Berkeley s Ideas of Reflection

Similar documents
WEEK 1: CARTESIAN SCEPTICISM AND THE COGITO

Jonathan Dancy. Department of Philosophy The University of Reading The University of Texas at Austin. Abstract

How Berkeley Redefines Substance A Reply to My Critics

Chapter 16 George Berkeley s Immaterialism and Subjective Idealism

Idealism from A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Part I by George Berkeley (1720)

Every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it; and every simple impression a correspondent idea

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

Berkeley Studies. No. 25 (2014)

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

History (101) Comprehensive Reading List Robert L. Frazier 24/10/2009

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2015

Class 18 - Against Abstract Ideas Berkeley s Principles, Introduction, (AW ); (handout) Three Dialogues, Second Dialogue (AW )

Idealism. Contents EMPIRICISM. George Berkeley and Idealism. Preview: Hume. Idealism: other versions. Idealism: simplest definition

Matter, God, and Nonsense

Was Berkeley a Rational Empiricist? In this short essay I will argue for the conclusion that, although Berkeley ought to be

History of Modern Philosophy Fall nd Paper Assignment Due: 11/8/2019

Lahore University of Management Sciences. PHIL 213: HISTORY OF WESTERN PHILOSOPHY FROM DESCARTES TO KANT Fall

Hume's Functionalism About Mental Kinds

Certainty, Necessity, and Knowledge in Hume s Treatise

IS SHEPHERD S PEN MIGHTIER THAN BERKELEY S WORD? Samuel C. Rickless. [forthcoming in British Journal for the History of Philosophy] Abstract

1/8. Reid on Common Sense

CARTESIAN IDEA OF GOD AS THE INFINITE

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

Berkeley s Metaphysics and Epistemology between common sense and science Berkeleyho metafyzika a epistemologie mezi common sense a vědou

Berkeley, Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous focus on p. 86 (chapter 9) to the end (p. 93).

Lahore University of Management Sciences PHIL 213 HISTORY OF WESTERN PHILOSOPHY FROM DESCARTES TO KANT

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

Philosophy 428M Topics in the History of Philosophy: Hume MW 2-3:15 Skinner Syllabus

5AANA003 MODERN PHILOSOPHY II: LOCKE AND BERKELEY

1/10. Primary and Secondary Qualities and the Ideas of Substance

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Materialism and the Activity of Matter in Seventeenth-Century European Philosophy. Stewart Duncan. 23 May 2016

The Synthesis of Empiricism and Innatism in Berkeley s Doctrine of Notions

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2011

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

5AANA003 MODERN PHILOSOPHY II: LOCKE AND BERKELEY

Berkeley s Idealism A Reply to My Critics

Hume's Argument for the Ontological Independence of Simple Properties

The British Empiricism

2007, Lehrstuhl für "Philosophy o

Locke s and Hume s Theories of Personhood: Similarities and Differences. In this paper I will deal with the theories of personhood formulated by

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Superaddition and Miracles in Locke s Philosophy of Science and Metaphysics

Hume on Representation, Reason and Motivation. Rachel Cohon and David Owen

Berkeley s Philosophy of Religion

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

Tim Black. In the Treatise, Book I, Part iv, Section 2, Hume seeks to explain what causes us to believe that

Empiricism. HZT4U1 - Mr. Wittmann - Unit 3 - Lecture 3

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Chapter 4. The Categ~ry of Causation in Locke and Hume. 4.1 Introduction. In this chapter, we shall explain, examine and compare the category

DESCARTES ON THE OBJECTIVE REALITY OF MATERIALLY FALSE IDEAS

Early Modern Philosophy

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

BERKELEY S COMMON SENSE APPROACH TO LOCKE S THEORY OF INFERENTIAL KNOWLEDGE *

Classic Thinkers Series. J. M. Fritzman, Hegel Bernard Gert, Hobbes Dale E. Miller, J. S. Mill A. J. Pyle, Locke Andrew Ward, Kant

Hume's Representation Argument Against Rationalism 1 by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina/Chapel Hill

Instructor Information Larry M. Jorgensen Office: Ladd Hall, room Office Hours: Mon-Thu, 1-2 p.m.

