Kantianism: Objections and Replies Keith Burgess-Jackson 12 March 2017

Similar documents
Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

Kant. Deontological Ethics

Deontological Ethics. Kant. Rules for Kant. Right Action

Kant's Moral Philosophy

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Kantian Deontology - Part Two

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

A Categorical Imperative. An Introduction to Deontological Ethics

Categorical Imperative by. Kant

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

Deontological Ethics

Theological Voluntarism: Objections and Replies Keith Burgess-Jackson 7 January 2017

Lecture 6 Kantianism. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

To link to this article:

An Epistemological Assessment of Moral Worth in Kant s Moral Theory. Immanuel Kant s moral theory outlined in The Grounding for the Metaphysics of

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics.

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

38 Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. [Ak 4:422] [Ak4:421]

On the Rawlsian Anthropology and the "Autonomous" Account

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2013 Russell Marcus

The Role of Love in the Thought of Kant and Kierkegaard

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Spring 2011 Russell Marcus

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

Deontology. Immanuel Kant ( ) Founder of Deontology

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1

IMMANUEL KANT Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals [Edited and reduced by J. Bulger, Ph.D.]

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas

(naturalistic fallacy)

Philosophy 110W: Introduction to Philosophy Spring 2011 Class 26 - April 29 Kantian Ethics. Hamilton College Russell Marcus

Kant, Deontology, & Respect for Persons

DEONTOLOGICAL ETHICS

Foundations of Bioethics

Is Morality Rational?

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

INTENTIONALITY, NORMATIVITY AND COMMUNALITY IN KANT S REALM OF ENDS

Lecture Notes Rosalind Hursthouse, Normative Virtue Ethics (1996, 2013) Keith Burgess-Jackson 4 May 2016

Animals in the Kingdom of Ends

Humanities 4: Lectures Kant s Ethics

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

NOTES. CPR CPrR G MM 8. G G G 389.

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

A primer of major ethical theories

REASONS AND REFLECTIVE ENDORSMENT IN CHRISTINE KORSGAARD S THE SOURCES OF NORMATIVITY ERIC C. BROWN. (Under the direction of Melissa Seymour-Fahmy)

Aristotle's Theory of Friendship Tested. Syra Mehdi

Download: Two clips from Star Trek. The needs of the many and The needs of the one found in Course Content Kant folder.

Kant's Rational Ethics

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

CMSI Handout 3 Courtesy of Marcello Antosh

ON THE INCOMPATIBILITY BETWEEN ARISTOTLE S AND KANT S IMPERATIVES TO TREAT A MAN NOT AS A MEANS BUT AS AN END-IN- HIMSELF

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation. Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Desert-Adjusted Utilitarianism, People, and Animals Jean-Paul Vessel New Mexico State University Eastern APA 2017

Ethical Theories. A (Very) Brief Introduction

Some Ethical Theories

Mill s Utilitarian Theory

Agency and Responsibility. According to Christine Korsgaard, Kantian hypothetical and categorical imperative

Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Keywords: Universalizability, Universal Law, Categorical Imperative, Maxim, Kant

The Formula of Humanity as an End in Itself

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

Ethics Prof. Vineet Sahu Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology-Kanpur

KANT S EXAMPLES. Robert Paul Wolff. Introduction, David Stewart

The Pleasure Imperative

NOTE ON KANT'S GROUNDWORK, PP PHILOSOPHY 13 FALL, 2004 Dick Arneson

Ethical Consistency and the Logic of Ought

My project in this paper is to reconsider the Kantian conception of practical reason. Some

RESPECT TOWARDS ELDERLY DEMENTED PATIENTS

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

What Is Wrong with Kant s Four Examples

Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals

World-Wide Ethics Chapter Five Deontology

Autonomous Machines Are Ethical

Dignity, Contractualism and Consequentialism

Zimmerman, Michael J. Subsidiary Obligation, Philosophical Studies, 50 (1986):

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 5 points).

The Role of Sympathy in Kant s Philosophy of Moral Education

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

Kantian Constructivism, Baseball and Christian Ethics. part of it, about physics, about morality or some of its parts, about reasons or normativity.

