Reviewed by Joseph Williams, University of Chicago

Similar documents
Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Instructor s Manual 1

Portfolio Project. Phil 251A Logic Fall Due: Friday, December 7

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

Human Nature & Human Diversity: Sex, Love & Parenting; Morality, Religion & Race. Course Description

Building Your Framework everydaydebate.blogspot.com by James M. Kellams

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

MPS 17 The Structure of Persuasion Logos: reasoning, reasons, good reasons not necessarily about formal logic

The SAT Essay: An Argument-Centered Strategy

Argumentative Analogy versus Figurative Analogy

Building Systematic Theology

what makes reasons sufficient?

2013 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved. 1

the negative reason existential fallacy

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Philosophy 12 Study Guide #4 Ch. 2, Sections IV.iii VI

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

RECOVERING ARGUMENT: A GUIDE TO CRITICAL THINKING AND WRITING. Richard E. Mezo

1. To arrive at the truth we have to reason correctly. 2. Logic is the study of correct reasoning. B. DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS

Logic Book Part 1! by Skylar Ruloff!

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

Logic Practice Test 1

Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000)

Video: How does understanding whether or not an argument is inductive or deductive help me?

Natural Rights, Natural Limitations 1 By Howard Schwartz

Chapter 15. Elements of Argument: Claims and Exceptions

A Brief Introduction to Key Terms

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

Logic: The Science that Evaluates Arguments

INTRODUCTION TO THINKING AT THE EDGE. By Eugene T. Gendlin, Ph.D.

Philosophical Traditions and Educational Research

Logic: A Brief Introduction. Ronald L. Hall, Stetson University

R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press

Circularity in ethotic structures

Foundations of Non-Monotonic Reasoning

The New Paradigm and Mental Models

2. Public Forum Debate seeks to encourage the development of the following skills in the debaters: d. Reasonable demeanor and style of presentation

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

1 Chapter 6 (Part 2): Assessing Truth Claims

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

LTJ 27 2 [Start of recorded material] Interviewer: From the University of Leicester in the United Kingdom. This is Glenn Fulcher with the very first

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

USING LOGOS WISELY. AP Language and Composition

The Philosopher s World Cup

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Mistaking Category Mistakes: A Response to Gilbert Ryle. Evan E. May

Sentence Starters from They Say, I Say

Take Home Exam #1. PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

1.5. Argument Forms: Proving Invalidity

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

How Will I Be Graded in This Class?

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

Overview of Today s Lecture

The Toulmin Model in Brief

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 20118/19. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

ISSA Proceedings 1998 Wilson On Circular Arguments

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

Philosophy 148 Announcements & Such. Inverse Probability and Bayes s Theorem II. Inverse Probability and Bayes s Theorem III

ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano

Coordination Problems

There are a number of writing problems that occur frequently enough to deserve special mention here:

Deccan Education Society s FERGUSSON COLLEGE, PUNE (AUTONOMOUS) SYLLABUS UNDER AUTONOMY FIRST YEAR B.A. LOGIC SEMESTER I

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

Index of Templates from They Say, I Say by Gerald Graff and Cathy Birkenstein. Introducing What They Say. Introducing Standard Views

Philosophy (PHILOS) Courses. Philosophy (PHILOS) 1

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

Ethical non-naturalism

LOGIC LECTURE #3: DEDUCTION AND INDUCTION. Source: A Concise Introduction to Logic, 11 th Ed. (Patrick Hurley, 2012)

Part II: How to Evaluate Deductive Arguments

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

Please visit our website for other great titles:

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Module 9- Inductive and Deductive Reasoning

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

Sociology 475 Classical Sociological Theory. Office: 8103 Social Science Bldng

Transcription:

Reviews The Art of Reasoning, David Kelley (New York: Norton, 1988,412 pages). Reviewed by Joseph Williams, University of Chicago Nothing is more useful than a well-written textbook that seems to layout in eminently teachable detail an account of those intellectual skills that every teacher wants to develop in his or her students. Such a book is David Kelley's The Art o/reasoning. Kelley provides an accessible and impeccable account of the principles of formal logic as they apply to classification, definition, and deductive and inductive reasoning. In Part One, he covers "Classification," "Definition," and "Propositions." In Part Two, "Arguments," he addresses "Basic Argument Analysis," "Fallacies," and "Advanced Argument Analysis." In Part Three, "Deductive Reasoning," he lays out with great clarity principles of "Categorical Propositions," "Categorical Syllogisms," "Disjunctive and Hypothetical Syllogisms," and "Syllogisms in Ordinary Reasoning." In an especially practical Part Four, "Inductive Reasoning," he devotes chapters to "Inductive Generalizations," "Argument by Analogy," "Statistical Reasoning," and "Explanation." He includes a glossary and answers to practice quizzes, which are abundant, interesting, and, unlike the ones in so many other textbooks of this kind, realistic and challenging. A particularly useful part of his exposition is a way to anatomize arguments by means of a notational device that encourages the critical reader to identify logical steps and their kind. To put it in oversimplified terms, it allows readers to distinguish multiple premises that must be taken as a set (he calls them "additive" premises) and multiple premises that are not necessarily related ("non-additive" premises). He also distinguishes between explicit premises and implicit premises and illustrates how to diagram the steps in argument and counterargument in a debate. Particularly useful are the last two chapters; one is on statistical reasoning and the other covers the differences between explanation and argument. It is in these two chapters that Kelley makes the closest connections between logical formalism and everyday reasoning, an issue that I will address at greater length in a moment. One can always quibble. For example, Kelley may obscure a useful distinction between abstract and general when he distinguishes Love as more "abstract" than Romantic Love. It might be more useful to say that "Love" refers to a concept that is not more abstract than Romantic Love, but more

184 Journal of Advanced Composition general. Elsewhere he argues that the two clauses in "Society has an obligation to support the needy because people who cannot provide for themselves have the right to the resources of the community" are logically synonymous and therefore have the logical structure "P because P" (124). If we considered for a moment the distinction between "X has a right to Y's resources" and" Y has an obligation to support X," we might decide that the two clauses are not functionally synonymous in all contexts-at least they weren't for a long time in our legal history when "an accused has a right to the legal community's resources of representation by counsel" did not entail,'the legal comm unity has an obligation to provide the accused with representation of counsel." (I understand that some would argue that the legal community was wrong.) These quibbles aside, The Art of Reasoning is a clearly written, engaging, and useful book for those who believe that one can teach thinking by teaching the formal principles that those in the philosophical tradition believe constitute good thinking. But that second quibble-an appeal to a historical con tex t to disagree with a formal principle of logic-leads us to a series of questions that go beyond the clarity of Kelley's text, because this kind of formal analysis raises some serious problems for those who take a different view of what counts as skilled thinking and how it is done. Kelley takes the view that good thinking has a universal structure (probably true) that can be taught generically (probably false). In light of the now abundant literature that explicitly questions Kelley's philosophical tradition that the structure of good thinking is in fact captured by the principles of formal logic (setting aside the question of whether it can be taught), there are three questionable assumptions that we must now recognize, if only so that those in the philosophical tradition can reject them: (1) how does language relate to whatever counts as the world?; (2) what constitutes thinking-formal processes or pragmatic schemata?; and (3) can" good thinking" be taught generically? I understand why those who write textbooks on critical thinking do not address these issues. When paradigms begin to change, the business of writing clear and unambiguous textbooks becomes very difficult. And if issues such as these cannot realistically be raised in textbooks (publishers and teachers having a low tolerance for cognitive dissonance), 1 think that they have to be raised in reviews, not to discredit a book but to provide a context in which to understand it. The first problem involves principles of classification and definition. Not to overgeneralize too much, Kelley,like most objectivist philosophers, seems to want readers to believe that there is not merely a privileged way to categorize and define words, concepts, individual referents, or classes of referents, but that things have essential attributes that are fundamental to their kind, and those essential attributes determine natural categories (19-20). As might be expected, Kelley's initial examples are from biological taxa, where for biologists the color of a creature is not essential to its kind; for biologists,

