"Book Review: FRANKFURT, Harry G. On Inequality. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2015, 102 pp., $14.95 (hbk), ISBN

Similar documents
Rawls versus utilitarianism: the subset objection

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition

John Charvet - The Nature and Limits of Human Equality

On Inequality, by Harry G. Frankfurt. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 2015, 120 pages, ISBN:

Equality of Capacity AMARTYA SEN

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Peter Singer, Famine, Affluence, and Morality

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

factors in Bentham's hedonic calculus.

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

Haberdashers Aske s Boys School

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

Andrei Marmor: Social Conventions

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS

A Rate of Passage. Tim Maudlin

The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

The Concept of Testimony

Contemporary moral issues

From Rawlsian Autonomy to Sufficient Opportunity Liam Shields

Some remarks regarding the regularity model of cause in Hume and Kant

Zdenko Kodelja HOW TO UNDERSTAND EQUITY IN HIGHER EDUCATION? (Draft)

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

Philosophy Pathways Issue nd October

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

IN DEFENSE OF AN ANIMAL S RIGHT TO LIFE. Aaron Simmons. A Dissertation

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords


Liberty of Ecological Conscience

World Hunger and Poverty

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

What God Could Have Made

HUME AND HIS CRITICS: Reid and Kames

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

7AAN2011 Ethics. Basic Information: Module Description: Teaching Arrangement. Assessment Methods and Deadlines. Academic Year 2016/17 Semester 1

David Ethics Bites is a series of interviews on applied ethics, produced in association with The Open University.

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

Immortality Cynicism

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 2. Background Material for the Exercise on Inference Indicators

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

THE RELATION BETWEEN THE GENERAL MAXIM OF CAUSALITY AND THE PRINCIPLE OF UNIFORMITY IN HUME S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

Political Science 103 Fall, 2018 Dr. Edward S. Cohen INTRODUCTION TO POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

B. C. Johnson. General Problem

e x c e l l e n c e : an introduction to philosophy

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

Skepticism and Internalism

A Social Practice View of Natural Rights. Word Count: 2998

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich

INTRODUCTION TO THINKING AT THE EDGE. By Eugene T. Gendlin, Ph.D.

Phenomenal Consciousness and Intentionality<1>

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

Bartolomé De Las Casas Essay Series

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

in Social Science Encyclopedia (Routledge, forthcoming, 2006). Consequentialism (Blackwell Publishers, forthcoming, 2006)

Against Against Intellectual Property: a Short Refutation of Meme Communism

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Common Sense: A Contemporary Defense By Noah Lemos Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. xvi

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument

ON THE TRUTH CONDITIONS OF INDICATIVE AND COUNTERFACTUAL CONDITIONALS Wylie Breckenridge

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

Transcription:

"Book Review: FRANKFURT, Harry G. On Inequality. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2015, 102 pp., $14.95 (hbk), ISBN 9780691167145." 1 Andrea Luisa Bucchile Faggion Universidade Estadual de Londrina - Filosofia Rodovia Celso Garcia Cid Pr 445 Km 380 Campus Universitário Cx. Postal 10.011 CEP 86.057-970 Londrina - PR, Londrina 86057-970 Brazil andreafaggion@gmail.com Article info CDD: 501 Received: 10.10.2016; Revised: 00.00.0000; Accepted: 22.10.2016 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1590/0100-6045.2016.v39n3.af Keywords: Inequality ABSTRACT On Inequality is a short book that skillfully handles a challenging topic. As its title suggests, its focus is a major theme in contemporary theories of justice: equality. Contrary to what one might expect, however, Frankfurt's critique of equality is not grounded in libertarian arguments or an ideal of the minimal state. Rather, it aims to clarify a cluster of alleged conceptual confusions about equality as a constitutive moral value. Frankfurt begins by making a familiar point against the imposition of strict economic equality: Inequality of incomes might be decisively eliminated [ ] just by arranging that all incomes be equally below the poverty line (p. 3). We should not infer from this, however, that Frankfurt reduces egalitarianism to economic egalitarianism, a trend of thought that argues for a brand of equality according to which everybody enjoys the same wealth. 1 Except where otherwise indicated, all references are to this text and are noted parenthetically.

