Freedom on This and the Other Side of Kant is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License.

Similar documents
The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical

To link to this article:

that calls not only the Christian community but also all humanity to do justice in faith/trust.

Kant and his Successors

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

PHILOSOPHY 214 KANT AND HIS CRITICS TUESDAYS AND THURSDAYS, 2:00 3:20PM PROF. KATE MORAN OFFICE HOURS FRIDAYS, 10AM 12PM

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

FIL 4600/10/20: KANT S CRITIQUE AND CRITICAL METAPHYSICS

Introduction. Karl Ameriks and Otfried Höffe

The Impossibility of Evil Qua Evil: Kantian Limitations on Human Immorality

Part I. Classical Sources

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

INTENTIONALITY, NORMATIVITY AND COMMUNALITY IN KANT S REALM OF ENDS

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

NOTES. CPR CPrR G MM 8. G G G 389.

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Lecture 18: Rationalism

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

From G. W. F. Hegel to J. Keating: An Introduction to G. Gentile s Philosophy of (Political) Education. Francesco Forlin. University of Perugia

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Kant on Biology and the Experience of Life

Immanuel Kant. Great German philosophers whose influence was and continues to be immense; born in Konigsberg East Prussia, in 1724, died there in 1804

J.f. Stephen s On Fraternity And Mill s Universal Love 1

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Pleasure and motivation in Kant s

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Kant s Copernican Revolution

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Kant s Ground-Thesis. On Dignity and Value in the Groundwork

METHODENSTREIT WHY CARL MENGER WAS, AND IS, RIGHT

On the Rawlsian Anthropology and the "Autonomous" Account

Guest Editor s Preface On the premises of the mind-body problem: an unexpected German path?

This paper serves as an enquiry into whether or not a theory of metaphysics can grow

For example brain science can tell what is happening in one s brain when one is falling in love

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

IMMANUEL KANT Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals [Edited and reduced by J. Bulger, Ph.D.]

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

Kantian Ethics, Animals, and the Law

Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals

PH 329: Seminar in Kant Fall 2010 L.M. Jorgensen

Paul Lodge (New Orleans) Primitive and Derivative Forces in Leibnizian Bodies

1 Little Newnham Corpus Christi College. United Kingdom

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal

Title: Kant s Account of Respect: A bridge between rationality and anthropology

The Role of Sympathy in Kant s Philosophy of Moral Education

Angelo Cicatello Kant s Idea of History

Liberty and Right. A Kantian outline. Osvaldo Ottaviani

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

Some remarks regarding the regularity model of cause in Hume and Kant

Apriority from the 'Grundlage' to the 'System of Ethics'

DEONTOLOGY AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY

PARADOXES OF AUTONOMY: ON THE DIALECTICS OF FREEDOM AND NORMATIVITY!!*

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

1/9. The Second Analogy (1)

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

An Epistemological Assessment of Moral Worth in Kant s Moral Theory. Immanuel Kant s moral theory outlined in The Grounding for the Metaphysics of

38 Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. [Ak 4:422] [Ak4:421]

Practical Reason and the Call to Faith: Kant on the Postulates of Immortality and God

The Ethics of Self Realization: A Radical Subjectivism, Bounded by Realism. An Honors Thesis (HONR 499) Kevin Mager. Thesis Advisor Jason Powell

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

Is Kant's Account of Free Will Coherent?

Understanding How we Come to Experience Purposive. Behavior. Jacob Roundtree. Colby College Mayflower Hill, Waterville, ME USA

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

The Idea of Freedom and Moral Cognition in Groundwork III

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Kantianism: Objections and Replies Keith Burgess-Jackson 12 March 2017

Stabilizing Kant s First and Second Critiques: Causality and Freedom

The role of ethical judgment based on the supposed right action to perform in a given

Problems of Ethical Pluralism: Arnold Gehlen s Anthropological Ethics

Humanities 4: Lectures Kant s Ethics

My project in this paper is to reconsider the Kantian conception of practical reason. Some

Morality as Freedom. The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters.

