Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll

Similar documents
Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Philosophy A465: Introduction to Analytic Philosophy Loyola University of New Orleans Ben Bayer Spring 2011

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Constructing the World

Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #10]

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke. M.A. Thesis Proposal. Department of Philosophy, CSULB. 25 May 2006

In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a

Semantic Externalism, by Jesper Kallestrup. London: Routledge, 2012, x+271 pages, ISBN (pbk).

The Philosophy of Language. Quine versus Meaning

Ayer and the Vienna Circle

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

On Katz and Indeterminacy of Translation

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Theories of propositions

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

Ch V: The Vienna Circle (Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, and Otto Neurath)[title crossed out?]

Defending A Dogma: Between Grice, Strawson and Quine

Conceptual Analysis meets Two Dogmas of Empiricism David Chalmers (RSSS, ANU) Handout for Australasian Association of Philosophy, July 4, 2006

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

REFERENCE AND MODALITY. An Introduction to Naming and Necessity

Constructing the World, Lecture 4 Revisability and Conceptual Change: Carnap vs. Quine David Chalmers

Class #19: November 1 Two Dogmas of Empiricism

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Relativism and Indeterminacy of Meaning (Quine) Indeterminacy of Translation

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Although Quine is widely known as an influential critic of logical positivism, there is now a

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Wittgenstein s Logical Atomism. Seminar 8 PHIL2120 Topics in Analytic Philosophy 16 November 2012

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Philosophy Courses-1

Philosophy of Logic and Language (108) Comprehensive Reading List Robert L. Frazier 24/10/2009

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Kripke s Naming and Necessity. Against Descriptivism

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Quine on Holism and Underdetermination

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Philosophy Courses-1

A Fregean Look at Kripke s Modal Notion of Meaning

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Dumitrescu Bogdan Andrei - The incompatibility of analytic statements with Quine s universal revisability

Areas of Specialization and Competence Philosophy of Language, History of Analytic Philosophy

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Russell, Wittgenstein, and the Project for Analytic Philosophy Nikolay Milkov

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Chapter 31. Logical Positivism and the Scientific Conception of Philosophy

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

145 Philosophy of Science

Quine and the Vienna Circle

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

WILLARD VAN ORMAN QUINE

Varieties of Apriority

Wolfgang Spohn Fachbereich Philosophie Universität Konstanz D Konstanz

Constructing the World

LENT 2018 THEORY OF MEANING DR MAARTEN STEENHAGEN

Ever since W. V. O. Quine wrote his famous Two Dogmas of

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

CLASS PARTICIPATION IS A REQUIREMENT

Ryle on Systematically Misleading Expresssions

The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth

Chalmers on Epistemic Content. Alex Byrne, MIT

A Defence of Kantian Synthetic-Analytic Distinction

A Distinction between Science and Philosophy

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

WITTGENSTEIN ON EPISTEMOLOGICAL STATUS OF LOGIC 1

Bayesian Probability

Two Dogmas of Analytical Philosophy

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Christopher N. Foster Curriculum Vitae

The New Wittgenstein, ed. Alice Crary and Rupert Read, London and New York, 2000, pp. v + 403, no price.

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

A HUNDRED YEARS OF ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

Necessary Truth and Grammatical Propositions

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997)

Class #17: October 25 Conventionalism

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

V3301 Twentieth-Century Philosophy PHIL V TR 2:40pm-3:55pm- 516 Hamilton Hall - Fall Professor D. Sidorsky

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Metaphysics of Logical Realism *

Department of Philosophy. PHIL 3130 Contemporary British and American Philosophy Fall 2005 MWF 11:30 12:20, MacKinnon 228

Epistemology Naturalized

Analyticity PAUL ARTIN BOGHOSSIAN

The Indeterminacy of Translation: Fifty Years Later

Transcription:

Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll Columbia University Press: New York, 2000. 302pp, Hardcover, $32.50. Brad Majors University of Kansas The history of analytic philosophy is a troubled genre. Analytic philosophers have only recently shown an interest in their historical roots, and to date no one has succeeded in providing a historical account of the period (roughly) 1879-1960 which is both relatively complete and free from excessive bias. We have fine, historically sensitive studies of practically every major early figure (e.g. Kenny on Frege 1, Baldwin on Moore 2, Hylton on Russell 3, Coffa 4 and more recently Friedmann 5 on the positivists, and too many to mention on Wittgenstein, both early and late); but these do not provide, and don't purport to provide, systematic accounts of the historical interconnections and influences in question. We also have a couple of ostensible histories proper; but these are either too idiosyncratic (Dummett 6, Hacker 7 ) or too incomplete (Gross", Passmore 9 ) to fit the bill. Avrum Stroll has written a history of analytic philosophy which suffers from neither defect. He discusses, usually in some detail, the work of Frege, Moore, Russell, Schlick, Carnap, Austin, Ryle, Quine, Kripke, Marcus and both Wittgensteins. He also attempts to unearth influences and interrelations amongst these thinkers. It cannot be said, moreover, that his book suffers from any particular bias or radical perspective. In nearly every case he attempts (admirably) to meet the philosopher in question on the latter's own terms. Despite this, however, the book cannot be judged a success. In the course of this review I will indicate why this is so, beginning with more general reasons and proceeding to discussion of Stroll's section on Quine, to my mind the worst of the book's nine chapters. The main problem with the book is that it fails to illuminate. Certainly some of the discussions (e.g. of Austin and the later Wittgenstein) are competent and interesting; but for the most part the reader receives little more than some biographical data and stock summary of the position. 10 Stroll is not without talent as an Auslegung, Vol. 25, No. 1

88 AUSLEGUNG expositor, and much of the biographical information is very enjoyable to read. However, in those cases in which he does attempt to go beyond this quite basic exercise, he fails. I'll give two examples (but see further below on Quine). First, in a chapter entitled "Logical Positivism and the Tractatus" Stroll wonders why given the mystical nature of the remarks near the end of the early Wittgenstein's opus and the apparent incompatibility between these and the metaphysics of logical atomism, Wittgenstein didn't just start over and write a new book (63)". This is an odd question. It might make some sense if Stroll were to demonstrate, and not assume, that there is a conflict between Wittgenstein's metaphysics and his mysticism. Second, Stroll notes the sad fact that Austin died at the height of his powers, in his late forties. He goes on to speculate about how philosophy might have been different had Austin lived for another twenty or thirty years. "My own guess is that its consequences would have been momentous and that the course of mainstream philosophy would have been radically different"(166). This conjecture belies a failure to understand the limited scope of Austin's influence. Stroll recognizes Quine's status as the most influential living philosopher, and accordingly devotes an entire chapter to his work. The discussion centers on Quine's rejection of the analytic/synthetic distinction, his behaviorism, and his epistemological naturalism. So far so good. But already in the opening biographical remarks we've got problems. Stroll notes, correctly, that Quine's 500- page autobiography amounts in general to little more than a travel diary. He says truly that Quine's work seems to him the most important thing in his life. He then draws conclusions which are nothing short of absurd. "Because his inward life is everything, his outward life is as solitary as a monk's";"... in a way Quine is a solipsist... a practical solipsist who isolates himself from [the world]"; "Der Mann ist seiner Arbeit"( 186). On the following page Stroll notes an even "greater mystery. Why would a solipsist write not one but two autobiographies?" This entire discussion is silly and a complete waste of time. Stroll distinguishes in Quine's work what he calls 'three successive phases', but then notes that the stages don't follow temporally upon one another (the first, 'logic' phase, is said to begin

BOOK REVIEWS 89 in 1934 and end in 1970; the third, 'epistemological' stage "commences in 1951"!) One wonders what 'successive' and 'phase' mean in Stroll's idiolect. We come finally to the substantive criticism of Quine. I will focus on four of Stroll's charges. First, he claims that Quine thinks there are no numbers (181, 188). This is easy to refute; it is just false. For at least the last forty years, and in publications Stroll himself mentions and quotes from, Quine has been an unrepentant platonist about mathematical entities. Second, he notes that Quine adheres to scientism. "So the question for him is whether scientific theory requires the existence of various kinds of abstract entities. His naturalism tells him that it does not"(201, his emphasis). As should be obvious to any reader of Quine, his concern is not with abstractness as such; it is with criteria of identity. Sets are abstract, and their identity criterion is as clear as could be. 'Two' sets are identical iff they have the same members. Propositions, attributes, and other intensional rodents are abstract as well, but lack clear criteria of identity. Quine keeps sets and dispenses with the rest. Third, Stroll thinks he has a devastating objection to Quine's indeterminacy semantics. "Quine thinks that we can identify what an utterance means with an auditor's reaction to it. But this thesis is susceptible to a serious objection. For an auditor to respond to an utterance, he must already understand what it means"(205). Quine does not think, nor has he ever said, that we can identify utterance meaning with audience reaction. Stroll is confusing, among other things, the intuitive notion of meaning, which Quine thinks is more-or-less useless, with the proposed notion of stimulusmeaning, which is not meant to replace the intuitive notion in every context. The final charge from Stroll I'll consider here is that he thinks he sees an inconsistency within Quine's treatment of the analytic-synthetic distinction (206-207). The criticism is familiar from Boghossian (so at least here Stroll is in good company). At times it seems as if Quine is saying that there are no analytic sentences; at other times he appears to claim merely that the a/s distinction is not clear. Stroll and Boghossian think the two claims are in conflict, and it isn't difficult to see why - if the predicate 'is analytic' is unclear, then how could we know what, if anything, is in its extension?

90 AUSLEGUNG The fallacy is in thinking that Quine's two claims, and I admit that he does say or imply both, are made on the same methodological level. A more perspicuous way of making his point would be to note first that the analytic/synthetic distinction is fatally unclear (it is crucial to note that clarity, at least for Quine, is a matter of degree); we can make no sense of it save by assuming the notions of meaning, synonymy or necessity, and the members of this ill-begotten triad are not one jot clearer than is analyticity. And second, it is to be pointed out that, in any case, there are no analytic sentences. Quine's commitments to extensionalism and to pragmatism sometimes come into conflict; e.g., propositional attitude contexts are woefully unclear, but we cannot practically get on without them. If the notion of analyticity (or necessity or synonymy) were likewise to be shown indispensable, Quine would tolerate its relative unclarity. However, we can do quite well without analyticity; indeed as Duhem showed recalcitrant data can be accommodated in sundry ways, and Quine takes this to demonstrate that sentences don't possess significance individually and that any can be revised. Now this argument assumes that any adequate notion of analyticity will entail incorrigibility; if you want a notion of analyticity according to which we might revise an analytic statement (such as Boghossian's epistemic conception), you're well advised to drop the word 'analytic' and take up instead 'a priori'. The latter can do the work needed without misleading the reader. In summary, while Stroll makes an honest effort at a hard and demanding task, his book in the end just isn't competent. The history of analytic philosophy has yet to be written. Notes 1 Frege (Penguin, 1995). 2 G.E. Moore (Routledge, 1990). 3 Russell, Idealism and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy (Oxford University Press, 1990). 4 The Semantic Tradition from Kant to Carnap (Cambridge University Press, 1991). 5 Reconsidering Logical Positivism (Cambridge University Press, 1999).

BOOK REVIEWS 91 6 Origins of Analytical Philosophy (Harvard University Press, 1994). Dummett's book is idiosyncratic in that he devotes far more attention to Husserl than to Russell and Moore combined. This is of course a consequence of Dummett's notion of what analytic philosophy consists in. 7 Wittgenstein's Place in 20"' Century Philosophy (Blackwells, 1996). Hacker's book, despite its rather narrow title, does purport to be, inter alia, some sort of general history. But it fails because of his radical Wittgensteinian outlook. 8 Analytic Philosophy (Western Publishing Co., 1970). Gross gives almost no attention to Frege, and stops short of considering Quine's full impact. Both of these faults are understandable given the time at which it was written. 9 One Hundred Years of Philosophy (Duckworth, 1957); Recent Philosophers (Open Court, 1985). The combination of Passmore's two books (the latter beginning as an appendage to the former) comes closest to success here. The problem is that the first book doesn't restrict itself to analytic philosophy as such, and the second is too brief. I don't of course suggest that Passmore set out to write the sort of history whose absence I am lamenting. 10 There are within the book a couple of original contributions to the issues, but these are naive and poorly thought-out. Here is one characteristic argument: in the course of discussing the direct reference theories of Kripke and Putnam Stroll claims (235-6) that water is not identical to H 2 0 because ice is water and ice is not so identical. " All intratextual page references are to the book under review.