Scientific realism and anti-realism

Similar documents
HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Kazuhisa Todayama (Graduate School of Information Science, Nagoya University, Japan)

145 Philosophy of Science

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

Approximate Truth vs. Empirical Adequacy

The Best Explanation: A Defense of Scientific Realism

Historical Inductions, Unconceived Alternatives, and Unconceived Objections

Are Scientific Theories True?

Why Does Laudan s Confutation of Convergent Realism Fail?

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics)

FINAL EXAM REVIEW SHEET. objectivity intersubjectivity ways the peer review system is supposed to improve objectivity

Scientific realism is dead, or so many philosophers believe. Its death was announced when philosophers became

What the History of Science Cannot Teach Us Ioannis Votsis University of Bristol

Theoretical Virtues in Science

SCIENTIFIC REALISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY

Structural Realism or Modal Empiricism?

The linguistic-cultural nature of scientific truth 1

Quests of a Realist. Stathis Psillos, Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth. London: Routledge, Pp. xxv PB.

Science as a Guide to Metaphysics? Katherine Hawley, University of St Andrews, June

Science, Metaphysics, and Scientific Realism

Why Should We Be Pessimistic about Antirealists and Pessimists?

The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best

Chapter One. Constructive Empiricism and the Case. Against Scientific Realism

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

REALISM/ANTI-REALISM

A Defense for Scientific Realism:

also for his help in selecting the material for this volume.

A Theory s Predictive Success does not Warrant Belief in the Unobservable Entities it Postulates

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

Grounds and Structural Realism: A Possible Metaphysical Framework 1

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

How the growth of science ends theory change

I. Scientific Realism: Introduction

Van Fraassen s Appreciated Anti-Realism. Lane DesAutels. I. Introduction

Philosophy of Science PHIL 241, MW 12:00-1:15

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE PHIL 145, FALL 2017

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

We aim to cover in some detail a number of issues currently debated in the philosophy of natural and social science.

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

UNIVERSITY OF ALBERTA MATHEMATICS AS MAKE-BELIEVE: A CONSTRUCTIVE EMPIRICIST ACCOUNT SARAH HOFFMAN

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Qualified Realism: From Constructive Empiricism to Metaphysical Realism.

Causal Realism, Epistemology and Underdetermination. Abstract: It is often charged against realist philosophers of science that because they are

Realism and Anti-Realism about Science A Pyrrhonian Stance

Tuomas E. Tahko (University of Helsinki)

6AANA026 Philosophy of Science Syllabus Academic year 2015/16

UNIVERSITY OF ALBERTA MATHEMATICS AS MAKE-BELIEVE: A CONSTRUCTIVE EMPIRICIST ACCOUNT SARAH HOFFMAN

Critical Scientific Realism

Truth and Realism. EDITED BY PATRICK GREENOUGH AND MICHAEL P. LYNCH. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. ix Price h/b, p/b.

Scientific Method and Research Ethics Questions, Answers, and Evidence. Dr. C. D. McCoy

Realism and instrumentalism

Empiricism. Otávio Bueno Department of Philosophy University of Miami Coral Gables, FL

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

The Theory/Experiment Interface of the Observation of Black Holes

Philosophica 67 (2001, 1) pp. 5-9 INTRODUCTION

The past vs. the tiny: historical science and the abductive arguments for realism

Jeffrey, Richard, Subjective Probability: The Real Thing, Cambridge University Press, 2004, 140 pp, $21.99 (pbk), ISBN

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

The evolution of the meaning of SCIENCE. SCIENCE came from the latin word SCIENTIA which means knowledge.

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Analogy and Pursuitworthiness

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Academic Integration in Engineering and Technology

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Beyond Structural Realism: pluralist criteria for theory evaluation

HAS SCIENCE ESTABLISHED THAT THE UNIVERSE IS COMPREHENSIBLE?

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

7AAN2075 Philosophy of Science Syllabus Academic year 2016/17

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

Kitcher, Correspondence, and Success

Revelation, Humility, and the Structure of the World. David J. Chalmers

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

Structural realism and metametaphysics

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

scientific realism 688 2nd edition

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

A Quick Review of the Scientific Method Transcript

The Problem of Induction. Knowledge beyond experience?

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

THE HYPOTHETICAL-DEDUCTIVE METHOD OR THE INFERENCE TO THE BEST EXPLANATION: THE CASE OF THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION BY NATURAL SELECTION

Inductive inference is. Rules of Detachment? A Little Survey of Induction

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

TESTING INFERENCE TO THE BEST EXPLANATION

K.V. LAURIKAINEN EXTENDING THE LIMITS OF SCIENCE

Realism, Approximate Truth, and Philosophical Method

The Coincidentalist Reply to the No-Miracles Argument. Abstract: Proponents of the no-miracles argument contend that scientific realism is "the only

How Successful Is Naturalism?