Reviews 185 what is essential is its line of descent, its ability to mate with others. But Kelley quickly proceeds to less clear-cut cases: in regard to classifying people, he says that' 'our standards for what is essential are too complex even to summarize" (21), an acknowledgment that ought to suggest that "essential" attributes may be less than entirely stable in the real and messy world of real and messy classification. He continues: Standards for what is fundamental or important vary from case to case. Identifying essential attributes may take years of research (as in science), and it always takes a good deal of thought... There is no simple, mechanical rule we can follow in distinguishing essential from nonessential principles of classification... Nevertheless, the examples... indicate the value of looking for essential attributes: they bring clarity and coherence to the organization of our knowledge. (22) That is, if we look hard enough, we will find the essential attributes that will define natural categories that constitute the structure of the world and by inference our knowledge of it. Kelley takes the same position about definition: "We do not have to settle the theoretical issue of whether concepts can-or should-have completely sharp borders. The important point is that there are degrees of precision in understanding a concept's boundaries, and definitions help us become more precise" (33). He does not suggest that if we are more precise about why we want to define things in the first place, that if we understand the end to which we will put the definition, then we will create better-that is, more useful-definitions. It is out of the activity of specific intention and general cognition that we construct definitions. We do not use definitions to define edges, nor do we see edges that delimit definitions unless we have already decided (explicitly but more often implicitly) that some one definition is going to be more useful than another. Kelley likens definitions to the search for essential criteria: "It won't always be easy to find a definition-in the case of ART. people have been trying for a long time-but even the effort to find one can clarify our understanding of a concept" (35; emphasis added). Kelley writes as if he believes that out there in the world, waiting to be found, is the definition of ART. In fact. we construct definitions to serve our ends. Is a picture of the late Mayor Harold Washington in women's underwear art? Is an American flag on the floor art? Questions like these don't get settled by aesteticians, no matter how rigorously they reason. If we adopt the objectivist approach. we find ourselves in the paradoxical situation in which we can agree that a word has an entirely acceptable meaning. even though we would never use the word to refer to a referent that meets the criteria of meaning associated with it. After much analysis, Kelley defines GAME as "a form of recreation constituted by a set of rules that specify an object to be attained and the permissible means of attaining it"

186 Journal of Advanced Composition (50). This definition describes what runners and weight lifters do, yet no native speaker of English would ever congratulate the winner of a race with "Good game!" But wait, these activities are included in the generic term Olympic games, so in that context, weight lifting must officially be a "game," even though we never use the word "game" to name the sport of weight lifting. In short, we may not assume in principle that there is some naturally given pattern to the meanings of words and their right use in regard to their range of referents. Kelley, I think, might argue that behind these inconsistencies is some ultimate epistemological consistency, if people would just get their categories and definitions straight: our problem is to correct our language to fit the world, the very objective of this book. Others would argue that categories and definitions are the products of human cognition and practice, and so to ask for natural rather than arbitrary consistency is to contradict the nature of human thought. The second problem is more abstract: is the structure of thinking best described in terms of formal logic ("if p, q," and so on) or do we think by means of pragmatic schemata deeply embedded in experience? If the former, then we ought to be puzzled why people cannot answer questions based on problem A below as consistently as they can answer a series of questions based on problem B, even though the two problems are structurally identical: (A) If a card has an "A" on one side, then it has "4" on the other. (B) If one is in the Armed Forces, then one must vote in the elections. The difference between the two problems is that the first is arbitrary, while the second is part of the familiar schema of "obligation." Patricia Cheng and her co-authors argue persuasively in "Pragmatic Versus Syntactic Approaches to Training Deductive Reasoning" that our ability to work out problems of this kind depend more on pragmatic schemata than on abstract structures of logical syntax. They also explain why training students to answer questions based on even arbitrary problems through training in "obligation" schemata is more productive than training in abstract formula (Cognitive Psychology 18 [1986]: 293-328). Now, I am not claiming that on the basis of one bit of research we should reject everything we have been doing for the last few hundred years in teaching thinking and logic. I am suggesting that the matter is less clear-cut than the best textbooks might make them seem. This brings me to the third problem, perhaps the pedagogically fatal one: after decades of teaching thinking in the way Kelley suggests-as a set of generic skills describable by the principles of formal logic-there is slight evidence (anecdotes aside) that such teaching makes students think better, and there is a great deal of evidence that it does not. Rather than go into this research in detail, I simply refer readers to the surveys in the literature, one of which is James McMillan's" Enhancing College Students' Critical Thinking: A Review of Studies', (Research in Higher Education 26.1 [1987]: 2-29). I understand how deeply those in the philosophical tradition distrust social

