Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations

Similar documents
Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

Wittgenstein: Meaning and Representation

CONCEPT OF WILLING IN WITTGENSTEIN S PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS

What is Wittgenstein s View of Knowledge? : An Analysis of the Context Dependency

"Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages

Truth, Nonsense, and the Meaningfulness of Ostensive Gestures. L: Public language is a logical prerequisite for an ostensive gesture to be meaningful.

Wittgenstein s Logical Atomism. Seminar 8 PHIL2120 Topics in Analytic Philosophy 16 November 2012

4181 ( 10.5), = 625 ( 11.2), = 125 ( 13). 311 PPO, p Cf. also: All the errors that have been made in this chapter of the

Kevin MacNeil, Culver Academies

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

TRUTH IN WITTGENSTEIN, TRUTH IN LINDBECK

Matters of Fact and Relations of Ideas

Death and Immortality (by D Z Phillips) Introductory Remarks

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

This paper distinguishes five key interpretations of the argument presented by

Meaning is Use and Wittgenstein s Treatment of Philosophical Problems

Wittgenstein and the Skeptical Paradoxes

A Study on Ludwig Wittgenstein s Concept of Language Games and the Private Language Argument

KRIPKE'S DOUBTS ABOUT MEANING

Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

What Happens When Wittgenstein Asks "What Happens When...?"

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Language

AN APPROACH TO WITTGENSTEIN'S PHILOSOPHY

Wittgenstein s The First Person and Two-Dimensional Semantics

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 3 : N A T U R E O F R E A L I T Y

Resolute Readings of Later Wittgenstein and the Challenge of Avoiding Hierarchies in Philosophy

Epistemology and sensation

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

What Numbers Might Be Scott Soames. John's anti-nominalism embraces numbers without, as far as I know, worrying very

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the

Class #3 - Meinong and Mill

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

A (Very) Brief Introduction to Epistemology Lecture 2. Palash Sarkar

The New Wittgenstein, ed. Alice Crary and Rupert Read, London and New York, 2000, pp. v + 403, no price.

Classical Theory of Concepts

Wittgenstein and Intentionality (Revised 2013)

The Metaphysical Status of Tractarian Objects 1

Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed

Wittgenstein. The World is all that is the case. http// Philosophy Insights. Mark Jago. General Editor: Mark Addis

Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (abridged version) Ludwig Wittgenstein

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Wittgenstein and Religion

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Grade 7. correlated to the. Kentucky Middle School Core Content for Assessment, Reading and Writing Seventh Grade

Issues in Thinking about God. Michaelmas Term 2008 Johannes Zachhuber

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

Foundations of Analytic Philosophy

Edmund Dain. and Wittgenstein s opposition or hostility to that tradition. My aim will be to argue that

Wittgenstein says in Philosophical Investigations I33 that

Is There an External World? George Stuart Fullerton

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

Philosophy 428M Topics in the History of Philosophy: Hume MW 2-3:15 Skinner Syllabus

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

The Indeterminacy of Translation: Fifty Years Later

Review of Wittgenstein-a critical reader Hans-Johann Glock (ed.) (2001)(review revised 2019) Michael Starks ABSTRACT

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall 2014

Philosophy Faculty Reading List and Course Outline PART II PAPER 09: WITTGENSTEIN READING LIST

Religious belief, hypothesis and attitudes

Language and the World: Unit Two

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

George Wrisley. Thesis: Wittgenstein s Conception of the Autonomy of Language and its Implications for Natural Kinds.

Title: Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction.

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Norman Malcolm ( )

Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke. M.A. Thesis Proposal. Department of Philosophy, CSULB. 25 May 2006

Reviews WITTGENSTEIN, CRITIC OF RUSSELL. Russell Wahl. English and Philosophy / Idaho State U Pocatello, id 83209, usa

PHIL/COMS/LING 2504-A. Language and Communication. Carleton University Department of Philosophy

To the first questions the answers may be obtained by employing the process of going and seeing, and catching and counting, respectively.