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Philosophy and Methods of the Social Sciences

Transcription:

Scientific realism and anti-realism Philosophy of Science (106a/124), Topic 6, 14 November 2017 Adam Caulton (adam.caulton@philosophy.ox.ac.uk) 1 Preliminaries 1.1 Five species of realism Metaphysical realism. The world, including unobservable entities, is the way it is independently of how conscious agents (like us) think or talk about it. Semantic realism. Language and thought refer to an autonomous world, including unobservable entities. Entails metaphysical realism. Epistemological realism. It is possible to have knowledge of an autonomous world, including unobservable entities. Entails semantic realism. Aspirational realism. At least one of the goals of science should be the development of theories about the world including unobservables that are true, or at least approximately true. Entails epistemological realism, if we also assume that any goal that scientists ought to pursue is in principle achievable. Optimistic realism. Our current scientific theories are true, or at least approximately true. Entails epistemological realism, if we also assume that our current scientific theories were produced by an appropriate method to constitute knowledge (i.e. a method that is reliable/such that we track the truth /... ). Disclaimer: these terms are mine; your mileage may vary with other authors. (E.g., Laudan calls what I call optimistic realism epistemological realism.) Scientific realism is ambiguous in the literature; one of the above is usually meant, and more recent discussions tend to focus on either aspirational or optimistic realism. 1.2 Ways to sophisticate or temper optimistic realism Selective optimism 1. Different scientific disciplines may warrant different degrees of optimism. (In particular, there are sciences, e.g. physiology, which seem only to study in-principleobservable entities.) Selective optimism 2. It might make sense and be justified to be optimistic about certain aspects of a scientific theory and pessimistic about others. Three important attempts to do this are: structural realism (see below), explanatory role realism (i.e., realism only about those aspects of the theory that play an essential explanatory role; see Psillos 1999 and Saatsi 2005) and entity realism (i.e., realism about entities that can be manipulated: if you spray them, they are real ; see Hacking 1983 and Cartwright 1983). Approximate truth. It seems implausible to claim that, e.g., general relativity and the standard model of particle physics are true (they are not consistent with one another!). But there may be a weakening of truth to approximate truth, according to which it may be cogent even reasonable to claim that general relativity and the standard model of particle physics are both approximately true. Moreover, one might wish to modify optimism to a diachronic claim: e.g. the historical progress of science is toward a collection of theories with ever-increasing approximate truth. But then what is approximate truth? It, and the related notion of verisimilitude, has been notoriously slippy in the history of the philosophy of science; see Newton-Smith (1981, Ch. 8). 1

2 The no miracles argument (for optimistic realism) The positive argument for realism is that it is the only philosophy that doesn t make the success of science a miracle. That terms in mature scientific theories typically refer... that the theories accepted in a mature science are typically approximately true, that the same term can refer to the same thing even when it occurs in different theories these statements are viewed... as part of the only scientific explanation of the success of science... Putnam (1975, p. 73). This is a sort of meta- inference to the best explanation, a form of inference often associated with scientific realism, since it typically permits inference to unobservable entities, or facts about how they are arranged. van Fraassen (1980) offers a rival, evolutionary argument for the success of science: our current scientific theories are successful just because we select our theories according to their success. But it is unclear that Putnam and van Fraassen are providing explanations for the same phenomenon here: Putnam is offering an explanation for the success of our current theories read de re (i.e. general relativity, evolution by natural selection, organic chemistry), while van Fraassen seems to be offering an explanation for the success of our current theories read de dicto (i.e. whatever they might be). (To grasp the de re/de dicto distinction, consider the statement: I want a sloop. Is there some particular sloop that you want, or do you only desire relief from slooplessness?) 3 Underdetermination and inference to the best explanation Inference to the best explanation is often cited as a means to overcome the underdetermination of theory by data. That is, many hypotheses may predict the same observable phenomena, but only one will provide the best explanation of those phenomena. 3.1 Underdetermination We should distinguish between: Underdetermination by all current data. Neither of two rival hypotheses or theories may be preferred by the evidence, since they are equally well supported (up to experimental error, etc.) by all the evidence we currently have. The underdetermination of the green vs. grue hypotheses by our current evidence of the colour of emeralds is an example of this. But these hypotheses make rival claims about future observations (the next emerald you observe after time t will be green vs. the next emerald you observe after time t will be blue). Underdetermination by all possible data. Neither of two rival hypotheses or theories may be preferred by the evidence, since they agree on all their claims about all possible observable data; i.e. they are empirically equivalent. Examples of this are controversial, since any two such hypotheses/theories may be claimed to be, in fact, reformulations of the same theory after all (putative examples from geometry are discussed by Glymour 1970, 1977); or else the original claim of empirical equivalence is at best contextual and defeasible, since it relies on ignoring connections to other (perhaps as yet unformulated) parts of science, and the shifting boundary between what is observable and unobservable (see Laudan & Leplin 1991). The second, stronger, form of underdetermination may be overcome in (at least) two ways: Deny that empirically equivalent theories can be rivals. This requires the denial of semantic realism, and was the route taken by the logical positivists, given the verification criterion of 2

