Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory of the Self Locke, The Prince and the Cobbler Reid, Of Mr. Locke's Account of Our Personal Identity

Similar documents
If the Identity of a soul alone makes the same man, and there be nothing in the nature of matter why the same individual spirit may not be united to

Locke s Essay, Book II, Chapter 27: Of Identity and Diversity

Introduction to Philosophy

Of Identity and Diversity *

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 4b Free Will/Self

A SKEPTICAL VIEW ON LOCKE S THEORY OF PERSONAL IDENTITY

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2014 Russell Marcus

Class 12 - February 25 The Soul Theory of Identity Plato, from the Phaedo

1/12. The A Paralogisms

IA Metaphysics & Mind S. Siriwardena (ss2032) 1 Personal Identity. Lecture 4 Animalism

Did Locke Defend the Memory Continuity Criterion of Personal Identity?

Thomas Reid on personal identity

To be able to define human nature and psychological egoism. To explain how our views of human nature influence our relationships with other

The self, part II: personal identity as psychological continuity

Class 11 - February 23 Leibniz, Monadology and Discourse on Metaphysics

THE PROBLEM OF PERSONAL IDENTITY

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Personal Identity and the Jehovah' s Witness View of the Resurrection

Material objects: composition & constitution

G.E. Moore A Refutation of Skepticism

Introduction to Philosophy

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

What am I? An immaterial thing: the case for dualism

IN THIS PAPER I will examine and criticize the arguments David

Reflections on the Ontological Status

St. Anselm s versions of the ontological argument

Department of Philosophy TCD. Great Philosophers. Dennett. Tom Farrell. Department of Surgical Anatomy RCSI Department of Clinical Medicine RCSI

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Trinity & contradiction

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 3 D A Y 2 : I M M A T E R I A L I S M, D U A L I S M, & T H E M I N D - B O D Y P R O B L E M

Essay Concerning Human Understanding By: John Locke

Do you have a self? Who (what) are you? PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2014

Teleological: telos ( end, goal ) What is the telos of human action? What s wrong with living for pleasure? For power and public reputation?

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Concerning theories of personal identity

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them?

Transcendental Knowledge

The Self and Other Minds

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Introduction to Philosophy

Introduction to Philosophy

Lecture 6 Objections to Dualism Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia Correspondence between Descartes Gilbert Ryle The Ghost in the Machine

George Berkeley. The Principles of Human Knowledge. Review

Early Modern Philosophy Locke and Berkeley. Lecture 3: Locke on Personal Identity

Class 18 - Against Abstract Ideas Berkeley s Principles, Introduction, (AW ); (handout) Three Dialogues, Second Dialogue (AW )

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Mind and Body. Is mental really material?"

Anna Marmodoro and Jonathan Hill (eds.), The Metaphysics of the Incarnation, Oxford University Press, 2011.

David Hume s The Self

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

In this paper I will critically discuss a theory known as conventionalism

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

Class #3 - Meinong and Mill

1/10. Descartes Laws of Nature

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte

Life, Automata and the Mind-Body Problem

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Noonan, Harold (2010) The thinking animal problem and personal pronoun revisionism. Analysis, 70 (1). pp ISSN

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick

Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument

Brad Weslake, Department of Philosophy. Darwin Day, 12 February 2012

Universals. If no: Then it seems that they could not really be similar. If yes: Then properties like redness are THINGS.

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 4 : I M M A T E R I A L I S M, D U A L I S M, & T H E M I N D - B O D Y P R O B L E M

The Nature of Personhood

GREAT PHILOSOPHERS: Thomas Reid ( ) Peter West 25/09/18

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Topic III: Sexual Morality

Either God wants to abolish evil and cannot, or he can but does not want to, or he cannot and does not want to, or lastly he can and wants to.

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 7

According to Russell, do we know the self by acquaintance? (hint: the answer is not yes )

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

Class 2 - The Ontological Argument

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

The British Empiricism

An excerpt from: Book II - Chapter XXVII of An Essay Concerning Human Understanding Of Identity and Diversity (1683) John Locke

Aquinas, Hylomorphism and the Human Soul

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Reid Against Skepticism

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Reading a Philosophy Text Philosophy 22 Fall, 2019

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

17. Tying it up: thoughts and intentionality

Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

Transcription:

Philosophy 110W: Introduction to Philosophy Spring 2012 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory of the Self Locke, The Prince and the Cobbler Reid, Of Mr. Locke's Account of Our Personal Identity I. Body and Soul We have discussed two accounts of personal identity: the body theory and the soul theory. According to the body theory, we are our bodies. The body theory is undermined by the inconstancy of material constitution. Our bodies change quickly, and thoroughly. We are all like Theseus s ship, physically, in the sense that our material constitution changes constantly even if our appearance does not. The changes to our selves are often gradual and almost imperceptible. But we might believe that there is a constant, underlying self, a haecceity which has the experiences, and undergoes the changes. In that latter case, the body theory has no plausibility. The soul theory, at which Descartes hinted, and which we saw explicitly in Plato s Phaedo, claims that we are essentially thinking things, our souls. I mentioned that Plato ascribed different properties to the soul than Descartes did. But according to any version of the soul theory, the self is an immaterial substance, a thing completely distinct from our bodies. There are two sorts of objections to the soul theory. The first sort of objection denies that there are souls distinct from bodies. This (usually-materialist) response argues that the soul theory must be false since there are no souls. One argument for the first kind of response relies on a problem of interaction between the body and the soul. We will discuss this problem in more depth after break, when we look at the philosophy of mind. Briefly, the problem is that if the soul is immaterial, it seems impossible for it to interact with the body in the way that our minds and our bodies do relate. For Plato, the problem of interaction is not a serious problem, since he denies that the world of bodies is a real world. I have been trying to put aside questions of skepticism about the material world. Descartes may be interpreted as trying to solve the problem of interaction by claiming that the self is an amalgam of mind and body. He even locates the soul in the pineal gland. But, that just pushes the problem back. A soul, in Descartes s sense, is non-physical and so can not be located anywhere. The second sort of objection to the soul theory of self, which we see in Locke s work, does not oppose the existence of souls. Locke points out that the defender of the soul theory is committed to the independence of bodies and souls. Thus, the body in which the soul is placed is inconsequential. The same soul could be put into two bodies.

Philosophy 110W: Introduction to Philosophy, Prof. Marcus; Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory, page 2 If the identity of soul alone makes the same man, and there be nothing in the nature of matter why the same individual spirit may not be united to different bodies, it will be possible that those men, living in distant ages, and of different tempers, may have been the same man: which way of speaking must be from a very strange use of the word man, applied to an idea out of which body and shape are exclude[d]... (Locke 340) Imagine that a soul had two different incarnations. We wouldn t say that there were only one person. Here is Locke, in a section you did not read, providing an example. Suppose it to be the same soul that was in Nestor or Thersites at the siege of Troy...which it may have been, as well as it is now the soul of any other man. But he now having no consciousness of any of the actions of either of Nestor or Thersites, does or can he conceive himself the same person with either of them? Can he be concerned in either of their actions, attribute them to himself, or think them his own more than the actions of any other men that ever existed? Thus, this consciousness not reaching to any of the actions of either of those men, he is no more one self with either of them than if the soul or immaterial spirit that now informs him had been created and began to exist, when it began to inform his present body... (Locke, Essay II.XXVII.14). The soul is not identical to the self, Locke says, since there can be more than one self using the same soul. Moreover, Locke argues that the problem works in the other direction, too. Locke believes that it is possible for the same self to be transferred between souls, as we will see when we get to Locke s positive account of the self. So, we can distinguish between two different types of objections to the soul theory, one which accepts the existence of souls and one which rejects them. On either objection, the soul theory of self meets counter-intuitive consequences. To avoid these unfortunate consequences, Locke provides a different account of self, which we can call the consciousness theory. Locke s account is both controversial and revolutionary. II. Identity and Sortals Locke s account of personal identity is important for two reasons. Neither of those reasons is that it is clear and well-written. Locke s work is turgid and often nearly incomprehensible. To be fair, Locke himself recognized the problem. Still, it doesn t make his work any easier to read. One of Locke s lasting contributions to the literature on personal identity is his observation that identity generally is relative to a sortal, to a kind of thing. We must consider what is meant by Socrates, or the same individual man. First, it must be either the same individual, immaterial, thinking substance; in short the same numerical soul, and nothing else. Secondly, or the same animal, without any regard to an immaterial soul. Thirdly, or the same immaterial spirit united to the same animal (Locke 343).

