Monitoring and Anti-Reductionism in

Similar documents
The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Skepticism and Internalism

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

Nested Testimony, Nested Probability, and a Defense of Testimonial Reductionism Benjamin Bayer September 2, 2011

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

Against Phenomenal Conservatism

Testimonial knowledge through unsafe testimony

TAKE MY WORD FOR IT: A NEW APPROACH TO THE PROBLEM OF SINCERITY IN THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF TESTIMONY. Masters in Philosophy. Rhodes University.

Do Anti-Individualistic Construals of Propositional Attitudes Capture the Agent s Conceptions? 1

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Self-ascription, self-knowledge, and the memory argument

TESTIMONY AS AN A PRIORI BASIS OF ACCEPTANCE: PROBLEMS AND PROSPECTS. Robert Audi

TESTIMONIAL KNOWLEDGE. Jennifer Lackey Northwestern University

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

The Concept of Testimony

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Epistemological Externalism and the Project of Traditional Epistemology. Contemporary philosophers still haven't come to terms with the project of

The Skeptic and the Dogmatist

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Perceptual Justification and the Phenomenology of Experience. Jorg DhiptaWillhoft UCL Submitted for the Degree of PhD

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

METHODISM AND HIGHER-LEVEL EPISTEMIC REQUIREMENTS Brendan Murday

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Varieties of Apriority

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014

Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive?

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Aboutness and Justification

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

A PROBLEM WITH DEFINING TESTIMONY: INTENTION AND MANIFESTATION:

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Should We Assess the Basic Premises of an Argument for Truth or Acceptability?

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Against Coherence: Truth, Probability, and Justification. Erik J. Olsson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xiii, 232.

knowledge is belief for sufficient (objective and subjective) reason

Phenomenal Conservatism and the Internalist Intuition

What Should We Believe?

Sosa on Human and Animal Knowledge

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple?

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

What s the Matter with Epistemic Circularity? 1

UNDERSTANDING, JUSTIFICATION AND THE A PRIORI

Gale on a Pragmatic Argument for Religious Belief

Seeing Through The Veil of Perception *

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

guilty, then the citizen must be judged innocent. What are the options for rejecting PI? As already mentioned, the immediate competitor for PI is

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary

I assume some of our justification is immediate. (Plausible examples: That is experienced, I am aware of something, 2 > 0, There is light ahead.

Dogmatism and Moorean Reasoning. Markos Valaris University of New South Wales. 1. Introduction

TESTIMONY, ENGINEERED KNOWLEDGE AND INTERNALISM. Dan O Brien

THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia ISSN:

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

Transmission Failure Failure Final Version in Philosophical Studies (2005), 126: Nicholas Silins

Hannah Ginsborg, University of California, Berkeley

Sensitivity hasn t got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior

Philosophical Issues, 26, Knowledge and Mind, 2016 doi: /phis IS THERE A PROBLEM WITH COGNITIVE OUTSOURCING? 1

External World Skepticism

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas

A Priori Bootstrapping

Four Arguments that the Cognitive Psychology of Religion Undermines the Justification of Religious Belief

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Presupposition and Accommodation: Understanding the Stalnakerian picture *

Rationalism of a moderate variety has recently enjoyed the renewed interest of

4AANB007 - Epistemology I Syllabus Academic year 2014/15

3. Knowledge and Justification

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Transcription:

Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LxxlI, No. 3, May 2006 Monitoring and Anti-Reductionism in the Epistemology of Testimony SANFORD GOLDBERG University of Kentucky DAVID HENDERSON The University of Memphis One of the central points of contention in the epistemology of testimony concerns the uniqueness (or not) of the justification of beliefs formed through testimony-whether such justification can be accounted for in terms of, or reduced to, other familiar sort of justification, e.g. without relying on any epistemic principles unique to testimony. One influential argument for the reductionist position, found in the work of Elizabeth Fricker, argues by appeal to the need for the hearer to monitor the testimony for credibility. Fricker (1994) argues, first, that some monitoring for trustworthiness is required if the hearer is to avoid being gullible, and second, that reductionism but not anti-reductionism is compatible with ascribing an important role to the process of monitoring in the course of justifiably accepting observed testimony. In this paper we argue that such an argument fails. 1. Fricker s argument from gullibility Polyanna is notoriously naive. She is optimistic in the face of cogent evidence that things are not going well. She maintains her faith in the goodness of humanity in spite of numerous examples of human perfidy and malice. She has no imagination when it comes to the vicious motives that often inspire people s behavior. Here we focus on another epistemic shortcoming: her gullibility. Polyanna is easily deceived insofar as she is ready to accept what she is told, merely in virtue of being so told. This is not admirable. The effects of her gullibility are both practical-she is easily manipulated by others-and epistemic-she comes to believe many things which could easily be the results of epistemically undesirable processes in others, and which she would not believe but for the testimony. An adequate epistemology of testimony must see Polyanna as unjustified in the way that she acquires beliefs through testimony. Elizabeth Fricker has presented an argument that anti-reductionist accounts of the epistemology of testimony (AR) would fail this adequacy requirement. 600 SANFORD GOLDBERG AND DAVID HENDERSON