Constructivism, Intrinsic Normativity, and the Motivational Analysis Argument

The Human Deficit according to Immanuel Kant: The Gap between the Moral Law and Human Inability to Live by It. Pieter Vos 1

Finding Obligations Within Second-Personal Engagement: A Critique of Christine. Korsgaard's Normative Theory. A thesis presented to.

How to Apply the Categorical Imperative

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Transcription:

Kantianism: Objections and Replies Keith Burgess-Jackson 12 March 2017 Kantianism (K): 1 For all acts x, x is right iff (i) the maxim of x is universalizable (i.e., the agent can will that the maxim of x become a universal law) 2 and (ii) x manifests respect for persons (i.e., the agent, in performing x, uses humanity including the agent always as end and never merely as means). 3 Commentary: Kant formulated the Categorical Imperative his name for the supreme principle of morality in three different ways, claiming that The three ways... are... fundamentally only so many formulas of precisely the same law.... 4 The problem is that Kant s formulas don t seem to express the same law. Perhaps he meant that the formulas are extensionally equivalent to one another, i.e., that they generate the same results. Another possibility is that one of the formulas the Formula of Universal Law supplies the form of a moral judgment, while another the Formula of Humanity supplies its material. 5 In what follows, we shall assume that K expresses Kant s normative ethical theory. K says two things: first, that there are two individually necessary conditions for rightness, namely, universalizability and respectfulness of persons; and second, that the two conditions (universalizability and respectfulness of persons) are jointly sufficient 1 Also known as Kantian Ethics and the Ethic(s) of Respect for Persons. The theory is named for its originator, Immanuel Kant (1724-1804). 2 As Kant puts it, Act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it become a universal law. Immanuel Kant, Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals (1785). This is known as the Universal-Law Formulation of the Categorical Imperative (or the Formula of Universal Law). 3 As Kant puts it, Act so that you use humanity, as much in your own person as in the person of every other, always at the same time as end and never merely as means. Ibid. This is known as the End-in-Itself Formulation of the Categorical Imperative (or the Formula of Humanity). 4 Ibid. (ellipsis added). 5 Kant suggests as much when he writes: All maxims have... (1) a form, which consists in universality, and then the formula of the moral imperative is expressed thus: That the maxims must be chosen as if they are supposed to be valid as universal laws of nature ; (2) a matter, namely an end, and then the formula says: That the rational being, as an end in accordance with its nature, hence as an end in itself, must serve for every maxim as a limiting condition of all merely relative and arbitrary ends ; (3) a complete determination of all maxims through that formula, namely That all maxims ought to harmonize from one s own legislation into a possible realm of ends as a realm of nature. Ibid. (italics in original). 1

for rightness. 6 It follows that (1) if the maxim of one s act is not universalizable, then one s act is not right; (2) if one s act does not manifest respect for persons, then one s act is not right; and (3) if (a) the maxim of one s act is universalizable and (b) one s act manifests respect for persons, then (c) one s act is right. There are two ways for a maxim to fail to be universalizable: first, the maxim may be incapable of becoming a universal law; and second, even if the maxim is capable of becoming a universal law, the agent may be unable to will that it become a universal law. Kant gives two examples of maxims that are incapable of becoming universal laws: committing suicide and making a lying promise. He gives two examples of maxims that are capable of becoming universal laws but which cannot be willed (by the agent) to become universal laws: letting one s talents rust and refraining from helping others. Here is how a Kantian reasons: The maxim of act a (e.g., committing suicide or making a lying promise) is incapable of becoming a universal law; therefore, the maxim of a is not universalizable; therefore, according to K, a is not right. The maxim of act a (e.g., letting one s talents rust or refraining from helping others) is capable of becoming a universal law, but the agent is unable to will that it become a universal law; therefore, the maxim of a is not universalizable; therefore, according to K, a is not right. An act manifests respect for persons when no person affected by the act (including the agent) is treated as a mere means to the agent s ends. An act fails to manifest respect for persons when at least one person affected by the act (including the agent) is treated as a mere means to the agent s ends. To treat a person (including oneself) as a mere means to one s ends is to treat the person as a means to one s ends without at the same time treating the person as an end in himself or herself. 6 Suppose Kant is correct that the two conditions (i and ii) are merely different ways of expressing the same moral law. Then K is harmlessly redundant. Now suppose Kant is incorrect, and that the two conditions are not merely different ways of expressing the same moral law. Then presumably an act must satisfy both conditions in order to be right. On either supposition, K can be taken to express Kant s view. 2

According to David O. Brink, a Kantian moral theory... attempts to explain our obligations in terms of what a rational being as such would will. David O. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, Cambridge Studies in Philosophy, ed. Sydney Shoemaker (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 251. The Animals Objection: 1. K implies that there are no direct duties to animals. 2. There are direct duties to animals. accepts premise 1, but rejects premise 2. (This is known as biting the bullet.) According to Kant, while there are no direct duties to animals, there are indirect duties. He writes: Our duties towards animals are merely indirect duties towards humanity. Animal nature has analogies to human nature, and by doing our duties to animals in respect of manifestations which correspond to manifestations of human nature, we indirectly do our duty towards humanity. 7 Commentary: Biting the bullet means sticking with one s theory even when it has implications that one finds it painful to accept. The term biting the bullet may be inapt here, because Kant probably didn t feel any pain in saying that there are no direct duties to animals. Since, in his view, animals are not rational, they have no inherent worth, value, or dignity. The Counterintuitive-Consequences Objection I: 7 Immanuel Kant, Lectures on Ethics, trans. Louis Infield, The Library of Religion and Culture, ed. Benjamin Nelson (New York: Harper & Row, 1963 [first published in 1930]), 239. 3

1. K implies that the investor 8 does not act rightly in withdrawing all his money from the bank. 2. The investor acts rightly in withdrawing all his money from the bank. accepts premises 2 (presumably) and 4, but rejects premise 1. (This is known as grasping the bull by the horn.) It s not clear, however, how the Kantian can reject premise 1. Perhaps the maxim of the investor s act is incorrectly stated. Perhaps the correct statement of the maxim is universalizable. Unfortunately, Kant never told us how to distinguish between correct and incorrect statements of maxims. Fred Feldman, who devised this objection, concludes that there is a very deep problem 9 with Kant s theory. Commentary: The problem here is that an innocent act i.e., an act that is intuitively right turns out to be wrong because its maxim is not universalizable. The fact that its maxim is not universalizable, however, has nothing to do with morality. The Counterintuitive-Consequences Objection II: 1. K implies that the borrower 10 acts rightly in ignoring his debt. 8 The maxim of the investor s act is, When the Stock Market Index reaches 1000, I shall withdraw all my money from the bank. Fred Feldman, Introductory Ethics (Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1978), 116. 9 Ibid., 117. 10 Suppose a student has borrowed $9.81 from his roommate, and is considering whether he should repay it. He finds it impossible to universalize the maxim, When you have borrowed money, don t repay. But there are somewhat more specific maxims, which he can equally well regard as the maxims of his act. He happens upon this one: Whenever one student in a small coeducational college borrows exactly $9.81 from another student who is his roommate, and on the day of the loan the borrower is exactly ----- years old (corresponding to his own age), and the creditor is exactly ----- years old, and the borrower s weight is exactly ----- and his height exactly -----, and the creditor s weight is exactly ----- and his height exactly -----, and if the borrower finds it very inconvenient to repay, then let him not repay 4

2. The borrower does not act rightly in ignoring his debt. accepts premises 2 and 4, but rejects premise 1. (This is known as grasping the bull by the horn.) The Kantian says that K does not imply that the borrower acts rightly in ignoring his debt, because, while the maxim of the act is universalizable, the act does not manifest respect for persons. In other words, the second necessary condition of rightness is not satisfied. the money. The student finds himself heartily in favor of universalizing this maxim. Hence, he concludes it is morally permissible to ignore the debt. Richard B. Brandt, Ethical Theory: The Problems of Normative and Critical Ethics (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1959), 34. 5