Time 1867 words Principles of Philosophy God cosmological argument

New Chapter: Epistemology: The Theory and Nature of Knowledge

JANI HAKKARAINEN University of Tampere, Finland ABSTRACT

Kantian Realism. Jake Quilty-Dunn. Kantian Realism 75

Hume s Missing Shade of Blue as a Possible Key. to Certainty in Geometry

Locke, Arnauld, and Abstract Ideas *

Leibniz on mind-body causation and Pre-Established Harmony. 1 Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra Oriel College, Oxford

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

Propositional Revelation and the Deist Controversy: A Note

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

Did Locke Defend the Memory Continuity Criterion of Personal Identity?

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

Causation, Extrinsic Relations, and Hume s Second Thoughts about Personal Identity

Metaphysics. Gary Banham

Udo Thiel* The Early Modern Subject Revisited Responses to Barth, Lenz, Renz and Wunderlich

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE LET THOMAS AQUINAS TEACH IT. Joseph Kenny, O.P. St. Thomas Aquinas Priory Ibadan, Nigeria

CHAPTER III KANT S APPROACH TO A PRIORI AND A POSTERIORI

does. All reality is mental, consisting only of minds and their ideas. Ideas are passive, whereas minds are active. Every idea needs a mind to be in.

DESCARTES ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: AN INTERPRETATION AND DEFENSE

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

PHIL History of Modern Philosophy Spring 2016

Berkeley s Meta-Ontology: Bodies, Forces, and the Semantics of Exists

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at

5AANA005 Ethics II: History of Ethical Philosophy 2014/15. BA Syllabus

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2016

Class 17 - Three Arguments for Idealism Berkeley s Principles, 1-33 (AW ) Three Dialogues, First Dialogue (AW )

KNOWLEDGE AND OPINION IN ARISTOTLE

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

The Existence of Material Substance. A Response to George Berkeley s Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous. Philosophy 104

Introduction to Philosophy PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2017

Reid Against Skepticism

4.00 cr. Phone: (541) SYLLABUS*

Spinoza on the Essence, Mutability and Power of God

Kant s Misrepresentations of Hume s Philosophy of Mathematics in the Prolegomena

Hume, Causation and Subject Naturalism. as opposed to that of an object naturalist. Object naturalism involves the ontological

THE RELATION BETWEEN THE GENERAL MAXIM OF CAUSALITY AND THE PRINCIPLE OF UNIFORMITY IN HUME S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

1/9. Locke on Abstraction

Transcription:

The Berkeley Newsletter 17 (2006) 7 Berkeley s Ideas of Reflection Daniel E. Flage Does Berkeley countenance what Locke called ideas of reflection? 1 A common answer is that he does not, indeed that he cannot, 2 given that ideas cannot represent minds or operations of mind. 3 Even the seeming reference to ideas of reflection in the opening sentence of Principles, Part I has been viewed as an accidental reference that does not represent Berkeley s considered position. 4 In this paper I show that a significant body of textual evidence suggests Berkeley was committed to the existence of ideas of reflection. I argue that Luce s claim, One of his [Berkeley s] cardinal contentions, urged over and over again, is that there are no ideas of the mind and its operations. 5 is either trivially true or false, neither of which precludes a commitment to ideas of reflection. Finally, I argue that insofar as ideas are effects of 1 See John Locke, An Essay concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), II.i.2, p. 123. 2 See G. A. Johnson, The Development of Berkeley s Philosophy (New York: Russell and Russell, 1965, reprint of the 1923 edition), 143-44; T. E. Jessop, footnote to George Berkeley, A Treatise concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Part I, in The Works of George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne, ed. A. A. Luce and T. E. Jessop (9 vols.; London: Thomas Nelson and Sons, 1948-1957), 2:41n1; and editor s introduction, Works, 2:8-9. Cf. A. A. Luce, Berkeley s Immaterialism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1945), 39-40; James W. Cornman, Perception, Common Sense, and Science (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1975), 104; A. C. Grayling, Berkeley: The Central Arguments (LaSalle, IL: Open Court, 1986), 50; David Berman, George Berkeley: Idealism and the Man (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994), 21; George Berkeley, Philosophical Works: Including the Works on Vision, ed. Michael R. Ayers (London: Dent, 1975), 89n1; Robert Merrihew Adams, Introduction to his edition of George Berkeley, Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1979), xxiv; and William McGowan, Berkeley s Doctrine of Signs, in Berkeley: Critical and Interpretative Essays, ed. Colin Turbayne (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982), 232. This position is not universally granted. See G. Dawes Hicks, Berkeley (New York: Russell & Russell, 1932), 108; J. O. Urmson, Berkeley, in John Dunn, J. O. Urmson, and A. J. Ayer, The British Empiricists (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), 109; and George Pappas, Berkeley s Thought (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2000), 106. 3 See Berkeley, Principles of Human Knowledge, 25, 27, 89, 135, 139, 142, in Works: 2:51-52, 52-53,79-80, 103, 104-105, and 106; and George Berkeley, Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous, in Works, 2:231-234; Philosophical Commentaries 684, in Works, 1:83. Further references to the Principles, Part I (PHK) will be made parenthetically by section, as will references to the Introduction to the Principles (Intro.), the New Theory of Vision (NTV) and the Theory of Vision Vindicated (TVV). Parenthetical references to the Three Dialogues (DHP) will be to page numbers in volume 2 of the Works; and references to the Philosophical Commentaries (PC) will be by entry number. 4 E. J. Furlong, An Ambiguity in Berkeley s Philosophy, Philosophical Quarterly 14 (1964): 334-44; and I. C. Tipton, Berkeley: The Philosophy of Immaterialism (London: Methuen, 1974), 71-79. 5 Luce, Berkeley s Immaterialism, 40.