In introducing AR, she writes that the problem to be solved by the epistemology of testimony is that of showing how it can be the case that a hearer on a particular occasion has the epistemic right to believe what she is told-to believe a particular speaker s assertion (1994: 128). There are, she insists, simply two possibilities: It may be shown that the required steg-from S asserted that p to p -can be made as a piece of inference involving only familiar deductive and inductive principles, applied to empirically established premises. Alternatively, it may be argued that the step is legitimised as the exercise of a special presumptive epistemic right to trust, not dependent on evidence (1994: 128). On this view, AR is supposed to be motivated by the claim that the first, reductionist route to justifying testimony is closed. The alleged result is a thesis asserting a positive presumption to trust, as the only non-skeptical solution to the epistemological problem presented by testimony. It is against AR, understood to be advancing such a positive-presumption thesis, that Fricker raises the objection from gullibility. Her objection begins by noting that The notion of a presumption to trust testimony... seems only to make sense when it is interpreted as giving the hearer the right to believe without engaging in epistemic activity; when there is no requirement to be on the alert for defeating conditions... (1994: 143) Fricker then suggests the following as the proper formulation of anti-reductionism: PR: An arbitrary hearer H has the epistemic right, on any occasion of testimony 0, to assume, without investigation or assessment, of the speaker S who on 0 asserts that P by making an utterance U, that S is trustworthy with respect to U, unless H is aware of a condition C which defeats this assumption of trustworthiness (1994: p. 144). The clear and sharp difference between the account she advocates and the PR account, is that on [the reductionist] account, but not on a PR thesis, tlie hearer must always be tnonitoring fhe speaker critically. This is a matter of tlie actual engagement ofa counterfartual sensitivily: it is true throughout of the hearer that if there were any signs of untrustworthiness, she would pick them up (1994: 154; italics ours). She reiterates this point in her (1995), writing that a PR principle worthy of the name must dispense a hearer from the requirement to monitor and assess a speaker for trustworthiness (404). The argument, then, appears to boil down to (a) Fricker s contention that, given AR, H s having the epistemic right to accept a piece of testimony is compatible with H s failure to have monitored the testimony for its trustworthiness, together with (b) her inference from SYMPOSIUM 601

this to the conclusion (call it GULL ) that AR is an epistemic charter for gullibility (1994: 143). 2. Gullibility and monitoring If Fricker s argument from gullibility is to amount to an objection to AR, gullibility (as it figures in GULL) must denote an epistemically undesireable condition-one that, were a hearer to form a testimonial belief in the relevantly gullible way, would render the testimonial belief unjustified. What is more, if her case is not to beg the question, the epistemic undesirability of the relevant gullibility-condition must not itself depend on any contentious claim regarding the epistemology of testimony. Now, GULL admits of various readings, depending on different construals of gullibility ; we attempt some clarifications in this section. In the section following we argue that there is no construal of gullibility on which (i) GULL is true and (ii) by anyone s lights, subjects could not be justified in gullibly forming a belief. A word on the relevant notion of justification and justified belief is in order. We take the fundamental notion to be that of a justified belief, where a subject S s belief that p is justified if it was reliably formed and sustained, and in forming and sustaining the belief, S violates no acceptable epistemic norms. Then one might say that S herself is justified in believing that p at time t when, roughly put, S s belief that p is justified at t, S is aware at t of the grounds of her belief, and S s awareness figures (or would figure) among the reasons she sustains the belief on reflection. In these terms Fricker s gullibility case against AR boils down to the claims, first, that AR sanctions the gullible formation of testimonial beliefs, and second, that for this reason AR runs afoul of the conditions on justified belief (whether because AR-sanctioned gullibility makes for unreliability, or because it violates some acceptable epistemic norm(s)). We move now to the various construals of gullible. One possible reading is this: G1 Subject S is gullible, =def others testimony. S is naively credulous in the face of Following a suggestion from an anonymous referee from this journal, we characterize gullibility, as a stance-occupying one end of a continuum on which the other end is a skeptical stance towards others testimony. (The stance-gullible person has a high trust quotient, where the skeptic has a low trust quotient.) A second possible construal of gullible involves unreliable (or unsafe or insensitive) testimony-based belief-formation: G2 S is gullible, kdef in circumstances C, S is disposed to acquire a good deal of unreliable (unsafe; insensitive; etc.) testimony-based belief. 602 SANFORD GOLDBERG AND DAVID HENDERSON

We can strengthen or weaken the notion of gullibility, depending on how wide or narrow we regard the range of circumstances under which S exhibits the disposition in question. Clearly, a subject who would exhibit the disposition in any set of circumstances is highly gullible,; whereas a subject who would exhibit the disposition only in remote circumstances involving highlytrained and sophisticated liars is much less gullible,. A third possible reading of gullibility designates a type of intellectual vice. We might formulate this as follows: G3 S is gullible, =def there are circumstances C in which S ignores (or would ignore) good reasons not to trust her interlocutor. Again, we can strengthen or weaken the notion of gullibility, depending on how wide or narrow we regard the range of circumstances under which S ignores the evidence. Finally, as a fourth notion, we introduce the notion of gullibility-as-a-failure-to-monitor-for-trustworhiness. G4 S is gullible, =def S fails to monitor testimony for trustworthiness. Whatever such monitoring-for-trustworthiness comes to (something we discuss below), it is clear that the notion of gullibility, is especially important to an assessment of Fricker s argument, as her argument infers GULL from the claim that anti-reductionism disposes of the need for hearers to monitor incoming testimony for trustworthiness. Before considering how Fricker s case for GULL fares as an objection to anti-reductionism, we would do well to identify the sense(s) in which the foregoing notions of gullibility are notions of epistemically undesirable conditions. To begin, there is one clear sense in which each of Gl-G3 identifies an epistemically undesirable condition. Assume (what is no doubt the case) that ordinary circumstances involve occasional interaction with the disingenuous and regular interaction with speakers who, though both sincere and aiming at truth, sometimes speak falsely. Then those who are gullible in any of the Gl-G3 senses are likely to acquire a good deal of false testimonial beliefs, and in this sense are in an epistemically undesirable condition. This is most clearly the case in connection with gullibilty,, which builds in the disposition to acquire false belief. But the point is also relatively clear in connection with vice-gullibility (= gullibility,): in ordinary circumstances, those who ignore good reasons not to trust will often end up accepting falsehoods. And it is also true in connection with stance-gullibility (= gullibility,): since ordinary circumstances involve liars as well as speakers whose testimony is sincere but false, those who are naively credulous are likely to acquire a good deal of false beliefs. Finally, regarding the crucial construal of gullibility-that of failure-to-monitor (= gullibility,)-we can say that if a SYMPOSIUM 603