DIALECTICS AND CONVERSION IN WITTGENSTEIN S LATER WORK: WHY IT IS GOOD TO CHANGE YOUR MIND 1

RUSSELL AND VAGUENESS

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Wittgenstein's Conception of First Person Psychological Sentences as "Expressions"

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia

WITTGENSTEIN S PRIVATE LANGUAGE ARGUMENT ACCORDING TO KRIPKE. Wittgenstein according to Kripke 1

Making Sense of Winch. Jan Overwijk August 2012 Supervisors: Bert van den Brink Joel Anderson

WITTGENSTEIN ON EPISTEMOLOGICAL STATUS OF LOGIC 1

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2015

Qualia Ain't in the Head Review of Ten Problems of Consciousness: A Representational Theory of the Phenomenal Mind by Michael Tye

How to Investigate the Grammar of Aspect- Perception: A Question in Wittgensteinian Method

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

The purpose of this paper is to introduce the problem of skepticism as the

From last lecture. Then W argues that this same series of events could not occur for a private language.

Fred Wilson UNIVERSALS, PARTICULARS, TROPES AND BLOBS

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Later Wittgenstein on Essentialism, Family Resemblance and Philosophical Method 1

ON NONSENSE IN THE TRACTATUS LOGICO-PHILOSOPHICUS: A DEFENSE OF THE AUSTERE CONCEPTION

Book Reviews 427. University of Manchester Oxford Rd., M13 9PL, UK. doi: /mind/fzl424

From Theory to Mysticism

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Transcription:

Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations Published posthumously in 1953 Style and method Style o A collection of 693 numbered remarks (from one sentence up to one page, usually one paragraph long). o These remarks are extracted by Wittgenstein from larger manuscripts (written from 1929 till 1951). We possess 20 000 pages of these (handwritten or typed) manuscripts. o There are many chains of remarks elaborating upon a certain topic. There are several breaks where the topic is changed without any explicit notice. o Many remarks have the form of a fictional dialogues between two (and occasionally three) partners or voices. Sometimes it is not clear which voice is Wittgenstein s. o Many remarks end with analogies or open questions (that are left unexplained or unanswered). o Wittgenstein uses often examples (real as well as imaginary). There are only a few generalizations (like meaning is use ). o These intricate characteristics of Wittgenstein s style are related to his philosophical method. Philosophical method o Philosophy is no doctrine (theory, a structured set philosophical theses). o There are no (deductive) arguments leading to certain conclusions. No explanations. o Philosophy is an activity. What kind of activity? Philosophy is a battle against the bewitchment of our intelligence by means of language. ( 109) A philosophical problem has the form: I don t know my way about. ( 123) What is its goal? A clear grammar of our language, a clear overview of the use of our words (a perspicuous presentation, 122). (Cf. Wittgenstein said allegedly: Meaning is use. ) o As soon as the goal (the perspicuous presentation) is achieved, there will be no need for philosophy. In other words, as soon as the philosophical problem completely disappears ( 133), there is no need for philosophy. o The bewitchment is a kind of confusion or obstacle that Wittgenstein compares to an illness. o Philosophy is (analogous to) a therapy. o Philosophical theories are, at best, objects of comparison ( 131). We compare them with the actual praxis, with reality. Critique of the Augustinian conception of language o The Philosophical Investigations begin with a long quotation from Augustine s Confessions, which is subsequently summed up as: 1/6