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

Leibniz on Justice as a Common Concept: A Rejoinder to Patrick Riley. Andreas Blank, Tel Aviv University. 1. Introduction

Sorin Baiasu Right s Complex Relation to Ethics in Kant: The Limits of Independentism 1

Kant on Moral Satisfaction

Introduction. 1. KANT s LIFE: A BRIEF BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

The Human Deficit according to Immanuel Kant: The Gap between the Moral Law and Human Inability to Live by It. Pieter Vos 1

Online version of this review can be found at:

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

COPLESTON: Quite so, but I regard the metaphysical argument as probative, but there we differ.

Making Sense of the Postulate of Freedom. and God, play in Kant s system is akin to walking a tightrope. First and foremost, the reader must

Transcription:

Freedom on This and the Other Side of Kant is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. Freedom on This and the Other Side of Kant Charles Taylor 1 and Axel Honneth 2 represent a tendency to trace the archaeology of the notion of freedom either to Isaiah Berlin s Two Concepts of Liberty or G.W.F. Hegel s Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts. Without claiming to be an exhaustive investigation of the discussion of freedom since or prior to Immanuel Kant, this paper proposes that the meaning of freedom since Kant has totally eclipsed the tradition of freedom prior to Kant that stems from Pico Mirandola and influenced Leibniz, Sulzer, Tetens all of whom shaped Kant s understanding of freedom. I. Freedom This Side of Kant: Isaiah Berlin and Charles Taylor; Axel Honneth and G.W.F. Hegel Berlin and Taylor Isaiah Berlin distinguishes among negative, positive, and social freedoms: Negative freedom is freedom from external coercion. Negative freedom is the notion that freedom exits to the degree that one is independent from tradition, the social order, and institutions. In short, it is freedom from any external constraints. In this version of negative freedom, then, one takes freedom to consist of refusing to conform to any external law either from tradition, society, or institution and maintains the radical liberty of self-determination to decide what one wishes to do. Positive freedom, in contrast, is coercive freedom by which the individual subordinates her-/himself to a higher authority such as parents or the state in order to increase one s, or to achieve a greater, freedom at some point in the future. Positive freedom requires us to surrender some of our negative freedom (our personal liberty) for the sake of a higher, larger/greater, rational freedom. Social freedom, Berlin s third option, is concerned with minorities within a dominate society. 1 Charles Taylor, What's Wrong with Negative Liberty, in A. Ryan (ed.), The Idea of Freedom, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979), reprinted in Philosophical Papers II. 2 Axel Honneth, Das Recht der Freiheit: Grundriß einer demokratischen Sittlichkeit [The Right of Freedom: Outline of a Democratic Ethics] (Berlin: Suhrkamp Verlag, 2011). 1

Social freedom is the freedom to obtain status and recognition on the part of a minority social unit within a dominant society. Taylor employs Berlin s concept of negative freedom (freedom from external interference) as the straw man for formulating an alternative notion of positive freedom to Berlin s. In contrast to Berlin, positive freedom for Taylor is not coercive but purposive freedom. Taylor wants to acknowledge that freedom involves not merely an alternative between radical independence and external coercion, but positive freedom is concerned with internal elements (the individual s desires) that lead to our pursuing purposive ends. For Taylor, then, Berlin s notions of negative and positive freedom are inadequate to grasp the true character of positive freedom: the pursuit of ends governed by our internal desires. Because not all desires are moral, though, the desires that govern Taylor s notion of positive freedom as purposive require a second-order reflection that invokes moral principles to govern our desires. For Taylor, the source of these moral principles is what Kant would call historical religion or heteronomous, relative morality. Hegel and Honneth Hegel formulates a notion of freedom (perhaps more appropriately called liberty and based upon recognized rights) in terms of the individual s dependence upon social institutions. This is a freedom with others that can be achieved only through shared values and institutional structures that, in turn, recognize the rights of individuals. Drawing on Hegel s discussion of freedom, Axel Honneth defines freedom as communicative freedom, which he distinguishes from negative freedom and reflexive freedom. In common with Berlin and Taylor, negative freedom means freedom from in the sense of rejection of any external, social determination of the individual. However, Honneth places Taylor s discussion of positive freedom under the label of reflexive freedom, which means freedom for acting according to one s own intentions (desires). Honneth distinguishes reflexive freedom from negative freedom in that the individual in reflexive freedom assumes moral responsibility for her/his self-selected goals. According to Honneth, reflexive freedom depends upon the individual s obligation to ground one s actions in something like the golden rule by which one expects oneself to act as one would want all others to treat oneself. Honneth finds that such reflexive freedom, exemplified for him in both 2