failure to monitor for trustworthiness gives rise to any of the other three gullibility properties, then gullibility, too will inherit the epistemically undesirable character of those. (Since this will go for all of the discussion to follow, gullibility,, will be relevant only insofar as it yields one of the other forms of gullibility.) The question then emerges whether (a core part of) the epistemic undesirability of gullibility in the various senses might be captured in the idea that gullibility gives rise to unreliable (testimony-based) belief.' If we restrict ourselves to ordinary circumstances, then the arguments given above give us a conditional affirmative answer. Above we saw that in ordinary circumstances stance-gullibility does introduce a significant degree of unreliability in the formation of testimonial beliefs, and so can be taken to be an epistemically undesirable condition for this reason? Passing over gullibility, (which builds in the notion of unreliable belief), we next consider vice-gullibility, It should be clear that in any world in which evidence is not regularly systematically misleading, subjects who are vice-gullible (and so who ignore relevant evidence) will acquire testimony-based beliefs in ways that are unreliable. What is more, even in a world W in which evidence is regularly systematically misleading, if there are possible worlds close to W in which evidence is not regularly systematically misleading, vice-gullibity on the part of subjects in W still makes for unreliability. For in that case although vicegullibility does not lead to false beliefs in W, it does in the nearby worlds in which the evidence against the trustworthiness of the testimony is not misleading. We have just suggested that at least some of the epistemic undesirability of gullibility (in any of its senses) can be traced to the role gullibility plays in leading to false or unreliable belief. But it might be thought that being gullible is epistemically bad independent of whether or not it conduces to false or unreliable belief. However, we submit that this is a controversial point, and that if Fricker's argument from gullibility depends on it, it is correspondingly contentious. For one thing, it is doubtful that the claim, that being gullible is epistemically bad independent of its connection to false or I 2 A fuller discussion might want to distinguish between general and lorat unreliability. For the former, see Goldman 1984 and McCinn 1986. For the latter, see See Nozick 1981. And for the use of a notion of local reliability in connection with testimony cases, see Fricker 1994: 147 and Graham 2000: 142. However, since our discussion will not turn on these issues, we speak of reliability simpliciter. Since the reliability of the stance-gullible hearer's testimonial beliefs reflects the reliability of the testimony she consumes, it would appear that one can be stance-gullible without acquiring unreliable testimonial belief (and hence without being gullible,). This is the case if H s sources are themselves invariably reliable, and where any possible world in which there are false reports is far enough away so as to be irrelevant to an assessment of the beliefs H forms through testimony in the invariably-reliable-reporting world. (Thanks here to an anonymous referee.) 604 SANFORD GOLDBERG AND DAVID HENDERSON

unreliable testimonial belief, can be established by appeal to the gullible subject s violation of epistemic norms: even if the existence of such norms is conceded, the very legitimacy of the epistemic norms themselves, qua epistemic norms, appears to depend on the role such norms play in conducing to the twin epistemic objectives of acquiring truths and avoiding falsehood^.^ And a similar point can be made in connection with the more contentious matter of epistemic duties, For this reason we will read Fricker s argument from gullibility as advancing the claim that anti-reductionism is an epistemic charter for a form of gullibility that leads, or is likely to lead, to unreliable (testimony-based) belief. In sum. The burden of Fricker s argument is to establish GULL. However, this succeeds in establishing an objection to AR only if the relevant reading of gullibility identifies what anyone should recognize is an epistemically undesirable condition-a condition whose presence in a belief-forming or -sustaining process would make for unjustified belief. We have exmined the epistemic undesirability of three distinct properties of gullibility; and we have suggested that the only uncontroversial sense in which these properties amount to epistemically undesirable conditions is that each makes for unreliability in testimonial belief-formation. Now, as noted at the end of section 1, Fricker s own notion of gullibility is introduced in connection with Fricker s contention that, given AR, a hearer H s having the epistemic right to accept a piece of testimony is compatible with H s failure to have monitored the testimony for its trustworthiness. So we can ask: is this contention correct? And if it is, does Fricker s inference (to the claim that AR is an epistemic charter for gullibility ) provide her with a way to reach the conclusion that AR sanctions an epistemically undesirable form of gullibility? 3. Fricker s case from gullibility revisited Return to Fricker s formulation of anti-reductionism as the following presumption-to-trust thesis: PR: An arbitrary hearer H has the epistemic right, on any occasion of testimony 0, to assume, without investigation or assessment, of the speaker S who on 0 asserts that P by making an utterance U, that S is trustworthy with respect to U, unless H is aware of a condition C which defeats this assumption of trustworthiness (1994 p. 144). Keeping in mind that the relevant notion of gullibility must be the notion of an epistemically undesirable condition, we can reconstruct her case against AR as depending on two key claims. The first is a possibility claim: This point is common ground among epistemologists who otherwise disagree on many basic issues: see e.g. Bonjour (1985: 7-8) and (2003: 5); Chisholm (1977: 14); Goldman 2001; Haack (1993: 203,220-21); and Lehrer (1981: 87) and (1989: 143). SYMPOSIUM 605

