Commentary on Scriven

Similar documents
Objections, Rebuttals and Refutations

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8

Should We Assess the Basic Premises of an Argument for Truth or Acceptability?

Commentary on Guarini

Reasoning, Argumentation and Persuasion

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

Informalizing Formal Logic

The Reach of Abduction: Insight and Trial (Book Review)

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

What is a Real Argument?

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Commentary on Feteris

Inquiry: A dialectical approach to teaching critical thinking

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

A problem in the one-fallacy theory

On the Very Concept of an Enthymeme

Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and. Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xvi, 286.

Assessing Confidence in an Assurance Case

Pragmatic Considerations in the Interpretation of Denying the Antecedent

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

On the Relation of Argumentation and Inference

Commentary on Paglieri

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood

COURSE GOALS: PROFESSOR: Chris Latiolais Philosophy Department Kalamazoo College Humphrey House #202 Telephone # Offices Hours:

Defeasibility from the perspective of informal logic

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.


The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics.

A. V. Ravishankar Sarma

2 Lecture Summary Belief change concerns itself with modelling the way in which entities (or agents) maintain beliefs about their environment and how

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5

On A New Cosmological Argument

How to formalize informal logic

History of Education Society

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

Inductive inference is. Rules of Detachment? A Little Survey of Induction

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Frege and Russell on Names and Descriptions Naïve theories

Conductive arguments and the inference to the best explanation

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

Two Accounts of Begging the Question

Philosophical Review.

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

The Logic of Ordinary Language

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 3. (Jul., 1991), pp

What is an argument? PHIL 110. Is this an argument? Is this an argument? What about this? And what about this?

All They Know: A Study in Multi-Agent Autoepistemic Reasoning

PHILOSOPHY-PHIL (PHIL)

INQUIRY AS INQUIRY: A LOGIC OF SCIENTIFIC DISCOVERY

Powerful Arguments: Logical Argument Mapping

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2009

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

Sensitivity hasn t got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Weighing Evidence in the Context of Conductive Reasoning

Logic, Inductive And Deductive By William Minto READ ONLINE

Revisiting the Socrates Example

Is Argument subject to the product/process ambiguity? *

NON-NUMERICAL APPROACHES TO PLAUSIBLE INFERENCE

Max Deutsch: The Myth of the Intuitive: Experimental Philosophy and Philosophical Method. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, xx pp.

Chapter 1. Introduction. 1.1 Deductive and Plausible Reasoning Strong Syllogism

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

Other Logics: What Nonclassical Reasoning Is All About Dr. Michael A. Covington Associate Director Artificial Intelligence Center

DO SENSE EXPERIENTIAL STATES HAVE CONCEPTUAL CONTENT?

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

Qualified Reasoning Approaching Deductive Validity

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

Here s a very dumbed down way to understand why Gödel is no threat at all to A.I..

Course Webpage:

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

Skepticism and Internalism

The paradoxical associated conditional of enthymemes

THE INTERNAL TESTIMONY OF THE HOLY SPIRIT: HOW DO YOU KNOW THAT THE BIBLE IS GOD S WORD?

Foundations of Non-Monotonic Reasoning

Anchored Narratives in Reasoning about Evidence

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

1.6 Validity and Truth

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

How many premises can an argument have?

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

Social mechanisms and explaining how: A reply to Kimberly Chuang Johannes Persson, Lund University

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

ST 501 Method and Praxis in Theology

Informal Logic and the Concept of 'Argument'

Transcription:

University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8 Jun 3rd, 9:00 AM - Jun 6th, 5:00 PM Commentary on Scriven John Woods Follow this and additional works at: http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive Part of the Philosophy Commons John Woods, "Commentary on Scriven" ( June 3, 2009). OSSA Conference Archive. Paper 148. http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/ossa8/papersandcommentaries/148 This Commentary is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty of Arts, Humanities and Social Sciences at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in OSSA Conference Archive by an authorized administrator of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact scholarship@uwindsor.ca.