These words, it seems to me, give us a particular picture of the essence of human language. It is this: the words in language name objects a sentences are combinations of such names. In this picture of language we find the roots of the following idea: Every word has a meaning. This meaning is correlated with the word. It is the object for which the word stands. ( 1) o Subsequently Wittgenstein (together with the reader) starts asking this theory: Are there any differences between kinds of words? His asking has the form of an example: Now think of the following use of language: I send someone shopping. I give him a slip of paper marked five red apples. He takes the slip to the shopkeeper, who opens the drawer marked apples ; then he looks up the word red in a chart and finds a colour sample next to it; then he says the series of elementary number-words I assume that he knows them by heart up to the word five, and for each number-word he takes an apple of the same colour as the sample out of the drawer. o Now the voice changes several times. Wittgenstein marks this by dashes. It is in this and similar ways that one operates with words. But how does he know where and how he is to look up the word red and what he is to do with the word five? Well, I assume that he acts as I have described. Explanations come to an end somewhere. But what is the meaning of the word five? No such thing was in question here, only how the word five is used. ( 1) o If there is any critique of Augustin s conception of language, then it is only implicit. Neither Wittgenstein, nor any of the voices claims that this conception of language is absolutely hopeless. o Any conclusion is up to the reader. o What follows: Wittgenstein introduces various extensions or improvements of this language (which are called language-games) and applies his method again and again. o Some of these games work akin the theory of names from his Tractatus. o These languages-games and their implicit conceptions of meaning are objects of comparison. Rule-following o What is alluded in the language-game from 1 is that we connect with certain words rather rules than objects. o The question is now how can we grasp a rule (that governs the use of a word)? o In particular, can we grasp a rule / the meaning of a word at a stroke? If so, then how can grasp potentially unlimited applications of this rule / uses of the word?

o What is the relations between meaning (something delimited) and use (something unlimited)? o How can I apply a certain rule / word (e.g. cube ) in a novel unforeseen situation? o The tractarian answer: We possess a method of projection (e.g. we are able to project our mental representation of a cube onto a real object). o But: The method of projection is a rule for applying other rules. Applying a rule requires another rule. o The same point can be made without invoking any mental representations: How do we grasp the rule of the series: 1 4 9 16 25? The must be a moment when I can say: Now I can go on (PI 151) It seems that I can indeed grasp this rule at a stroke when realizing that this is the series of second powers of natural numbers. o But: To understand what second power is we need a rule for it. o This is Wittgenstein s (or some of his voices ) tentative conclusion: This was our paradox: no course of action could be determined by a rule, because every course of action can be made out to accord with the rule. The answer was: if everything can be made out to accord with the rule, then it can also be made out to conflict with it. And so there would be neither accord nor conflict here. ( 201) o There must be an end in invoking additional rules. Sometimes the only possible answer is I do what I do. When I obey a rule, I do not choose. I obey it blindly. ( 219) No other interpretation is needed. o To use a rule blindly means that there is an established practice of following this rule. o Following a rule is analogous to obeying an order or following a signpost. o There must be some regularity and interpersonal harmony in obeying rules blindly, i.e. in established practices. Wittgenstein calls this harmony a form of life. Private language o What about rules governing the application of psychological concepts (i.e. concepts for sensations like pain, joy, anger, fear, love, hate)? o How do we learn these rules? By directing our attention at instances of these experiences, naming and remembering them. o But consider the following thought-experiment: o Suppose I have a new sensation worth remembering. o I write down the sign S and concentrate my attention on the sensation every time I am experiencing this sensation. But what is this ceremony for? For that is all it seems to be! A definition serves to lay down the meaning of a sign, doesn t it? Well, that is done precisely by concentrating my attention; for in this way I commit to memory the connection between the sign and the sensation. But I commit it to memory can only mean: this process brings it about that I remember the connection correctly in the future. But in the present case, I have no