The Berkeley Newsletter 17 (2006) 8 immaterial substances, there would be a strict parity between ideas of sense and ideas of reflection. Taken together, these provide good reason to believe that the common claim that Berkeley rejected ideas of reflection (the negative thesis) is false. The opening sentence of Principles, Part I, reads: It is evident to any one who takes a survey of the objects of human knowledge, that they are either ideas actually imprinted on the senses, or else such as are perceived by attending to the passions and operations of the mind, or lastly ideas formed by help of memory and imagination, either compounding, dividing, or barely representing those originally perceived in the aforesaid ways. To anyone who approaches Berkeley from a Lockean context, it is natural to read such as are perceived by attending to the passions and operations of the mind as an allusion to ideas of reflection. If this were the only place Berkeley seems to allude to ideas of reflection, it might be plausible to suggest it was an accidental or ambiguous allusion. But there are other places where he explicitly refers to ideas of reflection. 6 In Principles 25, where he is discussing the passivity of ideas, Berkeley writes, But whoever shall attend to his ideas, whether of sense or reflexion, will not perceive in them any power or activity; there is therefore no such thing contained in them. In PHK 35 he alludes to apprehension by sense or reflexion. In PHK 68, where Berkeley is arguing that the notion of material substance proposed by the occasionalist is unintelligible, he says, Now I would fain know how any thing can be present to us, which is neither perceivable [my emphasis] by sense nor reflexion, nor capable of producing any idea in our minds, nor is at all extended, nor hath any form, nor exists in any place. Similarly, there seems to be an allusion to ideas of reflection in PHK 74: For what is there on our part, or what do we perceive amongst all the ideas, sensations, notions, which are imprinted on our minds, either by sense or reflexion, from whence may be inferred the existence of an inert, thoughtless, unperceived occasion? In PHK 89, where Berkeley is discussing the idea of his own mind, he writes, We comprehend our own existence by inward feeling or reflexion, and that of other spirits by reason (cf. DHP 233, NTV 23). The allusions to apprehension and perception suggest that what is perceived is an idea, which could only be an idea of reflection. The allusion to an inward feeling or reflexion suggests one is concerned with what Locke called ideas of reflection, since it is on the basis of such ideas that Locke claimed the mind and its states are known. Do these allusions to ideas of reflection show that Berkeley countenanced a distinction between ideas of sensation and ideas of reflection? No. It is possible that Berkeley, who is generally known for his care in expression, inadvertently or intentionally suggested a 6 Berkeley does not use reflection and reflexion univocally. Sometimes it refers to a property of light (cf. NTV 30). Sometimes it is synonymous with thinking about or reasoning about (cf. PC 656, 670, 724; NTV 20 51, 80, 131, 135; TVV 56, 63; Intro. 18; PHK 22, 50, 51, 149; most uses of reflexion in the Dialogues are in this sense; see, for example, DHP 197, 205, 212, 231, 248, 261). Sometimes, when he explicitly alludes to ideas of reflection, he seems merely to be matching his verbiage to the Lockean model he is discussing (cf. PC 571, 585; PHK 13). These I discount.