246 Andrea Luisa Bucchile Faggion Moreover, Frankfurt s refusal to grant moral relevance to equality as such does not entail that he does not regard poverty as a moral problem. This is why he replaces egalitarianism with a doctrine of sufficiency the doctrine that what is morally important with regard to money is that everyone should have enough (p. 7) which also proscribes economic gluttony (p. 3). According to Frankfurt, egalitarianism misconstrues the real challenge of reducing poverty and excessive affluence (p. 4). Indeed, Frankfurt suggests that most people agree with him on this; what we really find repugnant when we express disapproval of inequality is another feature of the situation: the fact that some people have too little (p. 40). However we determine the concept of sufficiency, it is not a comparative concept. In other words, according to Frankfurt, the amount of money available to others is not directly relevant to determining what is needed for a certain kind of life (p. 10). Thus, instead of focusing on alleged conflicts between the pursuit of equality and freedom, Frankfurt emphasizes what he considers a form of moral disorientation caused by the pursuit of equality. The pursuit of equality as a good in itself distracts us from what is truly significant (p. 13). Frankfurt is willing to admit that the concept of having enough is hardly precise: [I]t is far from self-evident precisely what the doctrine of sufficiency means, and what applying it entails (p. 15). When he returns to the question What does it mean for a person to have enough? he notes that the assertion that a person has enough entails only that a requirement has been met, not that a limit has been reached. In other words, it s not bad to have more than enough (p. 47). Certainly, the main problem is how to specify the content of such a requirement, especially if one keeps in mind that this content entails claims of justice to be addressed by public policies. What counts in this specification? Is it the attitudes people actually have about the issue, or the attitudes it would be reasonable for them to have (p. 99, n. 15)? If the latter, what criterion of reasonableness would be useful here? Frankfurt rejects the possibility that sufficiency is related to having enough to avoid misery (p. 49), which would be the only easy way to determine a pattern of sufficiency. The above questions are thus as difficult as they are important. They are also questions, however, that go beyond the limits of Frankfurt s essay. In this work, Frankfurt merely warns against

On Inequality 247 hastily adopting an inadequate alternative in the face of the difficulties associated with the doctrine of sufficiency (p. 15). Frankfurt emphasizes that his interest is analytical rather than political (p. 65). In the end, however, it will seem obvious to some that Frankfurt s doctrine of sufficiency risks ultimately being much less economically feasible than egalitarianism if developed as a theory of justice even if Frankfurt is right about the fact that this does not count as a reason to adopt egalitarianism. Indeed, this does not even count against the claim that what lurks behind our disapproval of inequality is really the ideal of sufficiency. With this noted, what really matters here is whether Frankfurt is right about its being unreasonable for someone to be unsatisfied about her life only because her standard of living is bellow that of others (p. 73). In other words, is equality an important component of sufficiency itself? Would it be unreasonable to be unsatisfied with your life if everyone else were at least ten times wealthier than you? Some will understandably doubt Frankfurt s take on this issue. Still on the topic of economic equality, Frankfurt considers arguments based on marginal utility, according to which economic equality would maximize the aggregate satisfaction of members of society. The idea is that the marginal utility of money necessarily diminishes for the wealthy, and thus that the redistribution of income and wealth provides money to those for whom it has more marginal utility. An argument along these lines is presented by Abba Lerner, who is quoted by Frankfurt as follows: The principle of diminishing marginal utility of income can be derived from the assumption that consumers spend their income in the way that maximizes the satisfaction they can derive from the good obtained. With a given income, all the things bought give a greater satisfaction for the money spent on them than any of the other things that could have been bought in their place but were not bought for this very reason. From this it follows that if income were greater the additional things that would be bought with the increment of income would be things that are rejected when income is smaller because they give less satisfaction; and if income were greater still, even less satisfactory things could be bought. The greater the income, the less satisfactory are the additional things that can be bought with equal increases of income. That is all that is meant by the principle of the diminishing marginal utility of income. (qtd. on p. 28)

248 Andrea Luisa Bucchile Faggion Frankfurt s first reply to this kind of argument is grounded in his concept of a threshold effect. The satisfaction obtained via the purchase of the last item in a series may be greater than the satisfaction obtained by purchasing the other items because the last item represents the crossing of a threshold. The experience of collectors illustrates this point. Frankfurt s second reply involves the refusal to accept Lerner s assumption that if a consumer refrains from obtaining a certain good until his income increases, this necessarily means that he rejects it when his income is lower (p. 32). According to Frankfurt, even where a consumer does not save money to purchase a certain good, this doesn t necessarily mean that he rejects that good and prefers the good he actually purchases. The consumer may regard saving for a particular purchase as pointless because he believes that he will not be able to save enough money within an acceptable period of time (p. 97, n. 10). Thus Frankfurt claims that it is not the case that economic egalitarianism maximizes aggregate utility in society. Indeed, Frankfurt believes that an egalitarian distribution may minimize aggregate utility in certain circumstances: [W]hen resources are scarce, so that it is impossible for everyone to have enough, an egalitarian distribution may lead to disaster (p. 36). Frankfurt s example is a situation in which there is enough medicine and food to enable some members of a population to survive but where an equal distribution of these resources would result in nobody s receiving enough, and thus in everybody s death (p. 34). This line of thought is reminiscent of theories of justice according to which justice is meaningless in contexts of extreme scarcity and abundance (see, for instance, Hume, 2006, p. 93-94). Frankfurt is thus open to the objection that it is not only egalitarianism but indeed any conception of justice that would be inapplicable in such circumstances. With the above noted, the ideal of equal respect and concern is much more relevant to contemporary theories of justice than strict economic equality. The most important part of Frankfurt s book is therefore his analytical attempt to illustrate what he takes to be a conceptual confusion at the root of this ideal: Enjoying the rights that it is appropriate for a person to enjoy, and being treated with appropriate consideration and concern, have