Immanuel Kant s rational self-legislation of moral principles (autonomy) and Johann Gottfried Herder s discovery of one s authentic wishes (authenticity), are in fact not truly free but governed by a socialization process, which unmasks free choice and authenticity as illusions because one has appropriated socially relative principles to govern one s actions as if they were absolute and self-legislated. For Honneth in contrast to Theo Kobusch's latest reflections on freedom (Die Kultur des Humanen. Zur Idee der Freiheit [Human Culture: On the Idea of Freedom]), who otherwise is in complete agreement with Honneth, Charles Taylor s positive freedom anchored in religious, moral principles, then, is equally self-contradictory for what is taken to be an autonomous, self-legislated principle is in fact the product of social construction (the social construction of a religious tradition s morality). For his part, Honneth defends a Hegelian notion of communicative freedom, which means freedom with others that can be achieved only through shared values and, most importantly, institutional structures that recognize the rights of individuals. Communicative freedom can be achieved only through a shared social commitment to unhindered and unhampered rational discourse as guaranteed by mutually constructed social institutions that encourage such rational discourse. Honneth and the Frankfurt School call this communicative freedom because it is nothing natural and requires a social construction generated by commitment by all individuals and groups in society and accomplished by all concerned engaging in an open discourse to secure shared and optimal values. Communicative freedom requires a commitment to respect the voices of all and to conform to the decision of the majority within an institutional framework that protects the rights of the minority. Here Honneth joins forces with his colleague, Jürgen Habermas, in the pursuit of distributive justice based upon the construction of appropriate social institutions devoted to facilitating such justice. Communicative freedom acknowledges, Honneth points out, that different institutional systems will recognize such freedom to varying degrees and in different respects. One can evaluate social systems in terms of the degree to which they, in fact, further the right to freedom among their participants/citizenry. Because no institutional system can be perfect, however, there is no one system of communicative freedom that is universal, and any given institutional system requires the continued vigilance and effort of its membership in order to continually renew the commitment to freedom. 3

II. Freedom on the Other Side of KantThi: Autonomous Freedom The notion of autonomous freedom is by no means a Kantian invention. He himself reports that, as he was writing the Critique of Pure Reason, Johannes Tetens two volume Philosophische Versuche über die menschliche Natur und ihre Entwickelung (Philosophical Investigations on Human Nature and its Development) were on his desk. 3 Tetens second volume is devoted to the discussion of the significance of humanity s possession of what appears to be a unique causality over against the blind determinism of nature, our ability to initiate a sequence of events that nature cannot accomplish on its own. Johannes Sulzer treated the notion three years prior to the publication of Tetens reflections in his Vermischte philosophische Schriften (Compiled Philosophical Writings). Kant, Tetens, and Sulzer probably have the theme from Leibniz and Hume (see, as well, Kremer and Wolff in bibliography), and Ernst Cassirer attributes the notion to Pico Mirandola. 4 Unfortunately, the discussion of freedom Diesseits von Kant has for all intents and purposes totally neglected this discussion Jenseits von Kant that so profoundly takes center stage in Critical Idealism. Autonomous freedom is grounded in humanity s causal capacity to initiate a sequence of events that nature (physical causality) on its own cannot accomplish Kant calls precisely this independence from the physical law and desires negative freedom (Critique of Practical Reason KpV, 05: 8). Physical events occur blindly according to the deterministic laws of physics. 3 Although in Reflexionen Kants zur kritischen Philosophie. Aus Kants handschriftlichen Aufzeichnungen, Vol. II, one finds the following comments on Tetens by Kant. Entry 230: Tetens untersucht die Begriffe der reinen Vernunft bloos subjective (menschliche Natur); ich objective. Jene Analysis ist empirisch, diese transcendental. Entry 231: Ich beschäftige mich nicht mit der Evolution der Begriffe wie Tetens (alle Handlungen, dadurch Begriffe erzeugt werden), nicht mit der Analysis wie Lambert, sondern bloss mit der objectiven Giltigkeit derselben. Ich stehe in keiner Mitbewerbung mit diesen Männern. (68) 4 Ernst Cassirer suggests that Pico Mirandola s De hominis dignitate is the source of this revolutionary idea of creative freedom, and Cassirer points out that Mirandola is the source of this idea for Leibniz. See Über die Würde des Menschen von Pico della Mirandola in Studia humanitatis, 12 (1959): 48-61. 4