POSS It is possible that subject S acquires a testimony-based belief on occasion 0, where by the lights of AR S counts as having an epistemic right to her testimony-based belief on 0, and yet (insofar as she acquires her testimony-based belief on 0) she exhibits (some or another form of) gullibillity. Let us say that if POSS holds with respect to a gullibility-property then AR sanctions that gullibility-property. The second claim is an evaluative claim that can be formulated as follows: EVAL AR-sanctioned gullibility is an epistemically undesirable form of gullibility. Together, POSS and EVAL entail the possibility of a subject who, by the lights of AR, has an epistemic right to a testimony-based belief formed on a given occasion, even though the belief in question is formed through an epistemically undesirable form of gullibility. Hence the objection implicit in the claim that AR is an epistemic charter for gullibility. In reaction, we deny that there is any gullibility-property of which both POSS and EVAL. are true. Above we argued that the gullibility-property central to Fricker s case against AR is the notion pertaining to unreliable testimonial belief, i.e., gullibility,. But as we assess her argument it is worthwhile considering all four gullibility-properties; this will give us the opportunity to clarify what is at issue, and to suggest precisely where her argument goes wrong. Consider first vice-gullibility. Since vice-gullibility is clearly a vice, it would satisfy EVAL; so Fricker s case against AR need only establish that AR sanctions vice-gullibility. In this respect it is noteworthy that Fricker holds it against anti-reductionism that a PR principle worthy of the name must dispense a hearer from the requirement to monitor and assess a speaker for trustworthiness (1995: 404). Pursing this, her idea might be that if a subject S fails to constantly evaluate her interlocutor for signs of untrustworthiness, then S risks rendering herself ignorant of good reasons not to trust her interlocutor-reasons which would have turned up had she but monitored more carefully. Perhaps this is the idea behind Fricker s remark that the hearer should be discriminating in her attitude to the speaker, in that she should be continually evaluating him for trustworthiness throughout their exchange, in light of the evidence, or cues, available to her (1987: 149-50). But it is implausible to think that AR sanctions vice-gulliblity, Since no anti-reductionist regards the presumptive right to trust as indefeasible, the present charge must be that even an anti-reductionism that incorporates a no defeaters proviso sanctions vice-gullibility. Fricker s own formulation of AR recognizes as much, as her formulation of a presumption-to-trust thesis, PR, 606 SANFORD GOLDBERG AND DAVID HENDERSON

incorporates a proviso that there be no defeaters of which the hearer is aware. It is curious, though, that she restricts this proviso in this way. After all, as standardly conceived defeaters need not be known about, or even believed in, to play a defeating role: in addition to doxastic defeaters (which function by being believed), there are also factual and normative defeater~.~ What is more, characteristic formulations of anti-reductionism contain no such awareness restriction. Thus Burge s Acceptance Principle (formulated in terms of reasons rather than defeaters) reads: A person is entitled to accept as true something that is presented as true and that is intelligible to him, unless there are stronger reasons not to do so (1993: 467, italics in the original). So on the score of vice-gullibility, the trouble seems to be, not in the idea of a presumption to trust itself, but rather in Fricker s overly-restrictive PR formulation. Let us then reconsider Fricker s reason for imposing this awareness restriction on defeaters. Her claim is that the notion of a presumption to trust testimony... seems only to make sense when it is interpreted as giving the hearer the right to believe without engaging in epistemic activity; when there is no requirement to be on the alert for defeating conditions... (1987: 143). But those who formulate epistemic principles in terms involving defeaters regularly acknowledge all three sorts of defeaters (doxastic, normative, and factual). Consider the thesis that there is a defeasible presumption that one s own perceptual experience is trustworthy: an epistemologist who advanced such a thesis would clearly want to acknowledge all three sorts of defeaters. Since Fricker has not provided any reason to think that the presumption of trustworthiness regarding testimony is any different, her awareness restriction is unjustified. And once such a restriction is dropped and PR replaced by PR+ (just like PR except that it acknowledges all three sorts of defeaters), it is clear that the charge, that anti-reductionism sanctions vicegullibility, is unsupported. It is worth noting in this connection that, if AR s presumption-to-trust principle is formulated as PR+, then this places a special burden on Fricker to motivate her monitor-for-trustworthiness requirement. Consider that if there are any relevant defeaters which the hearer cannot defeat, then, even by the lights of PR+, the hearer will not count as having the epistemic right to accept the testimony-whether or not she has monitored for testimony: But then the alleged requirement to monitor-for-trustworthiness cannot be motivated by the need to uncover defeaters-so whence the need to monitor? And See e.g. Lackey (1999: 474-76) for a discussion of defeaters in connection with testimony cases. Nor is Burge s formulation of AR idiosyncratic in this respect: compare Evans (1982: 310-1 1) and Stevenson (1992: 448-49). We thank an anonymous referee for indicating the dialectical strength of Fricker s opponent here. SYMPOSIUM 607