meaning. Deny that science should aim for anything more than empirical adequacy : Science aims to give us theories which are empirically adequate; and acceptance of a theory involves as belief only that it is empirically adequate. van Fraassen (1980, p. 12). This requires the denial of (at least) aspirational realism. 3.2 Inference to the best explanation What counts as best? Following Lipton (2004), for any given phenomenon, we can distinguish between the likeliest explanation and the loveliest explanation. An explanation may be called lovely if it satisfies certain theoretical virtues, such as simplicity, scope, and fruitfulness. However, one wonders whether: (i) we have reason to think that these virtues are truth-conducive; (ii) we are able competently to rank hypotheses; and (iii) we may assume that the true hypothesis is among the rivals under consideration. If we can only overcome underdetermination by appeal to non-epistemic theoretical virtues, and if we have no good reason to believe that those virtues track the truth, then we cannot charitably conceive of science as practiced along the lines of aspirational realism. (A position along these lines is rehearsed by van Fraassen 1980.) Can IBE be reduced to Bayesian reasoning? Suppose we have two hypotheses H 1 and H 2, some evidence E and background knowledge K. By Bayes Law, if both: p(h 1 K) > p(h 2 K) and p(e H 1, K) > p(e H 2, K), then p(h 1 E, K) > p(h 2 E, K). (Note: it is not necessary that both conditions above hold to obtain this conclusion.) For an investigation into this idea, see Okasha (2000) and Lipton (2004, Ch. 7). Is realism a better explanation than constructive empiricism for the success of science? Consider the following argument from van Fraassen (1980). Let H 1 = Our current scientific theories are true, H 2 = Our current scientific theories are empirically adequate, and E = the empirical success of those theories. Then p(h 2 K) p(h 1 K) (since H 1 H 2 ) and p(e H 1, K) = p(e H 2, K) (? since E captures only what is observable?); so H 2 is preferable to H 1. (You may say: But what best explains the truth of H 2? Surely the truth of H 1! But explanations must stop somewhere: why not at H 2?) 4 The pessimistic meta-induction (against optimistic realism) From Laudan (1981): (P1) Of the theories we have developed, the false/nonreferring successful ones greatly outnumber the approximately true/genuinely referring successful ones. (C1) Therefore (by induction), any successful theory is likely to be false/nonreferring. (C2) Therefore our current theories are likely to be false/nonreferring. (For those sceptical of (P1): note that it seems to follow from the negation of (C2). We therefore have an argument from (C2) to (C2); this entails (C2).) 3

Laudan s examples: the crystalline spheres of ancient and medieval astronomy; the humoral theory of medicine; the effluvial theory of static electricity; catastrophist geology, with its commitment to a universal (Noachian) deluge; the phlogiston theory of chemistry; the caloric theory of heat; the vibratory theory of heat; the vital force theories of physiology; the electromagnetic aether; the optical aether; the theory of circular inertia; theories of spontaneous generation. Plausibly, these theories are not only false, they are not even approximately true. Can Laudan s inductive argument be undermined? Focus on mature theories. Good inductive inferences require that the inductive base be sufficiently similar to the projected cases. Perhaps current mature theories are sufficiently dissimilar from past theories to block the inference. But how to make a notion of maturity non-ad hoc? Be selective about truths/reference. We may then deny that previous theories were false/nonreferring about the things that matter. But what can we be selective about, save empirical success? 5 Structural realism Structural realism is a form of selective optimistic realism: the structural realist is selectively optimistic about the structural claims about unobservables in (sufficiently mature) scientific theories. It comes in two flavours: Epistemic structural realism, defended by Worrall (1989). Ontic structural realism, defended by Ladyman (1998). 5.1 Epistemic structural realism According to Worrall, both the no miracles argument and the pessimistic meta-induction must be taken seriously. Any form of optimistic realism will be implausible unless theory change is essentially cumulative about what matters. But can we find cumulative success at something beyond just the empirical level? Worrall s strategy: Eliminate examples of immature science. Science is mature only when it begins making successful novel predictions (in the Lakatosian sense). E.g.: Newtonian cosmology, Fresnel s wave theory of light,... For the remaining entries, seek continuity in the structure of those theories central equations. 4