Philosophy 110W: Introduction to Philosophy, Prof. Marcus; Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory, page 3 Let s say that my daughter re-forms her plasticine sculpture of a horse into the shape of a house. The lump of plasticine is the same lump but it is a different statue. The ship of Theseus may be the same ship while being a different material object. We can not know how to identify something unless we know what kind of thing it is. The same mass of matter may be a different statue while being the same toy. So, we can not know what our identity is until we know what kind of thing we are. We might, for example, think that we are a biological kind of thing. Locke takes man to refer to a type of animal, like human being. The idea in our minds, of which the sound man in our mouths is the sign, is nothing else but of an animal of such a certain form (Locke 341a). An animal is not merely its matter. The matter remains after the animal s death while the animal itself does not. The principles of identity of the sort man are biological. The identity of a man is determined functionally, by its organization and not by its matter. Note that a body theorist of the self could make this kind of appeal to a biological sortal. The body theorist could say that we are men, material objects with a certain sort of functional organization. But, according to Locke, the sort man can not serve as the sort of our selves. A man is identified by the functional organization of the body; it is a biological thing. But, person and self are forensic, or moral, terms used for practical purposes of ascribing responsibility. One can see an argument for the distinction between (biological) humans and (moral) persons clearly when we consider the question of whether aliens, or sentient machines, could be persons. There could be aliens or robots with very different biology, even mere artifacts, which nevertheless are persons. Since such cases are possible, our personhood must not be identical with our biology. In addition, Locke s account arises in part from the worry, raised by Robert Boyle, about the resurrection of bodies in the presence of cannibals. Imagine that some portion of one person s body is eaten by another person, and so becomes part of both of them. It is a puzzle to determine into whose body that portion of matter is supposed to go at the resurrection, when souls are supposed to be reunited with their bodies. Does it go with the eaten person or with the cannibal? I m not sure how much Locke s rejection of the body theory and his claim that man is the proper sortal for personal identity are responses to Boyle s worry. But Boyle s puzzle seems to have had some influence on Locke. We are looking for a criterion for identity for personhood: what makes us the same people over time. It s not sameness of body. It s not sameness of soul.

Philosophy 110W: Introduction to Philosophy, Prof. Marcus; Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory, page 4 III. The Consciousness Theory For Locke, what makes the same person over time, is consciousness, and, especially, connection through memory, which Locke calls consciousness extending backwards. Locke s view is sometimes labeled the psychological continuity theory, and sometimes the memory theory. I ll call it the consciousness theory. [A person] is a thinking intelligent being, that has reason and reflection, and can consider itself as itself, the same thinking thing in different times and places; which it does only by that consciousness which is inseparable from thinking, and, as it seems to me, essential to it... (Locke 341a). Locke argues for the consciousness theory from premises similar to those that Descartes invoked for the soul theory. In thinking about ourselves, we think about our thoughts. For Descartes, consciousness is the essential characteristic of mental life, and what distinguishes us from (other) animals. Locke denies Descartes s conclusion that we are our souls. But, he maintains an emphasis on conscious thought. Since consciousness always accompanies thinking, and it is that which makes every one to be what he calls self, and thereby distinguishes himself from all other thinking things, in this alone consists personal identity (Locke 341a). Locke s view is called the psychological-continuity theory because of its claim that continued consciousness is a mark of sameness of self. We know of continued consciousness through memory. So, memory is also essential to the criteria for identifying ourselves over time. For as far as any intelligent being can repeat the idea of any past action with the same consciousness it had of it at first, and with the same consciousness it has of any present action; so far it is the same personal self (Locke 341b). Locke s argument for the consciousness theory also invokes a series of thought experiments. He considers a prince who transfers his consciousness to a cobbler. Though he inhabits a different human being, Locke argues, it is the same prince in the pauper s body. Reid disagrees. This doctrine has some strange consequences...such as, that if the same consciousness can be transferred from one intelligent being to another, which he thinks we cannot show to be impossible, then two or twenty intelligent beings may be the same person (Reid 347a). Reid and Locke are here trading intuitions. Locke sees no contradiction in one person instantiated variously. Reid finds the view absurd. My intuitions favor Locke s account. But, they shouldn t be taken as decisive. Ask yourself what you think about the case.