The Berkeley Newsletter 17 (2006) 9 distinction he did not accept. So the fact that Berkeley alludes to ideas of reflection at several points is, perhaps, only an anomaly for which the proponent of the negative thesis must provide a plausible account. Proponents of the negative thesis correctly acknowledge that Berkeley regularly claims that we have no ideas of minds and their operations. Luce put it this way: One of his cardinal contentions, urged over and over again, is that there are no ideas of [my emphasis] the mind and its operations. 7 But what does this mean? What is the sense of of? Is it the of of identity, the of representation, or the of of signification? If one is concerned with the of of identity, Luce was certainly correct. If one sees a red apple, the redness of the idea is identical with the redness of the apple insofar as the idea is a constitutive part of the apple (cf. PHK 1). In this sense, Berkeley clearly denies that one can have ideas of minds, insofar ideas are passive and minds are active (PHK 25 and 27). So, if there are ideas of reflection, they cannot be constitutive parts of minds; the of cannot be the of of identity. If one is concerned with the of of representation, Luce s claim is true but uninteresting. The likeness principle (PHK 8) maintains that an idea can be like nothing other than an idea. Since Berkeley construed ideational representation in terms of resemblance (cf. Intro. 11-12), the likeness principle is applicable across the board: Ideas of sensation can represent nothing other than ideas of sensation indeed, ideas of the same kind of sensation and if there were ideas of reflection, they could represent nothing other than resembling ideas of reflection. So, if Luce s claim concerns the of of representation, it is true but uninteresting: It tells one nothing that is peculiar to ideas of reflection. On the other hand, if Luce was concerned with the of of signification, there is reason to believe his claim is false. Only an idea of sight can resemble and thereby represent another idea of sight. But, as we learn from the New Theory of Vision, although ideas of sight and touch are distinct in kind, they can be associated in such a way that an idea of sight signifies an idea of touch. Indeed, there is little question that ideas of sensation, for example, can be taken to signify passions. For example, blushing can signify shame (NTV 65; cf. NTV 10, 23, Intro. 20). This suggests that the signification relation is quite broad. For example, effects of causal relations properly so called (as well as occasional relations, PHK 65) can signify their causes (cf. DHP 223, 231-232). So, if Berkeley countenanced ideas of reflection, they could signify, even if they could not represent, operations of mind. 8 7 Luce, Berkeley s Immaterialism, 40. 8 Typically Berkeley construes signification as a relation among ideas. Ideas of sight and touch are experienced together. As a result of this temporal association, ideas of sight are taken to signify ideas of touch. The same holds regarding the ideas of words and the objects they signify. If there are ideas of reflection, the signification relation rests on a different ground, since there are no ideas that are identical with operations of the mind. Nonetheless, if there is a necessary (causal) connection between ideas of reflection and operations of the mind, that should be sufficient for a signification relation, since the relation is stronger than temporal association.

The Berkeley Newsletter 17 (2006) 10 But the fact that the signification could provide an unproblematic relation between ideas of reflection and a mind does not, in itself, show that Berkeley countenanced ideas of reflection. If we must discount the textual allusions to ideas of reflection in the Principles, is there any remaining evidence that Berkeley granted that there are ideas of reflection? Yes. In PHK 27 (all editions) Berkeley writes, Such is the nature of spirit or that which acts, that it cannot be of it self perceived, but only by the effects which it produceth. The general topic of PHK 27 is knowledge of mind. The sentence appears after Berkeley explicitly claims that one cannot have an idea of mind, and before he claims one cannot have so much as a relative idea of mind. 9 If Berkeleian ideas of reflection are the effects of operations of the mind, they parallel Lockean ideas of reflection. As Locke wrote: In time the mind comes to reflect on its own operations about the ideas got by sensation, and thereby stores itself with a new set of ideas, which I call ideas of reflection. These are the impressions that are made on our senses by outward objects that are extrinsical to the mind, and its own operations, proceeding from powers intrinsical and proper to itself; which when reflected on by itself, become also objects of its contemplation, are, as I have said, the original of all knowledge. 10 What does that mean? If there is a Lockean parallel, then a particular kind of mental state or operation produces a particular kind of idea of reflection: Distinct operations of mind produce what Hume later called different feelings or sentiments. 11 For example, being angry feels different from being in love. If there are ideas of reflection, they are distinct from, but parallel to, ideas of sensation: Ideas of sensation are effects of a mind or minds 12 other than one s own; ideas of reflection are only effects of one s own mind. Indeed, the Berkeley of the Theory of Vision... Vindicated suggests that it is: In certain cases a sign may suggest its correlate as an image, in others as an effect, in others as a cause (TVV 39; cf. DHP 223). 9 Cf. PC 712, TVV 18, PHK 145, 147, DHP 240. In the second edition of the Principles, this is followed by the remark that we have notions of mind. I have argued elsewhere that such notions might well be relative. See Daniel E. Flage, Berkeley s Doctrine of Notions: A Reconstruction based on his Theory of Meaning (London: Croom Helm, 1987). 10 Essay II.i.24, p. 141, emphasis added. He later identifies some of the modes of ideas of reflection as Remembrance, Discerning, Reasoning, Judging, Knowledge, Faith (Essay II.vi.1, p. 159). 11 David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, 2 nd ed. rev. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978), 623-624, cf. 636; David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. David Fate Norton and Mary Norton, Oxford Philosophical Texts (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), Appendix para. 2, p. 396, cf. para. 22, p. 401. Cf. Berkeley, PHK 89. 12 Whether Berkeley held that finite minds can produce ideas in other finite minds is an issue that is beyond the scope of this paper.