Commentary on Michael Scriven s Probative Inference JOHN WOODS Department of Philosophy University of British Columbia 1866 Main Mall E370 Vancouver, BC Canada jhwoods@interchange.ubc.ca 1. INTRODUCTION In 1986 at the first ISSA Conference in Amsterdam, straight off a plane from Australia, Michael Scriven gave an invited lecture entitled Probative Logic, rendered with that speaker s customary exuberant intelligence and stentorian disapproval of the laggardly and unreflexively orthodox. It was an outstanding performance, one of the first articulations within the CT/IL community of the analytical forces that were gathering unruly strength in computer science artificial intelligence. As far as I can tell, Michael gave voice to these ideas on his own and without direct contact with the various developments in default logics, systems of nonmonotonic reasoning, defeasible inheritance logics, autoepistemic and abductive logics, circumspection logics, truthmaintenance systems, theory update logics, preferential reasoning logics, to say nothing of logic programming and the likes of Prolog. The main idea of the Amsterdam talk was that the establishment paradigms came nowhere close to covering the reach of human reasoning; that beyond the narrow confines of the logics of deduction and statistico-experimental induction, there is an incipient third logic directed to the various kinds of reasoning that rightfully deliver their conclusions with something less than deductive tightness or in the technical sense of the term inductive strength. What was especially valuable about Michael s proposal was his insistence that there was nothing subpar or second-or third-best about this third type of reasoning, that it too had the quality or function of proving or demonstrating a conclusion (hence the name probative). It is a striking idea, largely because it could possibly be true if proving and demonstrating are given the senses imposed on them by the mainstream logics. What Michael was saying is, in effect, that mainstream logic had high-jacked the notions of proof and demonstration. In his, we can only be reminded of Stephen Toulmin, who levelled the same charge against the appropriation of the idioms of probability by purveyors of the applied mathematics of games of chance. It is easy to see the appeal that Michael s talk would have had for the Amsterdam conferees. For weren t they, too, of the view that the analysis of human reasoning was too much to ask of the deductive and inductive paradigms? Since Amsterdam, a certain picture of how best to proceed with the theory of reasoning whether deductive, inductive or probative has emerged. It is the way of the systematic analysis of Woods, J. (2009). Commentary on Michael Scriven s Probative Inference. In: J. Ritola (Ed.), Argument Cultures: Proceedings of OSSA 09, CD-ROM (pp. 1-4), Windsor, ON: OSSA. Copyright 2009, the author.

JOHN WOODS argument. But this was not Scriven s way in 1986 and it is not Scriven s way now. Scriven is a probative logician but he is not an argumentation theorist, except intermittently, that is to say, in those particular cases in which reasoning is intrinsically argumentative. This sets up an interesting question. How, if you are not an argumentation theorist, is the theory of probative reasoning to be done? And where, these twenty-three years later, is this probative logic or this family of probative logics to be found? Concerning the second of these questions, let my quickly dispose of a not altogether unnatural suggestion. Given that there is still a burgeoning industry in AI studying nonmonotonic logic [and the like], 1 why not turn to AI for our probative logic? I daresay that Michael would like John Pollock s response to this suggestion. Unfortunately, their lack of philosophical training led AI researchers to produce accounts that were mathematically sophisticated, but epistemologically naïve. Their theories could not accommodate the varieties of defeasible reasoning humans actually imply [ ] [T]his coming remains to the present day. 2 What, then, of the first question. What would (or should) a non-argumentative probative logic look like? What are its chief analytically constitutive features? This is a tough question subsuming a large task. In the time available to me it is not possible to take it on. So let me confine myself to a smaller question. What analytically constitutive features of a probative logic have been introduced and/or developed by Michael Scriven? (After all, it is twenty-three years later). Pleading again the press of time, I ll deal with just two of them. They are The concept of normic or generic propositions. The concept of selection-explanation or inference to the best explanation. 2. NORMICITY Michael has spent the lion s share of his intellectual life doing battle against orthodoxies that had got too big for their britches. In 1959, he took baleful issue with the received view of generalization and general propositions. 3 Generality lies at the heart of human reasoning, where so much of what we re up to is generalizing to and instantiating from general propositions. As briefly as I can put it, Michael noticed that both science and everyday life are replete with general propositions having neither the logical form nor semantic profile mandated for them by the orthodoxy. Consider, for example, Ocelots are four-legged. 4 Perhaps its most distinctive semantic feature is that there are true negative instances in the face of which it remains true (say, that Ozzie the ocelot is only three-legged). Accordingly, it is not a universally quantified conditional statement. It is of a different logical form. 1 John Pollock, Defeasible reasoning. In: J. Adler and L. Rips (Eds.), Reasoning: Studies in human inference and its foundations. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 2008 p. 452. 2 John Pollock, Defeasible reasoning p. 452. 3 Michael Scriven, Truisms as the grounds for historical explanations. In: P. Gardiner (Ed.), Theories of History, pp. 443-475. Glencoe IL: Free Press, 1959. 4 Earlier recognition to the same effect was Cooper Langford s The institutional use of the, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 10 (1949), 115-120. 2