Given that human creativity only occurs in a physical world, it necessarily is not independent of the blind and deterministic processes of nature, but it is not reducible to them. Because we only experience causes as effects and never directly, there is no way for us to prove (or disprove) by means of empirical data whether or not we possess this causal capacity. However, of those ideas that we must assume and that are incapable of confirmation in the senses if we are to understand ourselves as rational beings (i.e., God, the soul, and freedom), Kant proposes in the Critique of Practical Reason that creative freedom is the one pure idea of reason that comes closest to being a fact of reason. We experience ourselves as capable of purposive behavior that requires our selection not only of the goals of our actions but also requires that we determine the means appropriate for the accomplishment of those goals. The origin of this sequence of hypothetical, technical necessities with respect to the means (materials, tools, and skills) necessary to achieve the intended end is a causality that is categorical: it arises solely from ourselves and is our ability to do things that nature cannot accomplish on its own. No other animal is capable of the degree of purposive behavior like we are. In fact, much of what is viewed as purposive in other species is instinctual, by no means categorical and rational (i.e., initiated solely on the part of the initiator by reflection and the purposive selection of an end). Autonomy is Not Mere Spontaneity If creative freedom is a form of causality that rises above but is never independent from physical causality, creative freedom is also no mere random spontaneity because causal systems require laws (GMS, AA IV: 446.13f). If dreams have no other value, they have the value, Kant proposes (Critique of Pure Reason, KrV: B 520f; Metaphysik Mrongovius, V-Met/Mron, AA 29; and Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, Prol, AA 04) that they remind us that clarity and distinctness of perception in and of itself is insufficient for any sense of causal order. What obviously distinguishes dreams from the waking state is that the former is not, whereas the latter is, governed by a causal order. This causal order is imperceptible to the senses, hence, it is incapable of absolute proof (or disproof), but it makes all the difference in the world whether or not we approach the physical world as if its events conform to a causal order of physical laws. What dream and the physical world teach us, then, is that, where we have causality, there we have a causal order that we can depend upon and must depend upon for the expansion of our understanding and future actions. The same applies to the causality that is our creative freedom. 5

