mine). 3

could be clarified by claiming that it would be dishonest or insincere to advise a course of action that one does not believe is better than the course of action currently being pursued. Since moral views Y and Z are equally justified, it would be insincere to recommend that B follow Y over Z. The reformed argument would look like this: 1. Practical Constraint. If an agent A holds that several moral views are equally justified, then holding some moral view Y requires making sincere recommendations based on Y to adherents of other equally justified moral views. 2. Sincerity Constraint. A cannot sincerely make recommendations based on some moral view Y to someone who is adhering to what A takes to be an equally justified but rival moral system. 3. So, A cannot make sincere recommendations to adherents of other equally justified moral views. Conclusion. So, A cannot hold a moral view if he believes that other moral views are equally justified. I think there is one response to this argument that is available to anyone and two others which are available to Harman only. I look only at the latter two. 5 For a relativist like Harman, Postow s argument starts in the wrong place. Relativism does not commit an agent to believing that several moral views are equally justified and to think that it does confuses relativism with pluralism. The relativist does not believe that all moral views are equally acceptable, true, or justified. Indeed, the relativist cannot make sense of speaking about moral views in such universal terms. Instead, the relativist thinks of moral views as acceptable to or justified for. A well-worn example makes the point clear. I am a relativist about ice cream flavors. I think vanilla is good for me, but knowing that you like strawberry, I think strawberry is good for you. If you ordered strawberry, it would make no sense for me to say you ought to have ordered vanilla. As a relativist in this situation, I do not think that vanilla and strawberry are equally good. I think vanilla and not strawberry is good-for-me, and as a relativist, I cannot assess goodness without making it relative to someone. Additionally, Harman could, in a qualified sense, agree with Postow. Someone who holds a particular moral view will be disposed to offer advice to those who he believes to have similar moral 5 The public argument is in appendix A for optional reading. 4

commitments. The agreement is qualified because a relativist could not sincerely give moral advice to those that he knows are moral outsiders those who do not share his moral commitments. Whether the response is adequate depends on what support can be marshaled for thinking that a moral view must be able to sincerely offer moral advice to all other moral agents and not just ones that are similar to one doing the evaluating. Still, even if a commitment to giving sincere advice to all others is not a constraint on having a moral view at all, it is a familiar part of moral discourse, and Harman has nothing to say about it. It s true, ordinary speakers do shy away from making recommendations contrary to a person s moral code such as telling a devout Muslim that he ought to go to mass, but in other cases judgments may be knowingly made from the judger s moral perspective. If there are such cases, then Postow s criticism leaves a residual worry. 4 Lyons Criticism David Lyons spends most of his paper discussing appraiser relativism and then turns briefly to Harman s view, which he correctly flags as agent-relative. His argument is that agent-relativism is an ad hoc maneuver designed to save relativism, which, in its appraiser-relative form, is incoherent. The conclusion is that because agent-relativism is an ad hoc maneuver, it should not command our philosophical respect. So, clearly enough, Lyons argument will turn on whether an agent-relative account of inner judgments is in fact ad hoc, but before turning to this question, I want to signal the convergence of Lyons and Postow s criticisms. Lyons claims that an agent-relative interpretation of moral discourse is unsupported by everyday conversation and Postow claims that it is worse than unsupported; it is contradicted by it. Are they right? I tend to think so, but defending them requires responding to Harman s assertion that our ordinary ways of speaking do respect the agent-relative line he has drawn. His prime example is inner judgments about Hitler. We can properly say, Hitler ought not to have ordered the extermination of the Jews, if what we mean is that it ought never to have happened; and we can say without oddity 5

that what Hitler did was wrong. Oddity attends only the inner judgment that Hitler was wrong to have acted in that way. That is what sounds too weak. (MRD 7) But this gets things backwards I think. Talking about the wrongness of the situation or the action of genocide itself is sanitizing compared to a judgment about Hitler s action. Saying that the holocaust should not have happened is mistakes-were-made talk. Of course the holocaust should not have happened but this draws the focus off of the perpetrators who ought not to have done what they did, and nothing seems strange or weak about the formulation that connects actor and deed. Harman then goes on to say that inner judgments about Hitler seem too weak because it feels like he is beyond the the reach of moral motivation (MRD 8), but his motivational obstinacy is what I would have thought makes him evil, not what makes inner judgments about him sound odd. 5 Conclusion The objections made by Lyons and Postow come down to a simple, similar point; inner judgments don t feel agent relative in many situations. Harman of course has a response, but I think it is unsatisfactory. Still, all this shows is that Harman s view is wounded, not that it is dead. 6

A The Public Argument Against Postow The public response to Postow s argument is to question the motivation behind the practical constraint (1). Postow says that the condition for holding a moral view in the face of equally justified rivals is a disposition to make moral recommendations, but it could be something else. For example, why not say that the right practical commitment consists in allowing one view to be action guiding. In other words, the agent could concede that all views are equally justified but nonetheless adhere to one of them. Thus, the conclusion of the argument above is too strong. Willingness to give moral advice need not be a condition on holding a moral view because this role can be played by a willingness to let the theory guide one s action. Still, even if a disposition to make moral recommendations is not a constraint on holding a moral view, it seems that most moral views should make sense of this common phenomenon. 7

References [1] Harman, Gilbert. Moral Relativism Defended. The Philosophical Review 84.1 (1975): 3-22. [2] Harman, Gilbert. What is Moral Relativism? Values and Morals. Eds. Alvin Goldman and Jaegwon Kim. Reidel: Boston, 1978. 143-161. [3] Lyons, David. Ethical Relativism and the Problem of Incoherence. Ethics 86.2 (1976): 107-121. [4] Postow, B.C. Dishonest Relativism. Analysis 39.1 (1979): 45-48. [5] Postow, B.C. Toward Honest Ethical Pluralism. Philosophical Studies 132 (2007): 191-210. 8