so it can seem that even if Fricker s contention is correct-given AR, a hearer H s having the epistemic right to accept a piece of testimony is compatible with H s failure to have monitored the testimony for its trustworthines-even so, Fricker s case against anti-reductionism fails. For in that case Fricker s inference, from this contention to the conclusion that anti-reductionism is a recipe for gullibility, even if sound, would not identify a notion of gullibility that satisfies EVAL. We take this objection to Fricker s case to be substantial. But perhaps Fricker can somehow motivate the alleged monitoring requirement in the face of an anti-reductionism formulated as PR+ rather than PR. Or alternatively perhaps she might think to motivate the charge that AR sanctions gullibility without appeal to the alleged monitoring requirement. In the remainder of this paper we want to argue that Fricker s case against anti-reductionism would still fail. The dialectical situation is as follows. We have just seen that, if her gullibility objection to AR is construed as having vice-gullibility in mind, it fails. Assuming that the alleged requirement to monitor-for-trustworthiness can be motivated even after it is recognized that AR incorporates a fullblooded no-defeater condition, or that Fricker s case for the charge that AR sanctions gullibility can be pursued without appeal to such a requirement, it remains to be seen whether Fricker s gullibility objection can be vindicated by a gullibility-property other than vice-gullibility. The issue that needs to be addressed here is whether, perhaps in virtue of its implications regarding the monitoring requirement, AR sanctions one of the other forms of gullibility whose epistemic undesirability is uncontroversial: stance-gullibility or gullibility2. Consider first stance-gullibility. According to PR+, one has the defeasible but presumptive epistemic right to accept what one is told, where this presumption is defeated if there are positive (normative, factual, or doxastic) reasons not to trust one s interlocutor. So perhaps Fricker s claim is that there are cases in which PR+ would count a hearer as having the epistemic right to accept what she is told, yet where the hearer nevertheless exhibits stance-gullibility. It might even be argued that Polyanna provides such a case. After all, Polyanna is naively credulous, and so exhibits stance-gullibility; but (Fricker might note) in a case in which there are no relevant defeaters, she counts (by PR+) as having the right to accept what she is told. Some proponents of AR will simply choose to bite the bullet here: in the case described Polyanna, though stance-gullible, is epistemically entitled to accept what she is told, precisely because there are no defeaters for this entitlement. (On this reaction, POSS holds with respect to stance-gullibility but EVAL does not.) Our present claim, however, is that the proponent of AR does not have to bite this bullet: the anti-reductionist need not regard the mere absence of defeaters as sufficient to render the verdict that the hearer is 608 SANFORD GOLDBERG AND DAVID HENDERSON

entitled to accept what she is told. In particular, if AR can incorporate a monitoring requirement-and below we will argue that it can-then AR will not sanction testimonial belief in cases involving a failure to monitor-fortrustworthiness. Before arguing that AR can incorporate a monitoring requirement, we want to make clear how such a claim bears on the charge that AR sanctions stance-gullibility. Given the incorporation of a monitoring requirement, there are two ways to address this charge. The first and most obvious would argue that a subject is not stance-gullible if she monitors-for-trustworthiness: precisely not, since (it might be argued) monitoring is inconsistent with having a high trust quotient. If so, then an AR that incorporates a monitoring requirement will never sanction stance-gullibility. The second reply, however, does not assume that stance-gullibility is incompatible with monitoring. Rather, it argues that any stance-gullibility AR sanctions will not be an epistemically undesirable form of gullibility. Suppose that an agent monitors a speaker for trustworthiness, uncovering no defeaters for the claim that the testimony she observed was reliable; and suppose further that there were no defeaters (of any kind), and so that the testimony itself was reliable. Then, whether or not the hearer counts as stance-gullible, her testimonial belief will be reliable (based as it is on reliable testimony under conditions in which there are no factual, normative, or doxastic defeaters of the assumption that the testimony was trustworthy). So even on the concessive assumption that the belief in question was formed through stance-gullibility, the result would be that such stance-gullibility is not an epistemically undesirable form of gullibility, as it does not give rise to unreliable testimonial belief (see section 2). The foregoing offers a conditional response to the gullibility objection, when this objection is formulated in terms of stance-gullibility. On the condition that AR can incorporate a monitoring requirement, then either AR does not sanction stance-gullibility (since monitoring is incompatible with stancegullibility), or else AR is not objectionable on the score of sanctioning stance-gullibility (since in that case the testimonial beliefs it sanctioned, whether stance-gullible or not, would be reliable testimonial belief.) Indeed, the latter reply doubles as a conditional response to the gullibility objection construed in terms of gullibility, (the notion of gullibility tied to the acquisition of unreliable testimony-based belief). This is because the latter reply amounts to the claim that, if AR can incorporate a monitoring requirement, then it will not sanction any testimonial belief that is unreliable. In short, much hangs on whether AR can incorporate a monitoring requirement. If it can, then, since we have already argued that AR does not sanction vice-gulli- Arguably, some versions of AR actually do incorporate such a rnonitonng requirement See e.g. Coady (1992: 47), as cited in footnote 9 below. SYMPOSIUM 609