Philosophy 110W: Introduction to Philosophy, Prof. Marcus; Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory, page 5 Locke also considers a case of a day and night man. Consider a single man who has one consciousness in the day and one in the night, like Jekyll and Hyde. In this case, Locke says, we are tempted to say that there are two people in one biological man. Locke s solution to the problem of personal identity helps explain his objection to the soul theory. The soul theory posits that sameness of soul, taken as a substance, suffices for sameness of person. Locke considers a case in which consciousness varies but substance remains. He is taking the soul to be a conduit for thought and imagining that different consciousnesses (especially memories) are placed in the same container soul. If the soul theory were correct, then we should have the same person no matter what memories and thoughts are in the one soul. But, Locke says that multiple sets of memories seem to yield multiple different people, and so the soul theory is wrong. If the same consciousness...can be transferred from one thinking substance to another, it will be possible that two thinking substances may make but one person. For the same consciousness being preserved, whether in the same or different substances, the personal identity is preserved (Locke, Essay II.XXVII.13). IV. Reid Against Locke Locke s account of the self relies on continued consciousness. We know that we are the same person who had a certain earlier experience when we can recall, using memory, that experience. Memory is essential to connecting our consciousness. Reid worries about Locke s blurring the difference between memory and consciousness. Locke discusses memory as if it is consciousness of a past experience. Reid notes that there is a difference between remembering an experience and having consciousness of that experience. When, therefore, Mr. Locke s notion of personal identity is properly expressed, it is, that personal identity consists in distinct remembrance; for, even in the popular sense, to say that I am conscious of a past action means nothing else than that I distinctly remember that I did it (Reid 347b). Even Reid notes that this objection is not a serious one; it s just an unfortunate use of language which seems to have no effect on the theory of self. The more serious concern, as Locke himself points out, is that there are gaps in both our conscious experience and in our memory. Every time we sleep, we lose consciousness. Some experiences are forgotten. Two things can only be identical if they have all the same properties. If my self ends with the cessation of conscious experience, when I go to sleep, and then begins again in the morning, it seems as if I should have many different selves. While any being continues to exist, it is the same being; but two beings which have a different beginning or a different ending of their existence cannot possibly be the same (Reid 346a).

Philosophy 110W: Introduction to Philosophy, Prof. Marcus; Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory, page 6 If consciousness and psychological continuity are required for personal identity, then every time we sleep or lose a memory, we lose our identity. If the intelligent being may lose the consciousness of the actions done by him, which surely is possible, then he is not the person that did those actions; so that one intelligent being may be two or twenty different persons, if he shall so often lose the consciousness of his former actions (Reid 347a). Reid s worry is perhaps better expressed in the problem of the old general. The old general remembers being a middle-aged officer. The middle-aged officer remembers an experience from his childhood, being flogged for robbing an orchard. But, the old general does not remember being flogged. According to the transitive property of identity, the old general is surely the same person as the child. But according to Locke s theory, it seems, the old general is not the same person as the child. The old general cannot remember being flogged as a child. The general s consciousness does not reach so far back as his flogging; therefore, according to Mr. Locke s doctrine, he is not the person who was flogged. Therefore the general is, and at the same time is not, the same person with him who was flogged at school (Reid 347a). Reid has thus derived a contradiction from Locke s theory. The problem expands, since our consciousness is not a constant, but a stream of changing experiences. Our consciousness, our memory, and every operation of the mind, are still flowing like the water of a river, or like time itself (Reid 348a). Since our conscious experiences change constantly, it looks like Locke s theory entails that we are constantly changing, too. Reid s worry about these oddities may not be decisive against Locke. They point out some counterintuitive consequences of the consciousness theory, and in the case of the contradiction force Locke to restate some of his claims. But perhaps our conscious experience, ever flowing, does not support any kind of sameness of an individual over time. Reid suggests that Locke assert that we are the same kind of individual, rather than the same individual, over time. Even Reid s strongest words about these related problems do not show that he took them as refuting Locke. Is it not strange that the sameness or identity of a person should consist in a thing which is continually changing, and is not any two minutes the same (348a)? Most philosophical views have some strange consequences. The question is whether their virtues outweigh their oddities.

Philosophy 110W: Introduction to Philosophy, Prof. Marcus; Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory, page 7 V. Reid on Evidence Lastly, Reid has a more-significant complaint about Locke s theory. He claims that Locke confuses personal identity with evidence for personal identity. My memories of an experience are evidence that I had that experience. My consciousness of an experience is evidence that I am having an experience. But, my identity is not my memory or my consciousness. It is to attribute to memory or consciousness a strange magical power of producing its object, though that object must have existed before the memory or consciousness which produced it (Reid, 347b) Reid illustrates the formal problem, which is a general one, using the example of a stolen horse. The owner of a stolen horse, when presented with a horse which might be the stolen one, will use its similarity to the original to determine if the two horses are the same. The similarity of the original horse and the present one is evidence that the two horses are the same. But would it not be ridiculous from this to infer that the identity of a horse consists in similitude only (Reid 348a)? To put Reid s point in some philosophical jargon, he is accusing Locke of arguing from epistemological premises to metaphysical conclusions. We discover, says Reid, that we are the same over time by using memory and consciousness. But we should not confuse the way we learn about something with the thing itself. We use memory and consciousness to identify our selves, but our selves are not merely continued consciousness or memory. A more complete discussion of the lessons that Reid takes from the considerations of evidence will have to wait until next class, when we look at Reid s positive account of personal identity, which we might call a non-reductive, or primitive, theory of the self.