criterion of correctness. One would like to say: whatever is going to seem correct to me is correct. And that only means that here we can t talk about correct. ( 258) o The structure of this argument is the same as that of rule-following: There are some instances, but nothing guarantees a future correct application in a novel situation. o Tentative conclusion (there are only tentative conclusions in Wittgenstein): This method of giving meaning doesn t work. There must be something else what guarantees future correct applications. A public practice, a form of life. But what does it mean public? o What does this argument amount to? o Refutation of the basic tenets of Descartes philosophy, of classical empiricism, of phenomenalism, of sense-date theories of perception? o It is a kind of verificationist theory of meaning? A defense of logical behaviorism? Inner and outer o If we accept Wittgenstein s conclusion of the private language argument, what would remain of philosophy of psychology? Could we speak about our inner states at all? Are we committed to behaviorism? o Behaviorism takes psychological concepts like S to mean S -behavior. o Wittgenstein insists that there is a (grammatical!) distinction between the concepts of pain and pain-behavior (or between pain and crying). I can pretend pain-behavior without actually being in pain. o The main question is: What is the nature of the connection between psychological concepts and characteristic form of behavior? o The grammar of our language can mislead us: If I have pain is meaningful, then Others have pain too? Maybe Stones have pain? Maybe numbers? o Is this an object at all that can have pain? Can my hand have pain? Or only I can have pain? o There is, however, characteristic pain-behavior which we are taught to replace by the expression pain. E.g. Stop crying and tell me where do you feel pain! o Tentative conclusion: pain is the (inner) object of crying (outward manifestation). o The following beetle in the box parable seeks to show that this is not so: Suppose everyone had a box with something in it: we call it a beetle. No one can look into anyone else s box, and everyone says he knows what a beetle is only by looking at his beetle. Here it would be quite possible for everyone to have something different in his box. One might even imagine such a thing constantly changing. But suppose the word beetle had a use in these people s language? If so it would not be used as the name of a thing. The thing in the box has no place in the language-game at all; not even as a something: for the box might even be empty. No, one can divide through by the thing in the box; it cancels out, whatever it is. ( 293) o There is a language-game with the words beetle and box. But is there any connection between the beetle and the box at all?

o There is no independent meaning of beetle apart from anything inside the box. But the pronoun anything suggests that beetle refers to a thing, to an object. Once again, the grammar of English/German can mislead us. o A positive picture: The relation between psychological concepts and characteristic behavior is akin to psych. concepts and facial expressions. E.g. I read timidity in his face ( 573) or a smiling face ( 539). These kinds of expressions are a part of our form of life. Aspect seeing o This topic comes from the second part of the Philosophical Investigations (today labeled Philosophy of Psychology A Fragment ). The form is different: There are 14 sections more less corresponding the original manuscripts. Wittgenstein didn t manage to incorporate them in the main body of the Philosophical Investigations. o How do we recognize smile/fear/timidity in a facial expression? o We can say: I see this face as smiling/frowning/threatening. o These aren t any features or properties of a face. o How can we see or recognize something as or in something else? o There is the difference between seeing something and seeing something as something else. That is: There are two uses of the word see : The one: What do you see there? I see this (and then a description, a drawing, a copy). The other: I see a likeness between these two faces. (PIF, 111) o Look at the following picture: The picture is ambiguous. It can be seen as a duck or as a rabbit. o Pay attention at the moment when you realized that the picture is ambiguous, i.e. when you see the other aspect. This is the experience of the change of aspect. But the picture is still the same. o This is a kind of paradox: The expression of a change of aspect is an expression of a new perception and, at the same time, an expression of an unchanged perception. (PIF, 130) o Wittgenstein says that what I perceive in the lighting up of an aspect is not a property of the object, but an internal relation between it and other objects. (PIF, 247) o An internal relation is a grammatical relation between two concepts (of a duck-shape and of a rabbit-shape). o The sentence I see this picture as a rabbit doesn t express any property of the picture, but rather an internal relation between the two involved concepts. Further reading o Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, The German text, with an English translation by G. E. M. Anscombe, P. M. S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte, revised 4th

edition by P. M. S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte, Wiley-Blackwell, 2009. [Use this translation/edition.] o Marie McGinn, Wittgenstein and the Philosophical Investigations, Routledge, 1997. [Good as the first introduction for students] o David Stern, Wittgenstein s Philosophical Investigations: An Introduction, Cambridge University Press, 2004. [More demanding than McGinn s introduction] o Stephen Mulhall, Wittgenstein s Private Language: Grammar, Nonsense, and Imagination in Philosophical Investigations 243 315, Oxford University Press, 2006. [An innovative, but somehow controversial reading of the private language argument]