bility, and since we have just presented a conditional defense of AR against objections from stance-gullibility and gullibility,, the result would be that Fricker s objection from gullibility will have been shown to fail even if her monitoring requirement can be motivated or rendered unnecessary to her argument. In what follows we argue that AR can indeed incorporate a monitoring requirement. In addressing this issue, we begin by noting that there is a difference between being on the lookout for defeaters, and going out and looking for them. At most, only the former can legitimately figure as a necessary condition on the avoidance of gullibility (of any form). This much is conceded by Fricker herself, when she notes that in claiming that a hearer is required to assess a speaker for trustworthiness it would be absurd to insist... that [the hearer] is required to conduct an extensive piece of M15-type vetting of any speaker before she may accept anything he says as true (1994: 154). Rather, as Fricker herself formulates it, the monitoring requirement on gullibility-avoidance (and hence on justified testimonial belief) is merely that of having something like a counterfactual sensitivity (1994: 154) to the presence of defeaters, such that [it is] true throughout of the hearer that if there were signs of untrustworthiness, she would register them, and respond appropriately (Fricker 1987: 149-50). We believe that AR can incorporate a monitoring requirement of this sort into its account of the conditions on a subject s having the epistemic right to accept what she is told. In order to make our present case vivid, we will speak in terms, not of a realistic subcognitive monitoring system, but rather of an unrealistic buzzer system designed to exploit testimonial regularities. We indulge in this science fiction in order to work our way towards an understanding of a kind of monitoring that is compatible with a defeasible presumption to trust. We thank an anonymous referee for this apt way of putting the point. It is noteworthy that Coady, a writer prominently associated with AR, seems to envision the reception of testimony as involving an important dimension of critical monitoring by sensitive agents: What happens characteristically in the reception of testimony is that the audience operates a sort of learning mechanism which has certain critical capacities built into it. The mechanism may be thought of as partially innate, though modified by experience, especially in the matter of critical capacities. It is useful to invoke the model of a mechanism here since the reception qf testimony is normally unreflective but is not thereby uncritical. We may have no reason to doubt another s communication even where there is no question of our being gullible; we may simply recognize that the standard warning signs of deceit, confusion, or mistake are not present. This recognition incorporates our knowledge of the witness s competence, of the circumstances surrounding his utterance, of his honesty, of the consistency of the parts of his testimony, and its relation to what others have said, or not said, on the matter (Coady 1992: 47, italics added) 610 SANFORD GOLDBERG AND DAVID HENDERSON

Consider, then, the following illustration. Smith has a buzzer that is always by her side and which goes off whenever anyone tells her something that is not reliable. (For present purposes, it does not matter whether Smith herself knows how the buzzer works, nor whether she even knows or misonably believes that the buzzer is highly sensitive to the reliability of proffered testimony.) What is more, Smith never accepts any testimony that elicits a buzz from her buzzer. (Think of the buzzer as the contemporary version of Socrates daimon, applied to the case of received testimony). Then, no matter the stance Smith adopts towards incoming testimony, her testimonybased beliefs are reliable-in fact, they re perfectly reliable. True, this reliability is sustained by way of an intermediary, her buzzer (more on which below). But the point remains that a (reliability-sustaining) monitoring-based sensitivity to trustworthiness is not, by itself, incompatible with the antireductionist s assertion of a defeasible presumption to trust. In buzzer-theoretic terms: Smith enjoys a presumptive entitlement to accept testimony, which presumption is cancelled when a piece of testimony elicits a buzz. Those sympathetic to the claim that AR sanctions unreliable testimonial belief might respond by insisting that Smith is gullible,-if you take away her buzzer she would be easily deceived by unreliable say-so-albeit fortunate that she happens to form testimonial beliefs in accordance with a buzzer of this sort. But we can vary the story. Suppose that the buzzer cannot be easily detached from her, and attempts to do so have appreciable effects on her cognitive and practical life beyond those in connection with her dispositions to accept proffered testimony. And suppose as well that Smith s possession of the buzzer is not an idiosyncratic feature of her condition, but rather is a natural endowment possessed by all normal adult human beings. In that case, the charge that Smith is gullible, after all (because she is lucky to have such a buzzer) is simply unreasonable. The foregoing aims to show that if engaging in the epistemic activity [of monitoring] (Fricker 1994: 143) merely requires a counterfactual sensitivity (156) to the presence of defeaters, then such a requirement can be easily accommodated within a view endorsing a presumption to trust. Consider the following, strengthened presumption-to-trust thesis: PR++: A hearer H has the epistemic right to assume that speaker S s testimony on 0 was trustworthy if (i) there are no (doxastic, factual, or normative) defeaters for this assumption of trustworthiness, and (ii) on 0 H exhibits a counterfactual sensitivity SYMPOSIUM 61 1

