Repentance, Constitutionalism, and Sacrality

Similar documents
Is the Constitutional Concern with Religious Involvement in the Public Square Hostility?

What Kind of Freedom Does Religion Need?

Individual Conscience and the Law

Jefferson, Church and State By ReadWorks

God Loveth Adverbs. DePaul Law Review. Daniel O. Conkle

THE CONSTITUTIONAL REQUIREMENT OF SENSITIVITY TO RELIGION. Richard A. Hesse*

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

FAITH BEFORE THE COURT: THE AMISH AND EDUCATION. Jacob Koniak

Conscientious Objectors--Religious Training and Belief--New Test [Umted States v'. Seeger, 380 U.S. 163 (1965) ]

AMERICAN CENTER FOR LAW AND JUSTICE S MEMORANDUM OF LAW REGARDING THE CRIMINAL TRIAL OF ABDUL RAHMAN FOR CONVERTING FROM ISLAM TO CHRISTIANITY

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE

John Locke. compelling governmental interest approach to regulate. religious conduct, and I will discuss the law further below.

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

The Question of Democracy

Religious Freedom: Our First Freedom

denarius (a days wages)

SEPARATION OF CHURCH AND STATE: HISTORICAL FACT AND CURRENT FICTION. By Robert L. Cord. New York: Lambeth Press Pp. xv, 302. $16.95.

In Brief: Supreme Court Revisits Legislative Prayer in Town of Greece v. Galloway

1. Were the Founding Fathers mostly agnostics, deists, and secularists?

The American Sabbath Union and Human Rights

History of Religious Liberty in America By Charles Haynes

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

PROVOCATION EVERYONE IS A PHILOSOPHER! T.M. Scanlon

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism

The Churches and the Public Schools at the Close of the Twentieth Century

What God Could Have Made

Lifelong Learning Is a Moral Imperative

The Pledge of Allegiance and the Establishment Clause of the First Amendment: Why Vishnu and Jesus Aren't In the Constitution

It Matters What We Believe UUFR UU Fellowship of Raleigh July 22, 2012 Rev. John L. Saxon

Review of J.L. Schellenberg, Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason (Ithaca, NY: Cornell UP, 1993), i-x, 219 pages.

Exploring Concepts of Liberty in Islam

Mormonism as an Ecclesiology and System of Relatedness

AN AMERICAN PERSPECTIVE

THE WELCOME OF THE WEST END BAPTIST CHURCH OF NEWPORT, TENNESSEE

GDI Anthology Envisioning a Global Ethic

LIBERTY: RETHINKING AN IMPERILED IDEAL. By Glenn Tinder. William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company Pp. xiv, 407. $ ISBN: X.

Declaration and Constitution: 18 th Century America

Paradoxes of religious freedom in Egypt

90 South Cascade Avenue, Suite 1500, Colorado Springs, Colorado Telephone: Fax:

5_circ-insegn-relig_en.

Whether. AMERICA WINTHROP JEFFERSON, AND LINCOLN (2007). 2 See ALLEN C. GUELZO, ABRAHAM LINCOLN: REDEEMER PRESIDENT (1999).

ETHICAL POSITIONS STATEMENT

Informalizing Formal Logic

Paradox and the Calling of the Christian Scholar

II. THE SACRAMENT OF PENANCE THE SOCIAL ASPECT OF THE SACRAMENT OF PENANCE

Catholic University of Milan MASTER INTERCULTURAL SKILLS Fourteenth Edition a.y. 2017/18 Cavenaghi Virginia

AN EVANGELICAL MANIFESTO

The Integrity of Survival: A Mormon Response to Stanley Hauerwas

Queries and Advices. 1. Meeting for Worship. First Section: What is the state of our meetings for worship and business?

Good morning, and welcome to America s Fabric, a radio program to. encourage love of America. I m your host for America s Fabric, John McElroy.

LOS ANGELES UNIFIED SCHOOL DISTRICT Policy Bulletin

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid?

