BUDDHIST REFLECTIONS AT SEA LEVEL: A RESPONSE TO GOLDBERG S I WANT MY BEEF Mylan Engel, Jr. Northern Illinois University

Similar documents
Clarifications on What Is Speciesism?

Hume's Is/Ought Problem. Ruse and Wilson. Moral Philosophy as Applied Science. Naturalistic Fallacy

Philosophical approaches to animal ethics

Are Humans Always Selfish? OR Is Altruism Possible?

Animal Disenhancement

In Defense of Eating Vegan

BETWEEN THE SPECIES Issue V August 2005

Disvalue in nature and intervention *

Introduction. In light of these facts, we will ask, is killing animals for human benefit morally permissible?

Hindu Paradigm of Evolution

Morality, Suffering and Violence. Ross Arnold, Fall 2015 Lakeside institute of Theology

Good Eats ABSTRACT. Elizabeth Foreman Missouri State University Volume 17, Issue 1

Human Nature & Human Diversity: Sex, Love & Parenting; Morality, Religion & Race. Course Description

Reasons Community. May 7, 2017

24.03: Good Food 3 April Animal Liberation and the Moral Community

-1 Peter 3:15-16 (NSRV)

WhaT does it mean To Be an animal? about 600 million years ago, CerTain

Against "Sensible" Naturalism (2007)

Moral Vegetarianism vs. Moral Omnivorism. Park, Seungbae (2017). Moral Vegetarianism vs. Moral Omnivorism Human Affairs 27 (3):

IN DEFENSE OF AN ANIMAL S RIGHT TO LIFE. Aaron Simmons. A Dissertation

Gary Francione Interview on WTJS

THE MYTH OF MORALITY CHAPTER 6. Morality and Evolution

The Utilitarian Approach. Chapter 7, Elements of Moral Philosophy James Rachels Professor Douglas Olena

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

Hume s Is/Ought Problem. Ruse and Wilson. Moral Philosophy as Applied Science. Naturalistic Fallacy

HUMAN NATURE REVIEW ISSN Book Review

What if Klein & Barron are right about insect sentience? Commentary on Klein & Barron on Insect Experience

Darwinian Morality. Why aren t t all the atheists raping and pillaging? Ron Garret (Erann( Gat) September 2004

Warren. Warren s Strategy. Inherent Value. Strong Animal Rights. Strategy is to argue that Regan s strong animals rights position is not persuasive

Topic III: Sexual Morality

FREEDOM OF CHOICE. Freedom of Choice, p. 2

Contents Introduction...1 The Goodness Ethic...1 Method...3 The Nature of the Good...4 Goodness as Virtue and Intention...6 Revision History...

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

Puzzles for Divine Omnipotence & Divine Freedom

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

How to Live a More Authentic Life in Both Markets and Morals

Ethical non-naturalism

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

Issue VIII August Reasonable Humans and Animals: An Argument for Vegetarianism

Interview with Lori Marino By OUR HEN HOUSE Published February 22, 2014

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

THE GOD OF QUARKS & CROSS. bridging the cultural divide between people of faith and people of science

Psychological and Ethical Egoism

PROFESSIONAL ETHICS IN SCIENCE AND ENGINEERING

Responsibility and Normative Moral Theories

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

The Prospective View of Obligation

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

Review of Jean Kazez's Animalkind: What We Owe to Animals

Format for ONE Paragraph

Integrated Studies 002: Human Morality and Emotions University of Pennsylvania Spring 2017

If Natural Entities Have Intrinsic Value, Should We Then Abstain from Helping Animals Who Are Victims of Natural Processes? 1

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

Why Speciesism is Wrong: A Response to Kagan

Section 1 of chapter 1 of The Moral Sense advances the thesis that we have a

This house believes that animals have rights.

We are all Ninjas: Sympathy, solidarity and evolutionary ethics

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

SOCIOLOGICAL ANALYSIS Michaelmas 2017 Dr Michael Biggs. 7. Evolution. SociologicalAnalysis.shtml!

Being Human Prepared by Gerald Gleeson

MILL. The principle of utility determines the rightness of acts (or rules of action?) by their effect on the total happiness.

Annotated List of Ethical Theories

DOES ETHICS NEED GOD?

Atheism. Challenging religious faith. Does not endorse any ethical or political system or values; individual members may.

Moral Philosophy : Utilitarianism

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

HARE S PRESCRIPTIVISM

The Biological Foundation of Bioethics

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

Why Teach Ethics? J. N. Hooker. CORS/INFORMS, Banff, May 2004

Altruism. A selfless concern for other people purely for their own sake. Altruism is usually contrasted with selfishness or egoism in ethics.

On Dispositional HOT Theories of Consciousness

Religious and non religious beliefs and teachings about the origin of the universe.

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

The Great Compassion: Buddhism and Animal Rights

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

On the Alleged Incoherence of Consequentialism. by Robert Mckim and Peter Simpson

Evolution and the Mind of God

Darwinist Arguments Against Intelligent Design Illogical and Misleading


Superior Human. Wong Tsz Yan Chinese Medicine, New Asia College

Vegetarianism and Virtue: Does Consequentialism Demand Too Little?

To be able to define human nature and psychological egoism. To explain how our views of human nature influence our relationships with other

The Moral Value of Animals: Three Versions Based on Altruism

Perspectives on Imitation

SATISFICING CONSEQUENTIALISM AND SCALAR CONSEQUENTIALISM

Phil 114, April 24, 2007 until the end of semester Mill: Individual Liberty Against the Tyranny of the Majority

Morality and the Senses. One Does Not Equal the Other

Welcome back to week 2 of this edition of 5pm Church Together.

animals Animals 2011, 1, ; doi: /ani ISSN Book Review Ben Mepham

Challenges to Traditional Morality

Sample. Teaching the Classics: Worldview Supplement. By Adam and Missy Andrews The Center for Literary Education

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

The Problem of Evil. Prof. Eden Lin The Ohio State University

STUDY GUIDE ARE HUMANS MORE VALUABLE THAN ANIMALS? KEY TERMS:

Ought, Can, and Practical Reasons 1 Clayton Littlejohn

The belief in the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent and benevolent God is inconsistent with the existence of human suffering. Discuss.

Ethics is subjective.

Chapter 2: Commitment

Peter Singer, Practical Ethics Discussion Questions/Study Guide Prepared by Prof. Bill Felice

Transcription:

BUDDHIST REFLECTIONS AT SEA LEVEL: A RESPONSE TO GOLDBERG S I WANT MY BEEF Mylan Engel, Jr. Northern Illinois University mylan-engel@niu.edu David Goldberg s beef isn t just about beef. His goal is to justify the raising, killing, and eating of cows, steers (castrated bulls), and the myriad of other animals we routinely kill for food. While he promises to give us three arguments in defense of meat-eating, I detect five arguments: (i) the monk aping argument (If monks do it, so can I), (ii) the selfish gene argument, (iii) the animals can t suffer argument, (iv) the high elevation argument, and (v) the prey-liberation reductio. The arguments are independent of each other and will be treated as such. In what follows, I will address arguments (i) (iv), starting with (ii). [I won t address argument (v) per se, because Singer has already addressed it in Chapter 6 of Animal Liberation.] Along the way, I will argue that Goldberg misinterprets Dawkins, Singer, and Norcross, and that for this reason, along with countless others, his defense of eating meat fails. 1. The Selfish Gene Argument Goldberg contends that Peter Singer s call for a nonspeciesistic ethic flies in the face of the biological reality of gene selfishness. In The Selfish Gene, Richard Dawkins argues that traditional evolutionists are mistaken in thinking that species is the primary unit of selection in natural selection. He contends that the fundamental unit of selection is the gene. A successful gene will be long-lived (in the gene pool), fecund, and have a high degree of copying-fidelity. An unsuccessful gene will promptly be removed from the gene pool. But how exactly do selfish genes succeed? Here is the gist of selfish gene theory: An individual gene is like a tiny self-replicating computer program that builds/designs certain features into a resulting organism. As such, genes give rise to the phenotypic traits of the individual macro-organisms they, in concert with other genes, design. Those phenotypic traits that help an individual organism survive and procreate in a given environment are fitness enhancing (in that environment) and, as a result, are likely to be passed on to the next generation, and hence, the genes responsible for those phenotypic traits are selected for. Genes that result in maladaptive phenotypic traits are likely to result in organisms that die before procreating. Waxing Quinean, we might put the point as follows: Those genes that give rise to organisms ill-suited to their environment have the pathetic but praiseworthy tendency to remove

2 themselves from the gene pool. 1 The basic idea is that genes are selfish. They only survive by producing organisms well-suited to their environments. Of course, it s a far leap to go from the view that genes are fundamentally selfish to the view that the individual organisms they produce are selfish. After all, in certain environments unselfish, altruistic, cooperating organisms will have a better chance of surviving than selfish, uncooperative organisms, and in those environments, altruistic cooperation will be selected for, and this cooperation may be intraspecies or interspecies. Examples include kin selection, tit-for-tat cooperative strategies, and symbiotic relationships. It s an even farther leap to go, as Goldberg does, from the view that genes are selfish [i.e. replicator-centric ] to the view that the organisms they produce must, in turn, be species-centric. Not only is there counterevidence [Countless symbiotic species demonstrate the survival value of transspecies altruism and cooperation in certain environments], but more importantly, such a claim runs counter to selfish gene theory itself, which explicitly denies that species is the unit of selection. According to selfish gene theory, selection at the level of species is no more plausible than selection at the level of genera, orders, classes, or phyla. (Dawkins 1976, 11) And it s a leap to certain death to assume that the selfishness of our genes biologically necessitates a speciescentric ethic. Goldberg takes this latter leap as well, for he writes: As a behavior pattern that was selected for, a selection that rests precisely on a replicator-centricity, which secondarily leads to a species-centric position, evolutionary moral behavior flies in the face of Singer s desire to have a non-species-centric position (p. 6) There are two reasons that the latter leap is a leap to certain death: First, it commits the naturalistic fallacy of inferring an ought from an is. Dawkins himself begins his book with a caveat about drawing moral conclusions from the factual claims contained in his book: This brings me to the first point I want to make about what this book is not. I am not advocating a morality based on evolution. I am saying how things have evolved. I am not saying how we humans morally ought to behave. I stress this, because I know I am in danger of being

3 misunderstood by those people, all to numerous, who cannot distinguish a statement of belief in what is the case from an advocacy of what ought to be the case. (Dawkins 1976, 3) Second, in point of fact, human beings have evolved in such a way that we do care about the welfare of members of other species, and if selfish gene theory is correct, then the gene responsible for our empathetic concern for other species must either have survival value itself or must be inextricably tied to another trait that does have survival value. Otherwise, the caring-for-other-species gene would have been eliminated from the gene pool. Consequently, if biology were the sole determinant of our moral attitudes, moral concern for members of other species would necessarily be reflected in those attitudes. 2. The Animals Can t Suffer Argument Utilitarians, like Peter Singer and Alastair Norcross, maintain that an action X is right for an agent S iff, out of all the actions available to S, X maximizes pleasure and minimizes pain (and suffering) for all those affected by the action. In making our utilitarian calculations, utilitarianism requires that we take into account the suffering of any being capable of suffering. After all, any being capable of suffering has an interest in avoiding such suffering. Singer and Norcross both maintain that modern animal agriculture-- with its attendant unanaesthetized branding, dehorning, tooth-pulling, ear-clipping, debeaking, taildocking, and castration, and its confinement and severe movement restriction--causes farm animals intense pain and suffering for the duration of their lives. Since there is an alternative way of feeding ourselves, namely, eating a plant-based vegan diet, that doesn t require subjecting animals to such suffering, utilitarianism requires that we adopt a vegan diet. Goldberg objects to this argument for ethical veganism on the grounds that most of the animals we routinely eat i.e., cows, pigs, and chickens are incapable of suffering, and hence, there is no suffering to take into account. How does Goldberg defend this startling claim? Appealing to the Buddhist doctrine of four noble truths, he contends that dukkah, i.e., suffering, is not to be understood as simple neurological pain, which can occur in any organism with nociceptors. Rather, suffering results from desires that go unmet. He tells us: It is desire that brings about suffering, hence its elimination is possible only as a result of a being who is capable of re-conceptualizing the world. Goldberg then argues roughly

4 roughly as follows: 1. A being is capable of suffering only if that being possesses desires. 2. A being possesses desires only if that being is self-conscious. 3. Apart from a few higher mammals, animals are not self-conscious. Therefore, 4. Apart from a few higher mammals, animals are incapable of suffering. This argument is open to numerous objections. First, it is not at all clear that self-consciousness is restricted to the few higher mammals that Goldberg identifies. Antonio Damasio, a highly respected neuropsychologist, contends that selfhood and subjectivity are necessary conditions for consciousness per se and not just for self-consciousness. (Damasio 1994, 238). If Damasio is right, all the animals we routinely eat are self-conscious, since they are clearly conscious. The point is simply this: Given the current state of cognitive science, it is dangerous to speculate about which animal are self-conscious, especially when one has a desire to eat those deemed non-self-conscious. Second, since Goldberg is concerned with conforming his views to biology and evolutionary reality, it s worth noting that in The Descent of Man Charles Darwin, biologist and ethologist extraordinaire, argues that there is no fundamental difference between man and the higher mammals in their mental faculties (Darwin 1989, 27). Darwin begins with the observation that The lower animals, like man, manifestly feel pleasure and pain, happiness and misery (Darwin 1989, 27). [I assume by misery here he means something akin to suffering, since he is contrasting it with pain.] He then goes on to argue that lower animals including dogs, horses, elephants and other wild animals are excited by the same base emotions as humans including fear, suspicion, and jealousy and possess the same intellectual emotions and faculties including wonder, curiosity, attention, memory, imagination and reason. It would be very odd that animals would share all of these mental faculties with us, but not share the property of having desires. Third, there is enormous behavioral evidence that animals possess desires in particular, that they desire pleasurable stimuli (e.g., food, sex, grooming and being groomed) and that they desire to avoid

5 noxious stimuli (e.g., electric shocks, burns, and other painful stimuli). Moreover, possessing these desires would clearly have survival value (beings that didn t desire food or sex would quickly die out). Simply put, we have much better evidence that animals possess desires than that they are not self-conscious. As such, we should turn the above argument on its head and conclude that since animals possess desires either (a) self-consciousness isn t necessary for the possession of desires or (b) animals are self-conscious. Finally, the above argument is in an important sense otiose. After all, utilitarians are concerned with minimizing pain, as well as suffering. Even if it were to turn out that animals are incapable of suffering, they clearly are capable of experiencing pain, and Goldberg admits as much. So, the utilitarian argument for ethical veganism based on minimizing unnecessary pain would still go through. 3. The High Elevation Argument Goldberg accuses Singer of being guilty of a kind of contextualist localization, in that he doesn t appreciate that people living at elevations of 16,000 feet must rely on meat to survive. As Goldberg puts it: As with the Tibetans, who are incapable of growing sufficient sustenance at 16,000 ft., hence the need to rely on meat, so humans in the past would have existed in environments in which survival would have demanded eating meat... The two conditions that come to mind immediately are pre-agricultural societies and, more emphatically, our survival during the ice-age. Both of these would have demanded an omnivorous diet. (Goldberg 2005, 7) No utilitarian would deny that eating meat is permissible in certain circumstances. Certainly, neither Singer nor Norcross claim that eating meat is never permissible under any circumstances. According to utilitarianism, eating meat is permissible whenever there is no other option available that results in a better balance of pleasure over pain. Presumably, both Singer and Norcross would grant that eating meat is permissible when necessary for our survival, as in pre-agricultural and ice-age societies. Nevertheless, we are not living in a pre-agricultural society, and as far as I know, the ice-age is over. Whether or not it s permissible for human ice-age inhabitants to eat meat is irrelevant. The question is whether it is permissible for us to eat meat, and the utilitarian answer is: Not whenever there are equally nutritious plant-based foods available that produce a better balance of pleasure over pain. Since, in modern

6 societies, such plant-based foods are almost always available, utilitarianism entails that eating meat is almost always wrong. 4. The Monk Aping Argument The argument goes something like this: Zen Buddhist monks, including some high-ranking senior Geshes, eat animals (provided others kill the animals for them). So, it s permissible for us to eat animals, provided others do the dirty work of killing those animals for us. To be fair, Goldberg doesn t explicitly offer this as an argument in defense of eating meat, but he does use monk behavior as a rhetorical device throughout the article, and in several places, he holds monk behavior up as a supposed model of ideal ethical behavior. I submit that the monks he reveres and seeks to emulate are not worthy of emulation, at least where their dietary choices are concerned. Here s why: The First Precept of Buddhist ethical conduct is not to harm or kill sentient beings. The four sublime Buddhist virtues are loving kindness, compassion, sympathetic joy, and equanimity. People who routinely dine on the bodies of inhumanely-raised and slaughtered animals while professing to embrace these Buddhist values are simply hypocrites. They simply are not living their lives in accordance with their professed values. How did the meat-eating monks attempt to reconcile the apparent inconsistency between their professed values and their practices? With what must have been intended as a Zen Koan: Have you ever tried to be a vegetarian at 16,000 feet? When Goldberg heard this rhetorical question, he came to the following conclusion: environmental necessity... turned a Buddhist vegetarian dietary prescription into an omnivorous diet. By my lights, it was human rationalization, not environmental necessity, that resulted in these Buddhists adopting an omnivorous diet. First, it s the 21 st century. People today have quite a bit of choice about where they live. If it is impossible to maintain a vegetarian diet at 16,000 feet, the monks should have moved to a place where they could live in accordance with their professed values. Second, the suggestion that it is not possible to survive on a vegetarian diet at an elevation of 16,000 feet is ludicrous. Dried beans, whole grains, and flours last indefinitely without refrigeration. The monks could have easily stored enough beans and grains to last them through the winter without ever having to eating meat. After

7 all, to raise animals for food at 16,000 feet, these animals themselves have to be fed. What are they fed? Ground up grains and soybeans. These are foods that could, much more efficiently, be eaten directly by humans. Finally, even if it were absolutely necessary for these monks to eat meat in order to survive in their mountain monastery located 16,000 feet above sea level, this would in no way justify their current dietary practices here in the States. Westminister College is located in New Wilmington, PA, which boasts an elevation of 806 feet. No one in New Wilmington needs to eat meat to survive or thrive. In New Wilmington, like every other city in America, eating animals is entirely gratuitous. Even granting Goldberg his preferred contextualism, eating a large piece of a cruelly-raised and inhumanely-slaughtered steer, when doing so is not necessary for one s survival or health, violates the main tenets of Buddhist thought. Consistent Buddhists and consistent utilitarians agree that causing sentient beings unnecessary pain is wrong and ought not be supported or encouraged. The lesson these meat-eating monks should be espousing is: Do as we say, not as we do. Adopt our values, but not our practices. Surely, it s better to emulate a consistent Buddhist of integrity. Such a Buddhist would inspire us to eliminate our desire for meat, since doing so would prevent much dukkah (suffering), both our own and the animals. Conclusion At one point in his paper, Goldberg asks: What makes our eating of animals different from the lion whose taste is for young gazelles? (Goldberg, 7). The answer is twofold: First, we have a choice, the lion doesn t. We can choose to eat something else instead and be healthier to boot. The lion can t. Second, we won t die if we refrain from eating animals, the lion will. This underscores a crucial point: Eating meat, while necessary for a lion, is totally unnecessary for humans living in modern societies. It s this latter fact that makes it so hard to justify the raising, slaughtering, and eating of animals. Any satisfactory defense of eating animals must explain why it is morally permissible to subject them to so much pain and premature death for no good reason. One thing s for sure: It will take a much meatier argument than the ones proffered by Goldberg to justify eating our fellow sentient creatures.

8 REFERENCES Damasio, A.: 1994, Descartes Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain, New York, NY: Grosset/Putnam Publishing Co. Darwin, C.: 1989, Comparison of the Mental Powers of Man and the Lower Animals, in Animal Rights and Human Obligations, eds. Regan, T. and Singer, P. (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1989). Goldberg, D.: 2005, I Want My Beef: A Reply to Singer in manuscript. Singer, P.: 1990, Animal Liberation, 2 nd Edition, New York, NY: Random House. Singer, P.: 1995, How Are We to Live?, Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books. 1 With apologies to Quine who made the point with respect to the selection of individuals, rather than the selection of genes.