The Berkeley Newsletter 17 (2006) 11 If Berkeley s position is that minds are known only by their effects, then ideas of reflection are immediately known, and minds whether one s own or the minds of others are only mediately known. One s notion of a mind or activity of a mind is that which causes x, where x is an idea or series of ideas. It is this type of consideration that Berkeley cites as the basis for introducing the notion of immaterial substance in Principles 26. There he is concerned with the cause of the succession and order of ideas of sensation. If one s own mind is also known only by its effects, then one s notion of a certain state of one s own mind is the cause of x. where x is an idea of reflection. 13 But it is one thing to say there is room in Berkeley s system for ideas of reflection insofar as they are caused by and signify operations of the mind. It is something else to claim that Berkeley was committed to the existence of ideas of reflection. Here are three points that favor attributing ideas of reflection to Berkeley. (1) If there were ideas of reflection, it would yield a parallelism between knowledge of external causes and knowledge of internal states as causes. As in Locke s philosophy, ideas of sensation would causally correlate to states of external substances, while ideas of reflection would causally correlate to internal states; unlike Locke, both causes would be immaterial. 14 (2) It would explain why Berkeley was frequently willing to use the expression ideas of reflexion. even why in the New Theory of Vision he went so far as to claim, And yet no sooner shall he behold that colour to arise in the face of another, but it brings into his mind the idea of that passion which hath been observed to accompany it (NTV 23, emphasis added). 15 And,(3) it would yield a strictly ideational reading of the opening sentence of 13 I have long been puzzled by Berkeley s remark at PHK 30 that The ideas of sense are more strong, lively, and distinct than those of the imagination and comparable allusions to degrees of force and vivacity in Hume. How can ideas, which are inherently inactive (PHK 25), be strong or lively? As far as I know, Berkeley never answers that question. Nonetheless, if Berkeley countenanced ideas of reflection, I believe there is a plausible answer to that question. The clue comes from Hume. As I have shown elsewhere [Daniel E. Flage, David Hume s Theory of Mind (London: Routledge, 1990), 68-86], Hume s descriptions of his favorite mental state, belief, change between the Treatise and the first Enquiry. While in the Treatise he generally takes force and vivacity to be a characteristic of a perception, in the Enquiry he suggests that it is a feeling that accompanies or is annexed to an idea of sensation or reflection. It is the idea of reflection marking belief or, perhaps, a number of resembling impressions of reflection, which correspond to degrees of belief that constitute the force and vivacity of the idea. If Berkeley countenanced ideas of reflection distinct ideas that correspond to distinct operations of mind this could provide the basis for giving an account of the liveliness and strength of an idea. Notice that such ideas would be distinct from ideas of sensation that might also accompany ideas of sensation, e.g. kinesthetic sensations when the eye focuses or the pressure in one s finger that occurs when one picks up a book. 14 This might explain the entry in Berkeley s notebooks: Mem: To begin the 1st Book not with mention of Sensation & Reflection but instead of those to use perception or thought in general (PC 571). 15 Notice, this passage suggests an idea of sense signifies an idea of the passion. If there are ideas of reflection, the idea of that passion would be understood as the idea arising as an effect of a certain passionate state of mind. If there are not ideas of reflection, it is difficult to understand what could be meant by the passage.