A RESPONSE TO CHARLES DAVIS

They said WHAT!? A brief analysis of the Supreme Court of Canada s decision in S.L. v. Commission Scolaire des Chênes (2012 SCC 7)

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

The Role of Faith in the Progressive Movement. Part Six of the Progressive Tradition Series. Marta Cook and John Halpin October 2010

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

A Wall of Separation - Agostini v. Felton (1997)

Against Christianity Peter J. Leithart (Canon Press, 2003) Week 1: Preface and Chapter 1 Against Christianity

THE DIALOGUE DECALOGUE: GROUND RULES FOR INTER-RELIGIOUS, INTER-IDEOLOGICAL DIALOGUE

SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

Bill of Rights. The United States Bill of Rights of 1791, or more specifically the First Amendment, transformed

COMITÉ SUR LES AFFAIRES RELIGIEUSES A NEW APPROACH TO RELIGIOUS EDUCATION IN SCHOOL: A CHOICE REGARDING TODAY S CHALLENGES

Motion from the Right Relationship Monitoring Committee for the UUA Board of Trustees meeting January 2012

The Sources of Religious Freedom: Dignitatis Humanae and American Experience

Student Number: Programme of Study: MSc Nationalism & Ethnic Conflict. Module Code/ Title of Module: Nationalism & Ethno-Religious Conflict

Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views

A CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS OF SECULARISM AND ITS LEGITIMACY IN THE CONSTITUTIONAL DEMOCRATIC STATE

Julia M. Speller Course Syllabus

Jean Jacques Rousseau The Social Contract, or Principles of Political Right (1762)

FURTHER REFLECTIONS ON THE ROLE OF RELIGION IN LAWYERING AND IN LIFE

MULTICULTURALISM AND FUNDAMENTALISM. Multiculturalism

Uganda, morality was derived from God and the adult members were regarded as teachers of religion. God remained the canon against which the moral

A CRITICAL INTRODUCTION TO RELIGION IN THE AMERICAS

Societies Requiring No Belief in God Allowed to Share in Religious Tax Exemptions

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

Building Systematic Theology

Religion s Role in Education: A Paper discussing the changing And yet enduring role religion plays In America s System of Public Education.

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Gilbert. Margaret. Scientists Are People Too: Comment on Andersen. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 5 (2017):

15 Does God have a Nature?

GOV 312 P: Constitutional Principles: Core Texts Spring 2018 Unique Number: CLA 0128: Monday, Wednesday, Friday 2:00-3:00 pm

Individualism, Equality, and Rights: Reactions to Jackson, Priest, And Katz

Fact vs. Fiction. Setting the Record Straight on the BSA Adult Leadership Standards

Mill and Bentham both endorse the harm principle. Utilitarians, they both rest

Sidgwick on Practical Reason

MANY MINISTERS OR ONE, UNIQUE MINISTER OF THE AGE? W. Nee vs. the Blended Co-workers

1/12. The A Paralogisms

A RESPONSE TO "THE MEANING AND CHARACTERISTICS OF AN AMERICAN THEOLOGY"

Interfaith Marriage: A Moral Problem for Jews, Christians and Muslims. Muslim Response by Professor Jerusha Tanner Lamptey, Ph.D.

OUR LORD JESUS CHRIST, KING OF THE UNIVERSE (C) MEANING OF SEPARATION OF CHURCH AND STATE

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

JUDICIAL OPINION WRITING

We recommend you cite the published version. The publisher s URL is:

New Federal Initiatives Project

THE RE-VITALISATION of the doctrine

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

EXERCISING OUR CHRISTIAN BELIEFS THROUGH POLICIES AND PRACTICES: CAN WE STILL DO THAT?

School Prayer and the Establishment of Religion: A Look at Engel v. Vitale

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Transcription:

DePaul Law Review Volume 42 Issue 1 Fall 1992: Symposium - Confronting the Wall of Separation: A New Dialogue Between Law and Religion on the Meaning of the First Amendment Article 4 Repentance, Constitutionalism, and Sacrality Douglas Sturm Follow this and additional works at: http://via.library.depaul.edu/law-review Recommended Citation Douglas Sturm, Repentance, Constitutionalism, and Sacrality, 42 DePaul L. Rev. 61 (1992) Available at: http://via.library.depaul.edu/law-review/vol42/iss1/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Law at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in DePaul Law Review by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact mbernal2@depaul.edu, MHESS8@depaul.edu.

