Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy

Similar documents
FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Weekend Retreat and Workshop, Heidegger, Being and Time Graduate Seminar, Lotz Nov 21-Nov 23, 2008 Seminarpage

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017

REVIEW ARTICLE Steven Crowell and Jeff Malpas (eds.) Transcendental Heidegger Stanford University Press, 2007

11/23/2010 EXISTENTIALISM I EXISTENTIALISM. Existentialism is primarily interested in the following:

Sacha Golub. Heidegger on Concepts, Freedom, and Normativity. Cambridge University Press pp. $95.00 USD (Hardcover ISBN ).

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

CURRICULUM VITAE : Thomas Jack Lynch Teacher-Scholar Postdoctoral Fellow, Wake Forest University

A Review of Lack and Transcendence: The Problem of Death and Life in Psychotherapy, Existentialism, and Buddhism

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

INTENTIONALITY IN HUSSERL AND HEIDEGGER

Edmund Husserl s Transcendental Phenomenology by Wendell Allan A. Marinay

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

Jacob Martin Rump, PhD Symposium: Contemporary Work in Phenomenology Boston Phenomenology Circle Boston University, 1 April 2016

The Role of Love in the Thought of Kant and Kierkegaard

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

Chapter 25. Hegel s Absolute Idealism and the Phenomenology of Spirit

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE. Graduate course and seminars for Fall Quarter

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Heidegger Introduction

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00.

[THIS PENULTIMATE VERSION MAY DIFFER IN MINOR WAYS FROM THE PUBLISHED VERSION. PLEASE DO NOT QUOTE FROM THIS WITHOUT MY PERMISSION]

1/9. The Second Analogy (1)

EXISTENTIALISM AND FILM. LECTURE NOTES:

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Tuesday, November 11, Hegel s Idealism

Some Background on Jonas

Heidegger's What is Metaphysics?

A Christian Philosophy of Education

Haecceitas and the Question of Being: Heidegger and Duns Scotus

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger

Gelassenheit See releasement. gender See Beauvoir, de

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

6AANA032 Nineteenth-Century Continental Philosophy Syllabus Academic year 2013/14

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas

Department of Philosophy

Communicative Rationality and Deliberative Democracy of Jlirgen Habermas: Toward Consolidation of Democracy in Africa

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Course Coordinator Dr Melvin Chen Course Code. CY0002 Course Title. Ethics Pre-requisites. NIL No of AUs 3 Contact Hours

Kierkegaard: A Phenomenologist?

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Life has become a problem.

Teachur Philosophy Degree 2018

Naturalism and Subjectivity

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

REASONS AND REFLECTIVE ENDORSMENT IN CHRISTINE KORSGAARD S THE SOURCES OF NORMATIVITY ERIC C. BROWN. (Under the direction of Melissa Seymour-Fahmy)

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGIOUS STUDIES

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

How Technology Challenges Ethics

2 heidegger s analytic

Kant and his Successors

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

This is the penultimate version. Please quote from the published version, European Journal of Philosophy, 24:2 pp , DOI: /ejop.

The Kant vs. Hume debate in Contemporary Ethics : A Different Perspective. Amy Wang Junior Paper Advisor : Hans Lottenbach due Wednesday,1/5/00

Tatyana P. Lifintseva, Professor at the School of Philosophy, NRU HSE Staraya Basmannaya ul., 21/4, office

Anselmian Theism and Created Freedom: Response to Grant and Staley

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Philosophy Courses-1

The Soul Journey Education for Higher Consciousness

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Understanding the burning question of the 1940s and beyond

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Philosophy (PHILOS) Courses. Philosophy (PHILOS) 1

Philosophy Courses-1

John Haugeland. Dasein Disclosed: John Haugeland s Heidegger. Edited by Joseph Rouse. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2013.

KNOWLEDGE OF SELF AND THE WORLD

In what sense does consciousness provide its own criterion?

1/8. The Third Analogy

A Backdrop To Existentialist Thought

Reality. Abstract. Keywords: reality, meaning, realism, transcendence, context

Course Text. Course Description. Course Objectives. StraighterLine Introduction to Philosophy

LOOKING FOR INTENTIONALITY WITH HEIDEGGER

Action: Phenomenology of Wishing and Willing in Husserl and Heidegger

Perspectival Methods in Metaphysics

The Being of Intentionality

1/12. The A Paralogisms

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

Foundationalism and Practical Reason

Existentialism. And the Absurd

The Singularity of the Self

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) PHIL Courses. Philosophy (PHIL) 1

Theories of the Self. Description:

Gilles Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, trans. Mark Lester (New York: Columbia University Press, 1990 [Logique du sens, Minuit, 1969])

Rosmini and phenomenology

Transcription:

Provided by the author(s) and NUI Galway in accordance with publisher policies. Please cite the published version when available. Title Steven Crowell - Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger Author(s) O'Rourke, Jonathan Publication Date 2013-09-21 Publication Information O'Rourke, J. (2013). Steven Crowell - Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger. Symposium, 17(2). Publisher Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy Link to publisher's version http://www.c-scp.org/en/2013/09/21/steven-crowell- normativity-and-phenomenology-in-husserl-and-heidegger- 2.html Item record http://hdl.handle.net/10379/4788 Downloaded 2018-07-12T08:05:07Z Some rights reserved. For more information, please see the item record link above.

Steven Crowell, Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013; 321 pages. ISBN 978-1107682559 Review by Jonathan O Rourke, National University of Ireland, Galway Given the ubiquity of Husserl s influence in the twentieth century, it is often vexing to interpret the complicated appropriation of his vocabulary by later writers. In particular, his placement of phenomenology in the transcendental tradition has been a source of contention among his successors. It is not surprising therefore, that as the posthumous publications force us to revaluate the breadth of his work, the now caricatured relationship between Husserl and Heidegger requires some further clarification. It is this relationship in particular which forms the structure of the present volume. Given the radically different motives which drove both philosophers, this series of essays collectively attempt to interpret their work in terms of their analysis of normatively structured meaning. Read individually, the essays detail several key aspects of phenomenology s treatment of normativity in experience, both from Husserlian and Heideggarian perspectives. In so doing, an attempt is made to demonstrate the limitations of Husserl s approach which, Crowell argues, necessitate the work of Heidegger. In his analysis of the latter, Crowell further attempts to show that Heidegger s conception of authenticity as responsibility, is important in interpreting the nature of reason. To that end, the final set of essays centre themselves on issues in practical philosophy, examining among other things how the Heideggarian account of normativity surmounts that of Korsgaard, with which it is compared. Here and throughout this volume, there is also a significant emphasis on history. In particular, Crowell s first essay Making Meaning Thematic, attempts to evaluate the place of phenomenology in transcendental tradition. For Crowell, Husserl s thematization of meaning is a three tiered process: it involves the rejection of Kantian representationalism; an adoption of the Neo-Kantian interpretation of the categories; and an insistence on the first personal perspective of philosophical method. Owing to the lack of self-referential validity in Kant s Critique, phenomenology s radical step forward is not to ignore the anthropological or subjective dimension of Kant s method, but rather to thematise it, to render it philosophy s primary datum. (15) Crowell draws a comparison with Emil Lask, for whom the ontological status of the categories could not be resolved in Kant s two-world theory. According to Lask, the categories are neither metaphysical nor psychological, and thus

Kant s epistemology fails to account for them as an object of knowledge. It is from this starting point that Lask develops a normative account of meaning. Whilst both Husserl and Lask s conception of the object as unity-of-meaning bear out similarities, it is only Husserl who insists that reflective analysis of intentionality is the route to meaning. For Husserl, transcendental logic must finally be grounded in transcendental phenomenology. (23) An important aspect of Crowell s thesis is that Heidegger s departure from Husserl on actanalysis, through grounding noetic acts in a practical comportment, does not subvert the centrality of subjectivity as it often taken to do. The remaining portion of the chapter broadly outlines this thesis before picking it up again in Chapter 8, Subjectivity. Crowell begins here by distinguishing between the kind of self-apprehension disregarded by Heidegger, and the reflective self-disclosure offered to Dasein by practical involvements. For Crowell, Heidegger s untraditional conception of subjectivity cannot be considered an adequate account of self-awareness. (173) The I of my practical engagements merely offers Dasein the who of its everydayness. The task, as Crowell writes, is to describe a mode of selfawareness, one not subject to Heidegger s objections against the merely formal character of reflective I-consciousness. (173) Drawing on the work of Zahavi, Crowell outlines three conditions satiable by any first-person self-reference theory: that the use of I infallibly picks out the entity it purports to refer to (176); that self-identification is immediate, noncriterial, and non-inferential ; and it requires that I dispense with every type of third-person reference. (177) Crowell s aim is to show that it is Heidegger s conception of conscience which ultimately satisfies these conditions. Crowell centres on Heidegger s account of anxiety, which provides the framework by which Dasein grasps itself as the solus ipse. However, this does not mean that I find myself alone; rather, I discover my subjectivity irreducible to any totality of involvements. (180) It is in the breakdown of discourse, which manifests for Heidegger the call of conscience (gewissen), that we can find an analysis of self-awareness which satisfies these conditions. For Crowell, The phenomenon of conscience belongs to the breakdown of the one-self (181) that which is reflectively grasped by Dasein in its practical dealings and whilst Heidegger employs the term Self to describe what remains, Crowell interprets this as the subjectivity, or first-person self-awareness of Dasein. (181) Here, third person referents have been relinquished, and it is merely the self which is being appealed to. Moreover, the infallibility of this self-reference is clear. Quoting Heidegger, he writes though the call passes over what Dasein, proximally and for the most part, understands itself as nonetheless the Self has been reached, unequivocally and unmistakably. (182) Drawing a comparison