to the presence of defeaters (which, given (i), turns up no such defeaters on 0). lo (We do not claim that anti-reductionism ought to be formulated as PR++ rather than PR+; only that it can be.) Of course, Fricker herself might insist on a more demanding conception of monitoring (even though the less Jemanding characterization, in terms of a counterfactual sensitivity to the presence of defeaters, is hers!). But we doubt that the demanding conception can be motivated. For she would have to establish that monitoring, so construed, both is a necessary condition on gullibility-avoidance (in any of the epistemically undesirable senses of gullibility ) and is inconsistent with PR++. Since we have already seen that there is a kind of monitoring available to the proponent of AR on which AR sanctions none of the epistemically undesirable forms of stance-gullibility, gullibilty,, and vice-gullibility, it is hard to see how she can establish what she needs to establish. Our reasoning regarding AR s incorporation of a monitoring requirement leaves us with a compatibility claim: AR is compatible with certain ways of realizing a monitoring requirement (and so does not entail the sanctioning of gullibility in any of its epistemically undesirable forms). What remains to be seen is whether the way monitoring is actually performed by human subjects can be accommodated within a broadly anti-reductionist epistemology of testimony. On this score the sci-fi buzzer example is no help. Instead, we propose to speak to this issue by suggesting what we take to be a substantive parallel with the process of recollection. 10 I It seems that one can have an appropriate counterfactual sensitivity to defeaters, and thus can be objectively justified in holding a belief, even if that sensitivity is not perfect and would have missed factual defeaters of a sort that are not readily noted by normal, conscientious agents with normal experience. Take the following case: Jones is a normal adult who, like other normal adults, is attentive to signs of untrustworthiness in others testimony. Observing Smith testify thatp, he notes no such sign of untrustworthiness. Had the usual signs of untrustworthiness obtained, Jones would have been sensitive to their presence, and would have refrained from accepting Smith s testimony. Of course, if (contrary to fact) Smith s testimony had been that of a professional and meticulous liar bent on deceiving, Jones might not have caught any signs of deception. Even so, the fact that Jones would have missed such factual defeaters (had they obtained) need not undermine the claim that (in the actual situation) Jones is entitled to accept Smiths testimony. As a result, condition (ii) of PR++ (the counterfactual sensitivity condition) is best read as requiring only the reasonably developed and discriminating sort of sensitivity we encounter in such normal, conscientious agents in normal conditions. If space permitted, we would have liked to develop the parallel between testimony- and perception-based belief. We believe that this parallel is instructive. One who is perceptually competent on a given matter has learned much in the course of past training, and this learning makes for a kind of sensitivity to details then encountered. The sensitivity to trustworthiness requisite for the epistemically appropriate reception of testimony would seem to exhibit a parallel sensitivity to nuanced new information about concrete cases-a sensitivity itself borne of information antecedently acquired through ongoing experience with interlocutors. 612 SANFORD GOLDRERG AND DAVID HENDERSON

4. Monitoring in Recollection Let the process of recollection designate those core memory processes that generate that state of seeming to recollect something, where this is a state short of belief andor acceptance. Commonly, one proceeds smoothly and automatically- without a conscious, articulate thought -from seeming to recollect p to accepting that p. Still, the distinction is required by simple facts about recollection and memory: there are cases in which, having set oneself to recollect something (an acquaintance s last name, say), one finds a particular thought emerging from the process of recollection, but declines to accept the thought in question, owing to its failure to square with other things one takes oneself to know or believe on good evidence. In such cases, other pieces of information are somehow dredged out of memory and recognized to be relevantly in conflict with what one now seems to recall. In such cases, the process of forming a memory belief is inhibited by processes that check for coherence with other information antecedently possessed by the agent-coherence monitoring processes. More typical, of course, are those cases where all goes smoothly-one has no sense of an impending incoherence with antecedently possessed information-and one goes on to form the memory judgment. We submit that, in these cases, coherence monitoring processes are operative throughout the process of recollection. As a result, were the agent to possess bases for not believing what is recollected in a given case, these would likely inhibit the formation of that belief. At the very least, there then would be a reflective moment in which the agent would give some thought to the confidence to be assigned to what was recollected. In some cases, as in the illustration above, the agent may be able to dredge up a particular antecedent belief for purposes of articulate reflection on the content suggested by recollection. In other cases the agent will only be able to articulate a crude basis for caution (a sense that the content in question is not quite right, or that the memory is curiously sketchy or unsupported by associated details, etc.). This picture is one in which the coherence-monitoring process serves as a nearly constant filter on the production of memory beliefs-although it is seen as working largely submerged from articulate or conscious thought. But why should one think that such a process is so commonly in play? In part the answer is that it is difficult to understand how it could be deployed intermittently in an epistemically desirable way. Ideally, the filter would be employed selectively-where it would do the most good, where it is needed. This requires that the coherence-monitoring processes be triggered. But how? Not by some sense for the importance of the matter in question: sometimes one is inhibited in the formation of a belief on which little hangs either practically or epistemically. Nor can the filter be triggered by incoherence with antecedent beliefs, for that would require that the coherence monitoring filter SYMPOSIUM 613

be triggered by -the coherence monitoring filter! Rather, we submit that coherence-monitoring processes serve as a near ubiquitous check on the formation of memory beliefs, but that they do so by operating in a largely subconscious fashion, and only occasionally give rise to articulate reflection. Granting the prima facie epistemic desirability of such monitoring, is it plausible that humans have the capacity for such monitoring? Here a comparison with a wider set of epistemic chores and modalities is helpful. One does not need to be a coherence-theorist to recognize that there are coherencesensitive, holistic chores to be managed by the central processes of belieffixation. This is reflected in the literature on theory-choice and confirmation in science, and in Fodor s continuing (1983, 2002) cautions regarding the associated problems facing classical cognitive science. Employing Fodor s useful terminology, there are two holistic dimensions of confirmation in the central processes of belief-fixation: such processes are isotropic and Quineian. For reasons of space, we will discuss only the first, but both have similar implications. Central processes of belief fixation are isotropic-every belief or candidate belief one has is at least potentially relevant to any other belief one has. This obtains because relevance itself can be highly mediated. Beliefs about trace elements found in vats of dry-cleaning fluid deep in the earth can be relevant to beliefs about fusion processes at the center of a nearby star-given mediating theory. Beliefs about a politician s previous job experience can be relevant to expectations for future fuel efficiency standards for automobilesgiven one s expectations regarding human nature and political organizations. But, then, in deciding whether to adopt some proposed change in belief, one must somehow manage to identify what beliefs are relevant, and then one must gauge the cumulative significance of these relevant beliefs. There is a daunting catch here: since any belief is potentially relevant to any other belief, all beliefs are actually relevant to relevance, and so to determine what beliefs are relevant, one must somehow automatically accommodate or be sensitive to the relevance of all of one s beliefs to relevance. This challenge is closely related to what has come to be called the frame problem for computational cognitive science; managing such cognitive chores does not seem to be classically computationally tractable. Our suggestion, drawing on the work of Henderson and Horgan (2000) and Horgan and Tienson (1995 and 1996), is that these chores are managed by automatically and inarticulately taking into account much possessed information that is not articulately represented in the cognitive system itself. These quick remarks on the central processes of belief-fixation suggest how coherence monitoring can be tractably managed in connection with recollectiodmemory. Consider then the epistemic parallels with the reception of testimony. We submit that, much as the recollectiodmemory processes are 614 SANFORD GOLDBERG AND DAVID HENDERSON