REPENTANCE, CONSTITUTIONALISM, AND SACRALITY Douglas Sturm* Let me begin by expressing deep thanks to James Washington for his provocative essay. 1 He has adopted an original tack on the topic of this panel, namely, "An Historical Perspective of Religion's Views of the Law of Church and State." His focus on the meaning of conscience and the manner in which freedom of conscience constitutes a central political and religious question in the modern age is refreshing. As intended, his remarks are suggestive and bristle with multiple possibilities and problems. I am particularly drawn to his constructive suggestion that within our contemporary cultural milieu, conscience be reinterpreted for constitutional purposes as "adherence to the sanctity of the body." ' He further suggests that as a consequence of that reinterpretation, the First Amendment be construed as providing protection of the bodily integrity of all citizens, indeed all persons, if not all kinds and conditions of life, as a "primal natural right." ' As he is surely aware, that consequence may be construed, as a Karl Llewellyn would remind us, either narrowly or broadly.' Given Washington's reference to the Native American belief in the sacredness of the land and how that belief bears on the practice and theory of ownership, 5 I suspect he would want that reinterpretation construed most broadly. I have organized my remarks on the topic of "An Historical Perspective of Religion's Views of Law of Church and State" around three themes: repentance, constitutionalism, and sacrality. While these remarks are not in direct and explicit response to Washington's statement, they do bear on his concerns. In substance, the * Professor of Religion and Political Science, Bucknell University. This Essay is a revised version of comments presented on December 6 and 7, 1991, at the Conference on the Bicentennial of the Bill of Rights sponsored by the Center for Church/State Studies, DePaul University College of Law. 1. James M. Washington, The Crisis in the Sanctity of Conscience in American Jurisprudence, 42 DEPAUL L. REV. 11 (1992). 2. Id. at 24. 3. Id. 4. See KARL LLEWELLYN, JURISPRUDENCE (1962); KARL LLEWELLYN, BRAMBLE BUSH (1960). 5. Washington, supra note 1, at 24 n.53.

DEPA UL LA W RE VIE W [Vol. 42:61 three themes overlap, but I distinguish them for ease of organization and presentation. REPENTANCE At this conference, we are commemorating the day on which the final ratification of the American Bill of Rights was announced, December 15, 1791. But, lest we romanticize that moment and its significance, I remind you that the Bill of Rights was born of political compromise. It was the result of a rough and tumble political struggle to establish a new constitution and became, upon ratification, an integral part of that constitution. That constitution, and more inclusively, this nation, were founded in conquest. To be blunt, the Constitution, with its preamble about justice, the general welfare, and the blessing of liberty, was a pack of lies. When we reflect on the origins of this nation, we must, if we are honest, give full acknowledgement to this fact and we should, if we are at all sensitive to its implications, be driven to repentance. On a personal level, I confess that since my college days - when the dark side of American history became evident to me - I have never been a comfortable citizen of this country. Howeyer, in many respects, I love it dearly - including many aspects and aspirations of its constitutional statement. It is so easy to neglect the sheer viciousness of our corporate history. We forget, to our detriment, that this nation was born in violence, both direct and indirect - through the massacre of thousands upon thousands of Native Americans, through the exploitation and erosion of the earth, through the enslavement of thousands upon thousands of Africans, and through the deliberate suppression of one-half of the population of people who settled on the land (i.e., women). As we are told, during this time of presumed celebration, that the Bill of Rights is a prototypical charter of liberty, we must remember that the liberty promised therein was at best a half-truth, that many of the people who lived on this land were deliberately, even forcibly, excluded from the privileges and immunities declared in that document. This remains true, sad to say, even today. If I understand correctly, James Washington - given his references and allusions - would agree with me. He proposes, through his tendentious, but tantalizing, extension of the religion clauses, to embrace conscience understood as "adherence to the sanctity of the body," the rectifica-

19921 REPENTANCE AND CONSTITUTIONALISM tion of this wrong." In short, what he proposes would entail a development from deep repentance to radical reformation. Let us, he suggests, at long last take with eminent seriousness the religion clauses as signifying respect for the sanctity of all life in its material and corporate embodiment. He would, out of a religious sensibility, press the judicial community to repudiate the hypocrisies of our national and constitutional past and to take the First Amendment religion clauses with utmost seriousness to their furthest implications. CONSTITUTIONALISM Charles Howard McIlwain, throughout his extensive studies of Western political thought, suggests that the minimal meaning of constitutionalism is "limited government. " ' 7 The tradition of constitutionalism emerged from the idea that governments, by virtue of their proper purposes as well as their temptations, must be circumscribed. They must be bounded. We must therefore define with some care the arenas of our life into which governments must not be permitted to intrude even as we define what role governments properly fulfill in our common life. As an historian, McIlwain was keenly aware that over the course of centuries, the precise character of the limits to governmental action was a source of constant debate and was susceptible to alteration and change. Without neglecting the hypocrisy of the Bill of Rights' promises at the time it was ratified and throughout subsequent centuries, we may nonetheless conceive of it at its best (together with its historical counterpart, the French Declaration of the Rights of Citizen and Man [sic]) as a milestone in the history of constitutionalism. These proclaimed rights constitute a set of liberties, immunities,' and privileges that citizens possess and that may not be - except for compelling reasons, ultimately grounded in those rights themselves - modified or denied by governmental powers. They constitute a boundary for governmental action. It is significant - even if only, in a sense, an accident of history - that the first of the rights stated in the Bill of Rights as ratified has to do with religion. The placement is fitting, given the significance of religion in our human history. Yet therein lies an extraordinarily difficult conceptual problem with both theoretical and practi- 6. Id. at 26. 7. CHARLES HOWARD MCILWAIN. CONSTITUTIONALISM: ANCIENT AND MODERN (1947).