Reviews 187 science research, and I do not want to seem to accept that research as gospel. And to be fair, there is some evidence that in a few cases some change has been observed. But given the multitude of courses in logical thinking and the decades during which these courses have been taught, we should be able to find more evidence than we have that these courses succeed. We cannot just wish away a longstanding and widespread failure to demonstrate a connection between formal instruction in reasoning and the ability to reason well thereafter. Much of the evidence now available suggests that whatever counts as good thinking is inextricably bound up with a rich experience in a particular field. That is, good thinking depends on extensive knowledge and practice in a particular area, and that while experts do think in generically identifiable ways, what counts as skilled thinking is inextricably located in experience about the object of thinking. This dependency on experience is obvious in those sections in which Professor Kelley deals with inductive thinking. He argues-correctly-thatinductive thinking requires "enough" data on which to base an inference. In my judgment, what he does not sufficiently emphasize is that "enough" is a term wholly relative to the field and to the problem. Before suggesting that drug A cured acne with no serious side effects, a reviewer would insist on a very large number of cases-thousands, perhaps-showing a high rate of cure, more than, say, 15%, with no serious side effects. Butifit were found that after taking drug A 10% of those in the terminal stages of liver cancer recovered but went blind in one eye, and those figures were based on only 200 cases, it is fair to say that physicians would consider an apparent 10% cure rate based on 200 trials "enough" for them to make drug A available to those suffering from terminal liver cancer; or at least it would be for those physicians treating patients in the terminal stages ofliver cancer; or, in any event, it would be more than enough for those physicians who were themselves in the terminal stages of liver cancer. The point is that what counts as "enough" depends not just on a statistical formula, but on social, political, and human issues, as well. Here's a small example of a problem with Kelley's reasoning based on insufficient knowledge: Suppose you wanted to know which is the safer fonn of travel, commercial airlines or automobiles. You might compare their fatality rates. But which rate--deaths per vehicle mile, or deaths per passenger mile? Planes carry many more passengers than cars, so more people are likely to die in a single plane crash than in a single auto accident. For the same reason, though. a safe flight logs many more passenger miles than does a safe auto trip of the same distance. To compare overall safety, therefore. we should use fatalities per passenger mile. (312)

188 Journal of Advanced Composition But since most air fatalities occur just after takeoff or before landing, the critical factor in fatalities is not miles traveled but the number of takeoffs and landings. In this particular case, am I thinking about flying fifteen thousand miles a year in two 7500 mile segments? If so, I probably should fly rather than drive. Or am I thinking about flying three-thousand five mile segments? Maybe I should drive. Or maybe not. Maybe I'll die in an airplane crash, but I'll just get hurt in a car crash. Or maybe... You get the idea. Kelley's reasoning is impeccable, but it is based on insufficient knowledge. The obvious response is that good reasoning assumes sufficient knowledge, that Kelley just made a mistake in the relevant data. On the one hand, that is an entirely legitimate response. But at some point, it may be that what counts as the ability to think well is inextricably dissolved into (not intertwined with) sufficient experience. And so it makes no pragmatic sense to distinguish them. I want to be clear: Professor Kelley has written an excellent book about thinking well based on the philosophical tradition of logical analysis. But there is more than one school of thought about what it means to ' 'think well" and what it means to teach others to "think well." It is in no sense intellectually or pedagogically inappropriate to write an excellent textbook within a single tradition and not to address other schools of thought. But if to whatever degree the" Art of Thinking" in fact depends not on our finding categories and definitions but on our constructing them in ways that we and others find useful, if knowing how is inextricably bound up with knowing that, then in addition to understanding the formal principles that philosophers believe underlie good thinking, we ought to appreciate that what the thinker brings to the process of thinking may be at least as important. Politics of Letters, Richard Ohmann (Middletown: Wesleyan UP, 1987,321 pages). Reviewed by John Clifford, University of North Carolina at Wilmington In Reading Capital Louis Althusser cogently observes that only since Marx have we begun to suspect what reading and writing really mean. That, in short, is Ohmann's challenge in this collection of some twenty previously published essays: to help us re-see reading and writing in the complexity of their historical and socio-political context, to problematize the hundreds of ordinary transactions of reading and writing that make up academic life, to look deeper for' 'alignments of interest and power."