On Inequality 249 nothing essentially to do with the consideration and concern that other people are shown or with the respect or rights that other people happen to enjoy. Every person should be accorded the rights, the respect, the consideration, and the concern to which he is entitled by virtue of what he is and what he has done. The extent of his entitlement to them does not depend on whether or not other people are entitled to them as well. (p. 75) Frankfurt s point perhaps echoing Aristotle is that philosophers like Dworkin (see, for instance, 1985 and 2011) have mistaken the moral requirement to be impartial or avoid arbitrariness for the moral requirement to treat people with equal respect and concern: To avoid arbitrariness, we must treat likes alike and unlikes differently. This is no more an egalitarian principle than it is an inegalitarian one (p. 101, n. 3). Importantly, Frankfurt is not denying that there are rights that belong to every human being by virtue of their humanity. Where this is the case, however, your having the right in question is not grounded in a principle of equal treatment. Your right is explained by your having a characteristic that others also have. In other words, impartiality requires us to treat equals as equals, but it doesn t require of us that we view everybody as equal. According to standard contemporary conceptions of justice, equality is not to be embraced no matter what the circumstances. On the standard egalitarian view, equality is more like an original position, for which justifications are unnecessary and from which divergences must be justified. Nonetheless, if Frankfurt is right, equality is not this species of moral position by default, or a constitutive moral principle. It is necessary to argue for the requirement of equal treatment (by showing that there are no relevant differences between two persons, for instance) (p. 77-78). To sustain his thesis, Frankfurt challenges a scenario made famous by Berlin. It s worth reproducing the passage quoted by Frankfurt in full: The assumption is that equality needs no reason, only inequality does so If I have a cake and there are ten persons among whom I wish to divide it, then if I give exactly one tenth to each, this will not, at any rate automatically, call for justification; whereas if I depart from this principle of equal division I am expected to produce a special reason. (qtd. on p. 80)

250 Andrea Luisa Bucchile Faggion Frankfurt claims that it is not the moral priority of equality that explains why we should divide Berlin s cake into equal shares. In Frankfurt s view, the key feature of the situation is the lack of relevant information. If a distributor has no information at all about those among whom she is to distribute something, this amounts to a situation in which each person is identical to the others. This is why the cake should be divided into equal shares: It is the moral importance of respect, and hence of impartiality, rather than of any supposedly prior or preemptive moral importance of equality, that constrains us to treat people the same when we know nothing that provides us with a special reason for treating them differently. (p. 81) It is true that Frankfurt s point here looks like a dispute about words, since both Frankfurt and the egalitarian agree that Berlin s cake should ultimately be divided into equal shares. Yet the implications of Frankfurt s point are highly relevant. If equality on its own cannot justify, say, a rights claim, then the discussion is really about entitlement. The concept of entitlement is generally neglected in contemporary philosophical debates about social justice. It s as if the resources discussed in these debates appeared from nowhere, such that the only relevant issue is whether there is justification for departing from a policy of equal distribution such as differences between conceptions of the good, as in Dworkin (1985), or the fact that the cake diminishes when divided into equal shares, as in Rawls (1999). Against this background, Frankfurt s essay is a breath of fresh air for contemporary philosophy. References DWORKIN, RONALD. A Matter of Principle. Cambridge, Massachusetts; London, England: Harvard University Press, 1985. Justice for Hedgehogs. Cambridge, Massachusetts; London, England: Harvard University Press, 2011.

On Inequality 251 HUME, DAVID. Moral Philosophy. Ed. Geoffrey Sayre-McCord. Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company, 2006. RAWLS, JOHN. A Theory of Justice: Revised edition. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1999.