DEPAUL LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:61 cal import: What is the meaning of religion? How are we to construe what sorts of understandings and practices are embraced by the notion of religion? That has long been a puzzle in religious studies and has been a puzzle in judicial decisions as well. As Washington has noted, for some time in the West and in this nation, we assumed that belief in some sort of supreme being - a God - resides at the heart of religion. 8 In conscientious objector cases, for instance, those seeking an exemption from the armed services on grounds of conscience were required to respond to the question: "Do you believe in a supreme being?" 9 A negative answer was sufficient to deny the application.' However, the Supreme Court's approach to such cases took a radical turn in the cases of Welsh v. United States" and United States v. Seeger. 2 When confronted with conscientious objectors to participation in the armed services who, by their own declaration, were not theists, the Supreme Court, drawing upon language from Paul Tillich, adopted a "functional equivalency" test.'" Belief in God as such was not deemed essential to religion, at least for purposes of this line of cases. Moreover, in the academic study of religion, we encounter a wide range of diverse definitions of religion, many of which are intentionally not limited to theism. Paul Tillich stresses the notion of ultimacy;' 4 John Hick, the notion of transcendence;' 5 Mircea Eliade, the notion of sacrality; 16 and Franklin Gamwell, the notion of comprehensive purpose.' 7 All these notions are presented as efforts to embrace a vast plurality of philosophies, visions, and practices that we would want to call, in some vital sense, "religious" whether or not they are, in a strict sense, theistic - such as Confucianism, Buddhism, Islam, Judaism, or Christianity. 8. Washington, supra note 1, at 45-49. 9. See Douglas Sturm, Constitutionalism and Conscientiousness: The Dignity of Objection to Military Service, I J. & RELIGION 265, 268-69 (1983). 10. Id. 11. 398 U.S. 333 (1970). 12. 380 U.S. 163 (1965). 13. Welsh, 398 U.S. at 339-40; Seeger, 380 U.S. at 180. 14. PAUL TILLICH, DYNAMICS OF FAITH (1958). 15. JOHN HICK, AN INTERPRETATION OF RELIGION: HUMAN RESPONSES TO THE TRANSCEN- DENT (1989). 16. MIRCEA ELIADE, THE SACRED AND PROFANE: THE NATURE OF RELIGION (Willard R. Trask trans., Harcourt 1957). 17. FRANKLIN I. GAMWELL, BEYOND PREFERENCE 69-89 (1984). See also FRANKLIN 1. GAMWELL, THE DIVINE GOOD: MODERN MORAL THEORY AND THE NECESSITY OF GOD 168 (1990).

1992] REPENTANCE AND CONSTITUTIONALISM However, defined more specifically, it seems to me that all these efforts to construe the meaning of religion affirm something along the following lines, namely, that there is a dimension of reality after which the human spirit reaches as integral to its own enhancement which transcends the ordinary and the everyday. In that dimension, the spirit bloweth as it listeth. In a certain sense, even if we wanted to use coercive means in that dimension, the attempt would be futile precisely because the spirit bloweth as it listeth. The human spirit will break through all artificially induced boundaries because of its obsession with the search for ultimate meanings, for transcendent realities, for comprehensive purposes. More importantly, governments, given their proper functions, have no business even trying to define, to direct, to dictate what people think and feel, envision, and enact in that dimension because, in the final analysis, governments are meant to serve the human spirit, not vice versa. What I have affirmed as the impetus and character of religious dimension of human life corresponds, I believe, with James Washington's approach to a redefinition of conscience, even including the modifications suggested by Cole Durham. 18 Conscience, as I would phrase it in this context, is the human yearning for and apprehension of that which is, to the self, the dimension of ultimacy, transcendence, comprehensive purpose. It is the apprehension of that which will not let one go, of that which leads one hither and yon, of that with which one is obsessed, of that which constitutes one's most fundamental identity, of that whose character permeates in some measure all one does and all one is. Conscience is the point at which, as a matter of both judgment and fulfillment, there is a conjunction between one's individual reality and that deeper or, if you will, higher reality whose presence is the Alpha and Omega, the beginning and the end, of our being. In the religious dimension so understood, coercion is, in a sense, contradictory. In theistic terms, coercion in religious matters deprives God of God's sovereignty. In nontheistic terms, coercion in religious matters deprives the human spirit of its liberation and fulfillment. Governments not only ought to withhold their coercive powers from encroaching upon that dimension; they ought to manifest a decent respect for that dimension. That is the genius of the religion clauses from a religious perspective and is a way of getting 18. W. Cole Durham, Jr., Religious Liberty and the Call of Conscience, 42 DEPAUL L. REV. 71 (1992).