Creative freedom is no mere capricious spontaneity, but, rather, it is a causal system governed by the one system of laws that are compatible with freedom: a self-legislated moral order. Freedom and the Moral Order are no Merely Vicious Circle At the risk of what appears to be a vicious circle, we can view causal order (moral principles) as an indication of autonomous freedom. The very encounter with moral principles presupposes the causality that makes them necessary. Confronted with one s own execution if one were not to testify falsely against a stranger, everyone knows what is right although no one can determine for someone else what s/he must do. The principle that forbids false testimony presupposes that one has the capacity to do something that nature on its own cannot do. In short, it presupposes autonomous freedom. In Section III of the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (GMS, AA 04: 450.17f), Kant discusses this apparent vicious circle with respect to moral principles and the creative, efficient causality that is freedom. A creative causality presupposes a lawful order and a lawful order presupposes a creative causality especially because neither this causality nor moral principles are capable of proof or disproof. However, the circle is avoided, Kant proposes, when we recognize that autonomy is not an isolated capacity for itself but presupposes that we simultaneously and inseparable live in two kingdoms: 1) a sensible realm and 2) an intelligible realm. Autonomous freedom is the tip of a hierarchy of intelligible capacities that allows Kant to speak of humanity as the goal of nature. To be sure, this is not a pronouncement of humanity s right to treat nature as a mere means to satisfy its unlimited interests. Rather, humanity is the goal of nature to the extent that it exercises its autonomous freedom by self-legislating moral principles to govern it. This hierarchy of intelligible capacities stretches from a capacity clearly shared with species (determining judgment) to a capacity only shared in degree with other species (reflecting judgment). Determining judgment is the capacity to apply a concept that one already possesses to classify a set of phenomena. The concept can be given (in the case of other animals, by instinct) or it can acquired by means of reflecting judgment. The latter consists in the capacity to search out a concept that one does not possess already for classification of phenomena that, 6

without the acquisition of the unknown concept, would not be understood. Reflecting judgment is a powerful tool for a species so poorly endowed with instinct as in the case of humanity. However, the intelligible realm is not limited to such theoretical reason (i.e., the making sense of phenomena), but it includes aesthetic judgment where (as in the case of free beauty in nature; see 16 of the Critique of the Power of Judgment, KU, AA 05) one can formulate a judgment without a concept or where (as in the case of the mathematical and dynamical sublime, see 23-29 of ibid., KU, AA 05) one can discovers the illimitable nature of consciousness and, even more profoundly, one can discover that one possesses a causal capacity, precisely because it is not reducible to natural causality, that in principle can destroy nature. This capacity, of course, is autonomous, creative freedom that is at the pinnacle of our intelligible capacities. In other words, the apparent circle of autonomous freedom and moral principles can be defended (even if it cannot be proved) (GMS, AA 04: 459.14-18) not to be vicious because they are only the pinnacle of an illimitable, intelligible realm that is irreducible to the sensible realm. As a consequence, it can be defended as incapable of being accounted for by the blind, mechanical causality of physical nature alone. Our assumption of this intelligible realm and its hierarchy is what allows our escaping both from a vicious circle and from a status of being mere animals, marionettes, or automatons. Autonomous freedom is an extraordinary categorical capacity by means of which we have control with respect to the selection of the principle upon which we will act, and it is not reducible to any other form of freedom (Berlin s negative, coercive, or social freedom; Taylor s negative or purposive freedom, Hegel s institutional freedom, or Honneth s negative, reflexive, or communicative freedom). Autonomous freedom involves an acknowledgement of our creativity that can self-legislate categorical principles (see GMS, AA 04: 454, 6f to govern the application of that creativity even in a fashion contrary to our personal self-interest. As a consequence Kant, too, speaks of negative freedom, but he means it as a freedom that is not governed by physical causality alone. Conclusion Rather than seek to escape the conditions of possibility for our exercising of freedom, autonomous, creative freedom calls us to exercise our obligation as the goal of nature with moral responsibility. It would be a denial of our creative freedom and our status as human beings for 7