with Kierkegaard, Crowell identifies what conscience says as neither the one-self (who says I but not as I myself), nor the authentic Self, (a modification of the one-self), but the hidden condition of both. (183) Conscience, as Kierkegaardian inwardness, is the hidden condition of the world as a space of meaning. (184) The significance of Crowell s analysis here is that it lays the foundation for what is probably the book s most interesting thesis: conscience as the origin of reason. Crowell argues that if we move from viewing Dasein as a creature who has been socialised into normative rules, to one who grasps itself in light of these norms, we necessarily require an appeal to conscience and by extension, guilt as the ground for self-awareness. Dasein s responsibility transforms a creature who is grounded by social norms into a ground of obligation one who grounds norms by giving grounds, that is, reasons. (187) This analysis, fleshed out further in Chapters 9 and 10, is dealt with in the book s concluding section, concerning practical philosophy. In Chapter 11, The Existential Sources of Normativity, Crowell draws a comparison between the Heideggarian account of normativity and that of Christine Korsgaard. Whilst both theories are similar, he argues that Heidegger s approach surmounts that of Korsgaard by avoiding three logical aporias and phenomenological distortions which befall her theory: an equivocation in the concept of self-consciousness (241); an aporia in Korsgaard s account of the person (250); and distortions in the phenomenology of action (256). For Korsgaard, self-consciousness is that capacity by which we fission the impulse-response nature of our animal instincts. Freeze-framing this dynamic, and the ethical question it forces upon us, creates the space in which we are compelled to choose our practical identities. Selfconsciousness then, on Korsgaard s account, is the existential source of normativity. As Crowell states, quoting Korsgaard, Identifying with [a practical identity], its norms provide me with the principles that, in lieu of instinct, tell me what justifies what, what counts as a reason for what, what is worth doing for the sake of what. (246) For Crowell however, this account equivocates on the nature of self-consciousness. Defined both as a mode of selfawareness, and in terms of reflection, as a higher-order act that reifies a state into a kind of mental item or content of consciousness (246), the description leads to an infinite regress by appeal to the latter as a specific mental act. (246) Moreover, he argues that even if such self-consciousness does open the space between instinctive impulse and physical response, there is no account given as to why such animal instincts lose their authority. Quoting Thomas Nagel, he writes Why isn t the reflective individual just someone with more information How do reasons, laws, and universality get a foothold here? (248) Heidegger

too approximates this point in his description of Angst, in which Dasein can no longer press forward smoothly into practical possibilities for being. (249) However, for Dasein to take over being-a-ground is not to progress from some pre-normative ontological condition to one governed by norms; rather, it is to uncover the condition that enables me to act not only in conformity to norms but also in light of them. (249) Crowell argues that to appeal to selfconsciousness as the source of normativity, necessarily invokes an equivocation in the account of that very self-consciousness, one that is ultimately avoided by Heidegger. On her account of personhood, as the grounding of what we do in choosing one practical identity over another, Crowell levels against Korsgaard the same critique Heidegger offers on Kantian personalism, namely that it cannot do justice to the facticity of such an agent. Her account of animality, he writes, oscillates between being part of one s humanity and being something that stands over against it and it is this equivocation that distorts her conception of personhood. (252) Moreover, conceiving of humanity in a manner wholly governed by the concept of reflection, by a deliberating agent, non-deliberated action must either be seen as a reversion to animality, or the structure of deliberation must be smuggled back into it. (256) In taking the latter perspective, Crowell argues, Korsgaard s account distorts the phenomenology of such action (256) Overall, this series of essays present a fascinating interpretation of key themes in Husserl and Heidegger. Whilst at times the transition between essays can seem somewhat bumpy, the organisation within the four sections provides a well thought-out thesis concerning their relationship, and will no doubt be of interest to anyone working through the areas of subjectivity, normativity and the philosophy of action.