The Berkeley Newsletter 17 (2006) 12 the Principles, Part I. While none of these singly might be a sufficient reason to attribute ideas of reflection to Berkeley, they conjointly provide at least good circumstantial evidence that he was committed to the existence of ideas of reflection. Some are still likely to raise objections. One such might go as follows: Virtually everything you have said was based on the New Theory of Vision and the Principles of Human Knowledge. Comparable references to ideas of reflection are conspicuously missing in the Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous. Indeed, there Philonous is made to say, I know, that I who am a spirit or thinking substance, exist as certainly, as I know my ideas exist. Farther, I know what I mean by the terms I and myself; and I know this immediately, or intuitively, though I do not perceive it as I perceive a triangle, a colour, or a sound (DHP 231). This passage suggests that ideas of reflection are not needed to know oneself and one s states. Hence, there is still good reason to doubt that Berkeley was committed to ideas of reflection. There are two distinct issues here. The first concerns the Dialogues in general. The second concerns a specific passage from the Dialogues. If Berkeley was committed to the existence of ideas of reflection, why were they not mentioned in the Dialogues? One answer is that it might well have been beyond the scope of his interests to do so. If the Dialogues are nothing more than a popular reworking of the Principles, then one might expect the same distinctions would be found in the Dialogues that were found in the Principles. 16 But there is some reason to believe that Berkeley s focus was narrower in the Dialogues than in the Principles. In the Preface he indicated that the topics covered are farther pursued, or placed in different lights, and other points handled, which naturally tend to confirm and illustrate them (DHP 169) in the Principles and the New Theory of Vision. Further, his explicit objective was, in Philonous words, to examine which of us it is that denies the reality of sensible things, or professes the greatest ignorance of them; since, if I take you rightly, he is to be esteemed the greatest sceptic (DHP 173). That topic does not require a discussion of ideas of reflection. 17 16 Given other popular rewritings, however, such an expectation might be unwarranted. For example, although the distinction between perceptions of sensation and perceptions of reflection was prominent in Hume s Treatise, the distinction is all but ignored in the Enquiry concerning Human Understanding. See David Hume, An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, 3 rd ed. rev. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978), I.ii.5, p. 64; David Hume, An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, ed. Tom L. Beauchamp, Oxford Philosophical Texts (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), VII.1.9, p. 137. Hume s other allusions to reflection concern thinking about. 17 I have supported such a narrow reading of Berkeley s objective in the Dialogues in Berkeley s Epistemic Ontology: The Three Dialogues, in New Interpretations of Berkeley s Thought, ed. Stephen H. Daniel, Journal of the History of Philosophy Book Series (Amherst, NY: Humanity Books, forthcoming).

The Berkeley Newsletter 17 (2006) 13 As to the passage quoted, there is nothing that precludes a commitment to ideas of reflection. If there is a necessary (causal) connection between ideas of reflection and states or operations of the self, then the existence of the idea as known entails the existence of a state of the knower. 18 The second sentence is ambiguous. If it assumes a description of the properties and actions of the mind, these could be known by their effects, that is, ideas of reflection, which are perceived but not as I perceive a triangle, a colour, or a sound. 19 If it is concerned with the nature of mind as substance, it would still need to be substance under a certain description, e.g. that which knows, and its existence follows directly from the existence of something known. 20 So, we have seen that while Luce and others are correct in claiming that there cannot be Berkeleian ideas of reflection that are identical with operations of a immaterial substance or represent immaterial substance and its operations, it is entirely consistent with the Berkeleian texts to suggest that there are ideas of reflection that are caused by and signify operations of the mind. James Madison University deflage@jmu.edu 18 Cf. PHK 2, where Berkeley introduces a knower given the existence of ideas as objects of human knowledge. One might also notice that it is only in the second edition of the Principles that Berkeley adds a passage to PHK 89 that includes minds as objects of knowledge. 19 This would yield a description comparable to, although more complex than, Descartes description of himself in Meditation II: But what then am I? A thing that thinks. What is that? A thing that doubts, understands, affirms, denies, is willing, is unwilling, and also imagines and has sensory perceptions. René Descartes, The Philosophical Works of Descartes, trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch, vol. 2 (London: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 19. 20 Any attempt to give a description of Berkeley s theory of the nature of substance is beyond the scope of this paper. Suffice it to say that it is not a classical theory of substance and modes, since Berkeley denied that ideas are modes of a mind (see PHK 49; DHP 237).