us in the name of freedom to reject the material world, our interests/appetites, our desire for status and prestige in the eyes of others, or our creative activity in the physical world. Assuming our place in the physical world, then, creative freedom commits us to technical and pragmatic imperatives (i.e., necessities), but these are possible only because we are beings who can exercise a categorical causality higher than nature in conformity with nature. When we exercise our categorical causality on the basis of self-legislated moral principles, we experience no higher satisfaction even when we fail in our aim and/or when we act contrary to our personal interests. Although it is not because moral principles interest us that they have moral validity. Rather, it is because they have moral validity that they interest us (Section III, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals). Unlike Berlin s and Taylor s negative freedom, then, autonomy is no arbitrary rejection of tradition, social orders, or institutions. Yet autonomous freedom is more than Taylor s purposive freedom as well as more than Hegel s and Honneth s communicative freedom capable of being accomplished only through social institutions. To be sure, creative freedom can only occur in a material world and under social conditions (e.g., the civic law and public institutions), but our autonomy raises us above them to assume personal responsibility for our decisions and actions that, in turn, not only enable us to generate and modify the civic law but also, most remarkably but also dangerously, enable us to transform nature. Autonomous, creative freedom affirms that the only freedom that we can possess is because we are in a physical world in communities. Yet, this places humanity in a precarious position: Here... we see philosophy put in fact in a precarious position, which is to be firm even though there is nothing in heaven or on earth from which it depends, or on which it is based. Here philosophy is to manifest its purity as sustainer of its own laws, not as herald of laws that an implanted sense or who knows what tutelary nature whispers to it, all of which -- though they may always be better than nothing at all -- can still never yield basic principles that reason dictates and that must have their source entirely and completely a priori and, at the same time, must have their commanding authority from this: that they expect nothing from the inclination of human beings but everything from the supremacy of the law and the respect owed to it or, failing this, condemn the human being to contempt for himself and inner abhorrence (GMS, AA 04: 425-6.32f). 8

Bibliography Berlin, Isaiah, Two Concepts of Liberty in Four Essays on Liberty, London: Oxford University Press, 1969). Habermas, Jürgen, Kommunikatives Handeln und detranszendentalisierte Vernunft (Stuttgart: Philipp Reclam, 2001). Zwischen Naturalismus und Religion. Philosophische Aufsätze (Frankfurt a.m.: Suhrkamp Verlag, 2005) Höffe, Otfried, Can Virtue Make Us Happy? The Art of Living and Morality, trans. by Douglas McGaughey (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2010). Honneth, Axel, Das Recht der Freiheit. Grundriß einer demokratischen Sittlichkeit (Berlin: Suhrkamp Verlag, 2011) Hegel, G.W. F., Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts at http://www.zeno.org/philosophie/m/hegel,+georg+wilhelm+friedrich/grundlini en+der+philosophie+des+rechts Hume, David, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (Illinois: Open Court, 1963): Section 8.. A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978: 2.3.1.1-2 Kant, Immanuel, Critique of Pure Reason (New York: St. Martin s Press, 1929). Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. by Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008). Metaphysics of Morals, trans. By Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003). Metaphysik Mrongovius. In Kant s Vorlesungen von der Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen. Vol. VI. Supplement II. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co., 1983.. Reflexionen Kants zur Anthropologie, Vol. II, Benno Erdmann ed. (Leipzig: Fues s Verlag (R. Reisland), 1882). 9

. Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, Allen Wood and George di Giovanni, trans. Cambridge (Cambridge University Press, 2004).. Vorlesung zur Moralphilosophie. (1774/1775). Edited by Werner Stark and Manfred Kühn. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2004. Kobusch, Theo, Die Kultur des Humanen. Zur Idee der Freiheit in Humanismus: Sein kritisches Potential für Gegenwart und Zukunft, ed. by Adrian Holderegger (Fribourg: Academic Press, 2011) Kremer, Josef. Das Problem der Theodicee in der Philosophie und Literatur des 18. Jahrhunderts mit besonderer Rücksicht auf Kant und Schiller (Berlin: Verlag von Reuther & Reichard, 1909). Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, The Social Contract and Discourses, trans. by Rose M. Harrington (New York: G.P. Putnam s Sons, 1893) Sulzer, Johann George, Vermischte philosophische Schriften (Leipzig: Weidmanns Erben und Reich, 1773) Taylor, Charles, What s wrong with negative liberty in Philosophical Papers II (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985): 211-229. Tetens, Johann Nicolas, Philosophische Versuche über die menschliche Natur und ihre Entwickelung, Vol. II (Leipzig: Weidmanns Erben und Reich, 1777). Wollf, Karl. Einleitung. In Schillers Theodizee bis zum Beginn der Kantischen Studien mit einer Einleitung über das Theodizee-Problem in der Philosophie und Literatur des 18. Jahrhunderts (Leipzig: Haupt & Hammon, 1909): 1-111. 10