There was an important element of continuity in the shift from Fresnel to Maxwell and this was much more than a simple question of carrying over the successful empirical content into the new theory. At the same time it was rather less than a carrying over of the full theoretical content or full theoretical mechanisms (even in approximate form). And what was carried over can be captured without making the very far-fetched assumption... that Fresnel s theory was really about the electromagnetic field all along. There was continuity or accumulation in the shift, but the continuity is one of form or structure, not of content. Worrall (1989, p. 117). The inspiration from Poincaré is clear: The ephemeral nature of scientific theories takes by surprise the man of the world. Their brief period of prosperity ended, he sees them abandoned, one after the other... he predicts that the theories in fashion today will in a short time succumb in their turn... [But] his scepticism is superficial; he does not take into account the object of scientific theories and the part they play, or he would understand that the ruins may still be good for something. No theory seemed established on firmer ground than Fresnel s, which attributed light to the movements of the ether. Then if Maxwell s theory is preferred today, does it mean Fresnel s work was in vain? No; for Fresnel s object was not to know whether there really is an ether, if it is or is not formed of atoms, if these atoms really move in this way or that; his object was to predict optical phenomena... It cannot be said that this is reducing physical theories to simple practical recipes; these equations express relations, and if the equations remain true, it is because the relations preserve their reality. They teach us now, as they did then that there is such and such a relation between this thing and that; only the something which we then called motion we now call electric current. But these are merely names of the images we substituted for the real objects which Nature will hide forever from our eyes. The true relations between these real objects are the only reality we can attain. Poincaré, Science and Hypothesis (1905). So, in this example, the motion of bits of ether goes over to motion of the electromagnetic field itself. This involves a discontinuous shift in ontology, but the equations of motion are the same. More generally, the equations of previously successful theories can be recovered from the equations of the new theory in some appropriate limit. (Recall Newton and Einstein in Kuhn s discussion.) There is now no prospect (or so it is claimed) for a pessimistic induction on the mathematical structure of theories since this is preserved over theory change. What exactly is a theory s mathematical structure? Worrall flirted with the idea of using a theory s Ramsey sentence to express its structural claims; but it is now widely recognised that the resulting account amounts to little more than empiricism (see Ketland 2004). 5.2 Ontic structural realism Ladyman s stronger brand of structural realism holds that, when it comes to claims about unobservables, there is nothing above and beyond a theory s mathematical structure to believe in. Ladyman s own identification of a theory s structure is tied to the semantic account of theories, according to which theories are understood, not as sets of partially interpreted sentences in some formal language, but rather as sets of models (typically, though not exclusively, understood in the same sense as model theory). Distinct models may admit of isomorphisms (or, more realistically, partial isomorphisms) between them; structure, according to Ladyman, is what is preserved under these isomorphisms. 5

More recently, these ideas have been cast in a category-theoretic setting by a variety of authors, most notably Jim Weatherall. 6 Suggested reading Cartwright, N., How the Laws of Physics Lie (Clarendon, 1983). Glymour, C., Theoretical realism and theoretical equivalence, PSA: Proceddings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (1970), pp. 275-288. Glymour, C., The Epistemology of Geometry, Nous 11 (1977), pp. 227-251. Hacking, I., Representing and Intervening (CUP, 1983). Ketland, J., Empirical Adequacy and Ramsification, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55 (2004), pp. 287-300. Ladyman, J., What is Structural Realism?, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 28 (1998), pp. 409-24. Laudan, L., A confutation of convergent realism, Philosophy of Science 48 (1981), pp. 19-48. Lipton, P., Inference to the Best Explanation, 2nd Edition (Routledge, 2004). Newton-Smith, W., The Rationality of Science (Routledge, 1981). Okasha, S., Van Fraassen s critque of inference to the best explanation, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 31 (2000), pp. 691-710. Psillos, S., How Science Tracks Truth (Routledge, 1999). Putnam, H., What is Mathematical Truth? Chapter 4 of his Mathematics, Matter and Method: Philosophical Papers, Volume 1 (CUP, 1975). Saatsi, J., Reconsidering the Fresnel-Maxwell theory shift: how the realist can have her cake and EAT it too, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 36 (2005), pp. 509-38. van Fraassen, B. C., The Scientific Image (Clarendon, 1980). Worrall, J., Structural realism: the best of both worlds?, Dialectica 43 (1989), pp. 99-124. 6