DEPAUL LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:61 at James Washington's primary constructive thesis. Washington, if I understand the import of his statement, focuses on freedom of conscience as the centerpoint of church-state issues in this country. He proposes as a redefinition of conscience "adherence to the sanctity of the body.'"'" I take his reference to "body" to assert that the burden and import of conscience are not exhausted in belief alone. Freedom of conscience extends beyond freedom of belief. Contrary to Thomas Jefferson's beliefs," 0 conscience, by virtue of its character, pertains as well to social practice and institutionalized forms of interaction. Therefore, a respect for bodily integrity - and hence for associational autonomy and cultural diversity - is part and parcel, though not the sum total, of a respect for freedom of conscience. That, I assume, is part of the implication of Washington's haunting query, posed at the conclusion of his statement, "Who constrains nation-states that turn national interests into a fetish even to the point of destroying human life and cultural diversity?" 21 As the institution of slavery demonstrates so starkly, to degrade the body is to degrade the spirit, to constrain free interaction is to shackle the conscience, to stifle diversity in forms of life is to smother the principle of life itself. SACRALITY As a bridge to this theme, let me assert that in my understanding, constitutionalism properly construed does not put a premium on orderliness. Rather it institutionalizes tension. Constitutionalism, by virtue of its respect for liberty, especially liberty in that deeper, more ultimate dimension of reality about which I have spoken, entails an acknowledgement that life in the human community is never peaceful and quiet. It cannot be and should not be expected to be so. It is always in conflict and turmoil. Constitutionalism means that in our common life, we must so or- 19. Washington, supra note 1, at 24. 20. See ARLIN M. ADAMS & CHARLES J. EMMERICH, A NATION DEDICATED TO RELIGIOUS LIBERTY: THE CONSTITUTIONAL HERITAGE OF THE RELIGION CLAUSES 112 (1990) (quoting Thomas Jefferson, Reply to the Danbury Baptist Association (Jan. 1, 1802), in 8 THE WRITINGS OF THOMAS JEFFERSON 113-14 (H. Washington ed., 1853)). Significantly, Chief Justice Morrison Waite, in the first of the Mormon cases, construed Jefferson's doctrine of separation of church and state, as stated in his response to the Danbury Baptists, as supporting a radical distinction between belief and action in interpreting the Free Exercise Clause: "Congress was deprived of all legislative power over mere opinion, but was left free to reach actions which were in violation of social duties or subversive of good or'der." Reynolds v. United States, 98 U.S. 145, 164 (1878). 21. Washington, supra note 1, at 60.

19921 REPENTANCE AND CONSTITUTIONALISM ganize ourselves to sustain that conflict and turmoil - but to do so in such a way that we stretch ourselves, not narrow ourselves; that we broaden the possibilities for life, not constrict them; that we celebrate plurality, not drive toward conformity and uniformity. At the same time, constitutionalism, in a seeming paradox, means that there are boundary lines of a sort. They, however, are only boundary lines resisting parochialism and provincialism. That is, we must resist movements that tend to constrict and constrain the human spirit (e.g., the destructive tactics of the Ku Klux Klan), not movements whose purposes are to open up new possibilities of thought and action (e.g., the ritual practices of the Native American Church). As Cole Durham hinted in his preceding comments, 2 we confront the question of who properly draws the line. In a recent issue of The Journal of Law and Religion, a set of articles derived from a Georgetown symposium on church and state addressed that question." Stephen Pepper and William Marshall, in their articles, took a traditional route of asserting that the state, with its concern for public order, has the authority and duty to draw the line. 4 But given the meaning of sacrality, I would take the side of John Howard Yoder who, in his response, rejected that assertion." According to Yoder's interpretation, Pepper and Marshall were proposing that government, given its purposes, has the authority to define a special space for religion and should confine religion to that space." Yoder, in reaction, reversed the equation. Affirming the supremacy of sacrality, Yoder stated, in effect, that sacrality has the authority to define a special space for government, not the other way around! From a religious perspective, government is subordinate to the higher reaches of the human spirit and must accommodate those higher reaches. Religious liberty and its corollary, religious tolerance, are not a privilege granted by political authority; they constitute a right grounded in the religious dimension. Sacrality is supreme. 22. Durham, supra note 18. 23. See Georgetown Symposium on Church and State and Society and Law Colloquium, 7 J.L. & RELIGION 257 (1989). 24. Stephen Pepper, A Brief for the Free Exercise Clause, 7 J.L. & RELIGION 323, 354-55 (1989); William P. Marshall, The Case Against the Constitutionally Compelled Free Exercise Exemption, 40 CASE W. RES. L. REV. 357 (1989-90), reprinted in 7 J.L. & RELIGION 363, 401-03 (1989). 25. John H. Yoder, Response of an Amateur Historian and a Religious Citizen, 7 J.L. & RELIGION 415, 415-16 (1989). 26. Id. at 418.

DEPA UL LA W RE VIE W (Vol. 42:61 This proposition, as Cole Durham reminds us, was affirmed during the beginnings of this nation, not only by radical Protestants, but also by enlightenment rationalistsy 7 On this point, I would underline a long standing conviction of mine, a conviction well-founded in historical evidence, even though yet contested by historians and theologians. According to a dominant tradition of interpretation, Protestants and rationalists have been presented as, respectively, religionists (to whom sacrality is supreme) and secularists (for whom public order takes priority over religious concerns). That interpretation, however, is contradicted by the historical record. As one telling example, I would cite James Madison's Memorial and Remonstrance 28 in which he asserts: This duty [which we owe our Creator] is precedent both in order of time and in degree of obligation, to the claims of Civil Society. Before any man [sic] can be considered as a member of Civil Society, he must be considered as a subject of the Governor of the Universe: And if a member of Civil Society, who enters into any subordinate Association, must always do it with a reservation of his duty to the general authority; much more must every man who becomes a member of any particular Civil Society, do it with a saving of his allegiance to the Universal Sovereign. 29 That is James Madison. This is not to say that all enlightenment rationalists would support such a sentiment, but James Madison did. Benjamin Franklin did, as well as others (e.g., Patrick Henry and Thomas Paine). My point is that not only radical Protestants, but also enlightenment Deists, understood the supremacy of sacrality. From the standpoint of that premise, government's authority is secondary and subordinate. I would conclude with a quotation from George Fox, the founder of the Quakers. I am, I admit, fond of the Quaker tradition in many ways. Regarding religious liberty, George Fox once wrote: And let him [or her] be Jew or Papist or Turk or heathen or Protestant or what sort so ever or such as worship sun or moon or stocks or stone, let them have liberty where everyone may bring forth his [or her) strength and his [or her] mind and judgment. 80 That is a striking statement for its time. William Penn, who com- 27. Durham, supra note 18, at 79-85. 28. James Madison, Memorial and Remonstrance Against Religious Assessments, reprinted in THE MIND OF THE FOUNDER: SOURCES OF THE POLITICAL THOUGHT OF JAMES MADISON 5 (Marvin Meyers ed., rev. ed. 1981). 29. Id. at 7. 30. MELVIN B. ENDY, JR., WILLIAM PENN AND EARLY OUAKERISM 315 (1973).

1992] REPENTANCE AND CONSTITUTIONALISM posed constitutions for Eastern New Jersey and, later, for Pennsylvania, came fairly close to Fox's expansive sentiment in his provision for religious liberty, albeit, in my judgment, not close enough. Fox's sentiment, I would argue, is grounded in an understanding of what it means to be human. To be human in the Quaker tradition is to be possessed of an inner light. As Washington would remind us, that is an understanding of conscience. The inner light corresponds to the divine light. In that correspondence, we have entered upon the realm of the sacred. At that point, if we would respect the innermost depths of our humanity, we must let people do their own searching - whether they worship stones or sun, whether they be Turk or Papist or heathen or Protestant. That is their reason for the religion clauses in the Bill of Rights. From this standpoint, the religion clauses are protective of that sacred space beyond the jurisdiction of government within which and through which we may continue our search for ultimate meaning.