regulated by coherence-monitoring processes throughout, so too the process by which one moves, from the reception-with-understanding of testimony, to the formation of belief through that testimony, is regulated by processes that monitor for trustworthiness. As we have seen, monitoring of this sort is needed anyway, independent of considerations of testimony. What is more, many of the chores monitoring performs in connection with memory-in particular, determining the coherence of a recollected content with background belief-have clear analogues in connection with the reception of testimony. In sum, we have independent reasons to suppose that the human cognitive system employs a pervasive but largely subcognitive monitoring system in connection with the reception of testimony. Not only is AR compatible with certain ways of realizing a monitoring requirement; the hypothesis that humans monitor testimony in one of these ways is itself independently plausible. 5. Conclusion: Wither the presumption to trust? We conclude by noting how the model of testimonial belief-fixation on offer, on which coherence monitoring processes are constantly operating (albeit typically subcognitively), relates to AR s hallmark doctrine of a default epistemic entitlement to believe what one is told. To say that the acceptance of testimony enjoys such a default status is to say that it is epistemically appropriate for one to accept testimony, provided that there are no defeating or overriding reasons for not doing so (and one exhibits the relevant counterfactual sensitivity?). To better understand the default status AR extends to testimony it may help to consider epistemic channels to which no such status is to be attributed. As her mind is wandering, the thought occurs to Smith ( out of the blue ) that there are albino penguins. Although she has no strong positive reasons for thinking that there are,? the hypothesis itself is consistent with her background beliefs (or what she has accepted to date). For this reason, were the claim that there are albino penguins to be subject to a process of subpersonal monitoring for coherence, such a claim would pass.13 But would the musing-generated hypothesis that there are albino penguins then be such that Smith would be entitled to believe it? That seems dubious in the * The reasons that she does have are from certain general claims she accepts-the claim, for example, that for any (of the precious few!) species into which she has looked into the matter, there have been albino members of the species-and from a lack of any reason to think that such general claims are restricted in scope in ways that prevent their application to the case of penguins. 13 We are glossing over some subtle and significant questions regarding that character of the monitoring processes. Do the processes monitor not simply $or consistency of what is imagined with what is antecedently known, but also for more demanding coherentist features such as explanatory unification? If so, then it becomes correspondingly less plausible that a given suggestion of imagination would pass, and correspondingly less plausible that imagination-so-checked would enjoy a default entitlement. SYMPOSIUM 615

~~ ~~~ extreme. Herein is the substance of the presumptive status that AR ascribes to observed testimony: the fact that a proposition was attested to provides it with a sort of epistemic seal which generates a defeasible but presumptive entitlement to accept that proposition. This does not go for propositions that occur to one in one s daydreams. Musing-with-monitoring-unlike perception-, memory-, or testimony-with-monitoring-does not give rise to entitled belief. l4 References Audi, R. 1997: The Place of Testimony in the Fabric of Knowledge and Justification. American Philosophical Quarterly 34:4, pp. 405-422. Bonjour, L. 1985: The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Bonjour, L. and Sosa, E. 2003: Epistemic Justification. Oxford: Blackwell. Chisholm, R. 1977: Theory of Knowledge, 2 ld Edition. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Coady, C. 1992: Testimony: A Philosophical Study. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Evans, G. 1982: The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Fodor, J. 1983: The Modularity ofmind. Cambridge: MIT Press. Fodor, J. 2002: The Mind Doesn t Work That Way: The Scopes and Limits of Computational Psychology. Cambridge: MIT Press. Fricker, E. 1987: The Epistemology of Testimony. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 61, pp. 57-83. Fricker, E. 1994: Against Gullibility. In B. K. Matilal and A. Chakrabarti, eds., Knowing from Words Amsterdam: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 125-61. Fricker, E. 1995: Telling and Trusting: Reductionism and Anti-Reductionism in the Epistemology of Testimony. Mind 104, pp. 393-411. Goldman, A. 1986: Epistemology and Cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Goldman, A. 2001: The Unity of the Epistemic Virtues. In A. Fairweather and L. Zagzebski, Virtue Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Graham, P. 2000: Transferring Knowledge. Noris 34: 1, 131-152. Haack, S. 1993: Evidence and Inquiry. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Henderson, D. and Horgan, T. 2000: Iceberg Epistemology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61:3,497-535. l4 We would like to thank an anonymous referee from ttus journal for some very helpful suggestions and criticisms of an earlier draft. 616 SANFORD GOLDBERG AND DAVID HENDERSON