COMMENTARY ON MICHAEL SCRIVEN What is the significance of this for human reasoning? Consider the case at hand. Given that ocelots are four-legged and Ozzie is an ocelot there is a correct default inference for you to draw. It is that Ozzie is four-legged. But, as you now see, Ozzie is three-legged. If the general premises had been a universally quantified conditional statement, you would have made two mistakes. You would have been wrong about Ozzie and you would have been wrong about ocelots. But since the general premise is in fact a normic proposition, you have made only one mistake. You were wrong about Ozzie but you were right about ocelots. The economics of this set-up speak for themselves and they lend weight to a further normic generalization, which is that By and large, human reasoners generalize to and instantiate from normic propositions, not universally quantified ones. This is not expressly in Truisms as the grounds for historical explanations but it is certainly incipiently present. I regard it as a discovery of the first importance for the logic of human reasoning. 3. SELECTION-EXPLANATION Selection-explanation has a longer pedigree than normicity, occurring in Michael s D. Phil. Thesis of 1956. Perhaps it is not precisely what Gil Harman was on about nine years later in his The inference to the best explanation, 5 but it is a near thing all the same, something undoubtedly in the same family. Another piece of orthodoxy that Michael was doing battle with was the deductive-nomological model of explanation. But there is also a related issue, itself somewhat contentious as to whether or not evidential force is truthindicating. (Damn, I was nearly going to say probative!). Consider this rather coarsegrained schema of a selection-explanation inference: 1. The orbit of Mercury is perturbatious. If it were true that a planet call it Vulcan existed unseen at such and such place in the heavens, then this would explain Mercury s orbital perturbations. 2. So, let us provisionally make of Vulcan a working hypothesis. There are two points of importance to notice here. One is that it doesn t matter for the tenability of this reasoning whether explanatory force is or is not truth-tracking or evidentially clinching (Geoff Goddu). What the schema relies on is merely the subjunctive claim that if Vulcan were to exist, it would explain the perturbations. It does not say, and need not say, that Vulcan does explain them. The other point of interest is that the conclusion is not probative in Michael s preferred sense, which is meaning number two of his New Oxford American Dictionary. The premises don t have the quality or function of proving that Vulcan exists. Rather, they have the quality or function of rendering the Vulcan hypothesis worthy of exploration, that is, exploration on 5 Philosophical Review, 74 (1965) 88-95. 3

JOHN WOODS sufferance. And this, according to Michael s dictionary, is the first meaning of probative exploratory. Abduction which is the generalization of selection-explanation inference is as least as central to human reasoning as generalization. Michael s anticipation of its structure well over a half-century ago is a large achievement. And if, in later years, he misnamed it as probative, it is only the slightest of errors. For the name is right; it is only is primary sense that requires reinstatement. Link to paper 4