Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi

Similar documents
Klein on the Unity of Cartesian and Contemporary Skepticism

Counterparts and Compositional Nihilism: A Reply to A. J. Cotnoir

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Varieties of Apriority

Analyticity and reference determiners

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Philip D. Miller Denison University I

In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a

The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth

The Endurance/Perdurance Controversy is No Storm in a Teacup

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

On a priori knowledge of necessity 1

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

Scope Fallacies and the "Decisive Objection" Against Endurance

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Strawson On Referring. By: Jake McDougall and Siri Cosper

Against the Vagueness Argument TUOMAS E. TAHKO ABSTRACT

Framing the Debate over Persistence

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Anti-Metaphysicalism, Necessity, and Temporal Ontology 1

Presentism, persistence and trans-temporal dependence

Skepticism and Internalism

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers

Between the Actual and the Trivial World

Compositional Pluralism and Composition as Identity

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Persistence, