Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 2, Number 6

Similar documents
The Austinian Conception of Illocution and its Implications for Value Judgments and Social ontology

AVNER BAZ Associate Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy Tufts University Medford, MA

Philosophy of Logic and Language (108) Comprehensive Reading List Robert L. Frazier 24/10/2009

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Critical Appreciation of Jonathan Schaffer s The Contrast-Sensitivity of Knowledge Ascriptions Samuel Rickless, University of California, San Diego

Assertion and Inference

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

Honors Thomas E. Sunderland Faculty Fellow, University of Michigan Law School, ADVANCE Faculty Summer Writing Grant, 2016, 2017

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise

2018 Philosophy of Management Conference Paper submission NORMATIVITY AND DESCRIPTION: BUSINESS ETHICS AS A MORAL SCIENCE


Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

2014 THE BIBLIOGRAPHIA ISSN: Online First: 21 October 2014

Skepticism. LPS 221 Fall Winter 2014 (final)

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Honours Programme in Philosophy

MSc / PGDip / PGCert Epistemology (online) (PHIL11131) Course Guide

AVNER BAZ Professor and Chair Department of Philosophy Tufts University Medford, MA

Elizabeth Barnes Corcoran Department of Philosophy University of Virginia

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

General Philosophy. Stephen Wright. Office: XVI.3, Jesus College. Michaelmas Overview 2. 2 Course Website 2. 3 Readings 2. 4 Study Questions 3

Meaning, Contexts and Justification

Skepticism and Internalism

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

Philosophy 1760 Philosophy of Language

A HUNDRED YEARS OF ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY

Elizabeth Barnes Corcoran Department of Philosophy University of Virginia

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Tuomas E. Tahko (University of Helsinki)

PH 463/663 Philosophy of Language, Spring 2019 Professor Juliet Floyd, Boston University

PH 463/663 Philosophy of Language, Fall 2016

Feminist Epistemology Feminism in Analytic Philosophy Week One, MT 2012, Oxford

Foundations of Analytic Philosophy

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

*Please note that tutorial times and venues will be organised independently with your teaching tutor.

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

Comments on Nancy Bauer s How to Do Things with Pornography Amia Srinivasan

Believing Epistemic Contradictions

ANALOGIES AND METAPHORS

Epistemicism, Parasites and Vague Names * vagueness is based on an untenable metaphysics of content are unsuccessful. Burgess s arguments are

Introduction. Bernard Williams

WITTGENSTEIN, AUSTIN, AND THE ORIGINS OF SPEECH-ACT THEORY

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Avoiding the Dogmatic Commitments of Contextualism. Tim Black and Peter Murphy. In Grazer Philosophische Studien 69 (2005):

WEEK 1: WHAT IS KNOWLEDGE?

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

Supplementary Section 6S.7

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Philosophy Courses-1

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 1

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

Hume's Treatise of Human Nature

Introduction to Calderoni s The Philosophy of Values

CURRICULUM VITAE STEPHEN JACOBSON. (Title: What's Wrong With Reliability Theories of Justification?)

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

Philosophy Courses-1

CONSTRUCTIVISM IN ETHICS

Philosophy. Aim of the subject

PHIL-210: Knowledge and Certainty

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

After Sen what about objectivity in economics?

BLACKWELL PUBLISHING THE SCOTS PHILOSOPHICAL CLUB UNIVERSITY OF ST ANDREWS

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE

Also by Nafsika Athanassoulis. Also by Samantha Vice

The Concept of Testimony

One Notion of Religious Truth? Hilary Putnam s Conceptual Truth and the Justification of Religious Propositions

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Avner Baz a a Tufts University, Massachusetts, USA. To link to this article:

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Meaning and Privacy. Guy Longworth 1 University of Warwick December

Curriculum Vitae. Education. Academic Appointments. Fellowships, Grants, Awards

Philosophical reflection about what we call knowledge has a natural starting point in the

Dr. Evangelia Papadaki. Curriculum Vitae

Anti-intellectualism and the Knowledge-Action Principle

Action in Special Contexts

Circularity in ethotic structures

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

ABSTRACT: In this paper, I argue that Phenomenal Conservatism (PC) is not superior to

DOMINICAN UNIVERSITY COLLEGE

(P420-1) Practical Reason in Ancient Greek and Contemporary Philosophy. Spring 2018

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014

THREE LOGICIANS: ARISTOTLE, SACCHERI, FREGE

PHILOSOPHY (413) Chairperson: David Braden-Johnson, Ph.D.

The Nature of Enquiry

PHENOMENAL CONSERVATISM, JUSTIFICATION, AND SELF-DEFEAT

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Putnam and the Contextually A Priori Gary Ebbs University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign

Wisdom: A Selective Annotated Bibliography. Forthcoming in Oxford Bibliographies Online Dennis Whitcomb August 31, 2009

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Philosophy Courses Fall 2011

THE APOLOGY STRATEGIES USED BY A BUDGET HOTEL FRONT OFFICERS IN HANDLING CUSTOMER COMPLAINTS

Subject Overview Curriculum pathway

Terence CUNEO, The Normative Web. An Argument for Moral Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008, 263 pp., 46.99, ISBN

Intuition as Philosophical Evidence

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Transcription:

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 2, Number 6 Martin Gustafsson and Richard Sørli, editors. The Philosophy of J. L. Austin. Oxford. Oxford University Press, 2011. ISBN: 9780199219759 Reviewed by Claudia Bianchi Editor in Chief Mark Textor, King s College London Editorial Board Juliet Floyd, Boston University Greg Frost-Arnold, Hobart and William Smith Colleges Ryan Hickerson, University of Western Oregon Henry Jackman, York University Sandra Lapointe, McMaster University Chris Pincock, Ohio State University Richard Zach, University of Calgary Production Editor Ryan Hickerson Editorial Assistant Daniel Harris, CUNY Graduate Center Design Douglas Patterson and Daniel Harris 2014 Claudia Bianchi

Review: The Philosophy of J. L. Austin, edited by Martin Gustafsson and Richard Sørli Claudia Bianchi John Austin has had a strange fate: much revered during his lifetime, he was almost forgotten after his death, to the point that his work is still inadequately known and largely underestimated. Many factors contributed to such a fate. During his teaching in Oxford he was celebrated for his extraordinary personality and innovative philosophical method: for Austin, philosophy was not an endeavour to be pursued privately, but a collective effort, as exemplified by his legendary Saturday mornings. However his method was better suited for discussion than for publication, and his philosophical talent more fully appreciated in private conversations. Moreover we owe to Searle and Grice many of the developments of Austin s ideas in speech act theory and pragmatics: as Martin Gustafsson writes in his excellent Introduction, it seems fair to say that their works have contributed more than anything else to the general sense that Austin s endeavours have become outdated (p. 16). In recent times this situation has changed. Nowadays Austin is studied in research fields as diverse as philosophy of language, linguistics, epistemology, philosophy of action, ethics, legal theory, political thought and feminist philosophy. The collection of essays edited by Martin Gustafsson and Richard Sørli ( the first collection of essays on Austin s philosophy published by a major Anglophone press in almost forty years, p. 3) is another indication of this Austinian renaissance. The eight essays and the Introduction focus on Austin s place in philosophy, epistemological issues (scepticism, epistemology of testimony, contextualism) and Austin s work on truth. In what follows, I will offer a concise sketch of each essay, before concluding with some critical remarks. Martin Gustafsson in the Introduction ( Inheriting Austin ) and Simon Glendinning in Chapter 2 ( Unmasking the Tradition ) situate Austin among his contemporaries and within Western philosophy at large, showing both the continuity and the originality of his approach to philosophy. The British philosopher was deeply dissatisfied with both the traditional way of doing philosophy and with Logical Positivism. In particular, his dissatisfaction was directed towards a way of practicing philosophy which, in his view, was responsible for the production of tidy dichotomies, oversimplifications and dogmatic schemes of thought. As a consequence, he developed a new philosophical methodology and style, which became paradigmatic of Ordinary Language Philosophy. According to Austin, within ordinary language are deposited all the distinctions and connections established by human beings, as if our words in their daily uses had stood up to the long test of the survival of the fittest (Austin 1956/1961, 182). To be sure, this is not a new methodology in the history of philosophy (consider, for instance, Socratic questioning); yet, this strategy was carried out by Austin with exceptional care and conceived as a collective endeavour. Chapters 3 to 6 are devoted to epistemological issues. Mark Kaplan in Chapter 3 ( Tales of the Unknown: Austin and the Argument from Ignorance ) and Adam Leite in Chapter 4 ( Austin, Dreams, and Scepticism ) focus on scepticism, and its relation with our ordinary judgements. Kaplan s essay is the latest of a series of papers devoted to a defence of Austin s approach to the theory of knowledge as an epistemology true to our ordinary practices. Drawing partially on his previous work, Kaplan here examines a particular variety of what DeRose calls the argument from Ignorance, in order to show that the dichotomy between what one knows and what one doesn t know is not exhaustive: the adoption Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, vol. 2 no. 6 [1]

of an Austinian methodology severely undermines sceptical arguments about knowledge. Leite examines a different argument for scepticism, the dream argument: he shows how Austin challenges global scepticism not only with a linguistic strategy, but also with factual claims regarding our ordinary epistemic procedures. In Chapter 5 ( Believing what the Man Says about his own Feelings ), Benjamin McMyler offers an innovative reading of Other Minds not only as an essay on the problem of other minds, but also as a work on the epistemology of testimony. In particular, McMyler addresses the Austinian analogy between I know and I promise, trying to clarify what constitutes the justification of testimonial knowledge a justification grounded on its essentially interpersonal character. In Chapter 6 ( Knowing Knowing (that Such and Such) ) Avner Baz questions a wellestablished claim in both contemporary philosophy of language and epistemology, namely that Austin was a contextualist, or at least the forefather (along with Wittgenstein) of contextualism. Baz shows that contextualists and anti-contextualists share the idea that the basic role of knowing that is to enable us to represent people as knowing this or that. The accent placed on truthconditions domesticates the Austinian perspective: according to Austin, our everyday epistemological claims are expressive of and answerable to the participants intents and purposes those often involving not truth and falsity, but competence, reasonableness and responsibility. In Chapter 7 ( Truth and Merit ) an ideal, partial reply to Baz Charles Travis concentrates on Austin s conception of truth. Travis underlines that truth/falsity is simply one among many dimensions of evaluation. Statements, as traditionally conceived, are abstractions: stating something is instead just offering a guide to treating things (p. 192). The relation between the conceptual (statements) and the non-conceptual (state of affairs) cannot be fixed once and for all: in applying a statement we must exercise the same sensibility and the same virtues we use in giving advice or issuing verdicts. In a similar vein, Jean-Philippe Narboux (Chapter 8, 'There's Many a Slip between Cup and Lip': Dimension and Negation in Austin ) examines Austin s claim that truth and falsity, and felicity and infelicity are on a par as dimensions of evaluations of utterances. In so doing, he underlines the often neglected systematic character of Austin s work of his approach and his conceptual tools. The major value of this collection is unquestionably that of providing an overview of the complexity and variety of Austin s contributions to philosophy, too often circumscribed to speech act theory, and to his method of linguistic phenomenology. And yet one feels that something is missing from this very fine volume. It is undeniable that the standard picture of Austin as the doyen of Ordinary Language Philosophy and the founder of speech act theory hides from view the diversity and variation that are in fact prominent characteristic of [Austin s philosophical landscape] (Gustafsson, p. 1). Choosing not to include in the collection a single contribution to speech act theory is, however, at best controversial. Even more so if one claims as Gustafsson does in the section of his Introduction devoted to Austin s legacy that there are still philosophers that treat Austin as a philosopher to think with, rather than as a respectable but obsolete precursor (p. 17), such as William Alston and Marina Sbisà (Alston 2000, Sbisà 2007, 2009, 2013), and furthermore that there is at least a contemporary philosophical debate in which Austin still figures as a living and direct source of influence, (p. 18), namely the discussion on pornography and free speech. Indeed the debate on free speech, pornography and censorship is one of the most remarkable current applications of speech act theory (cf. Hornsby 1993, Hornsby & Langton 1998, Langton 1993, 2009, Bianchi 2008, Langton, Haslanger and Anderson 2012). Catharine MacKinnon s claim that pornography subordinates women (MacKinnon 1987) has been defended Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, vol. 2 no. 6 [2]

by Rae Langton and Jennifer Hornsby in terms of speech acts: works of pornography can be understood as illocutionary acts. Pornography subordinates women by conditioning people to regard women as willing sexual objects; it silences women by creating a communicative environment that deprives women of their illocutionary potential. Against the liberal defence of pornography as a form of expression (a simple form of locution), Langton and Hornsby argue that pornography does more than simply express; it acts to silence the expressions of women (a form of illocution), thereby restricting their freedom of speech. The debate on free speech and pornography is, then, an excellent example of a domain where most participants actually read and discuss what Austin says, treating his writings as texts from which there is still something important to learn (p. 18). Such remarks notwithstanding, this is an extremely rich and fascinating collection, questioning the generally received picture of Austin, filled with suggestions and innovative analyses of his work. I agree with what is said in the Introduction, that our temporal distance from Austin (and his students and colleagues) can truly be a blessing: the consequences and import of his philosophy can be better understood in light of its recent applications and developments. Once more, a careful analysis of the things we, as philosophers, do with Austin s words helps to clarify an extensive variety of contemporary issues. Claudia Bianchi Faculty of Philosophy Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele, Milano, Italy claudia.bianchi@unisr.it References J. L. Austin. A Plea for Excuses. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 57, 1 30: 1956. Reprinted in Austin 1961, 175 204. J. L. Austin. Philosophical Papers. J. O. Urmson and G. J. Warnock, editors, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1961. 3rd Edition, 1979. J. L. Austin. How to Do Things with Words. J. O. Urmson and M. Sbisà, editors, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 2nd edition, 1975. C. Bianchi. Indexicals, speech acts and pornography. Analysis 68 (4): 310 316, 2008. J. Hornsby. Speech Acts and Pornography. Women s Philosophy Review 10: 38 45, 1993. J. Hornsby and R. Langton. Free Speech and Illocution. Legal Theory 4: 21 37, 1998. M. Kaplan. To What Must an Epistemology Be True?. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (2): 279 304, 2000. M. Kaplan. Austin s Way with Skepticism. In The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism, J. Greco, editor. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 348 371, 2008. R. Langton. Speech Acts and Unspeakable Acts. Philosophy and Public Affairs 22: 293 330, 1993. C. MacKinnon. Francis Biddle s Sister. In MacKinnon, C. 1993, Only Words, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 163 97, 1987. Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, vol. 2 no. 6 [3]

R. Langton, S. Haslanger, and L. Anderson. Language and Race. In Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Language, G. Russell and D. Graff Fara, editors. Routledge, 753 67, 2012. M. Sbisà. How to Read Austin. Pragmatics 17, 461 73, 2007. M. Sbisà. Uptake and Conventionality in Illocution. Lodz Papers in Pragmatics 5 (1), Special Issue on Speech Actions, 33 52, 2009. M. Sbisà. Locution, Illocution, Perlocution. In Pragmatics of Speech Actions, Handbooks of Pragmatics (HoPs), Vol. 2, M. Sbisà and K. Turner, editors, Berlin, Mouton de Gruyter, 25 75, 2013. Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, vol. 2 no. 6 [4]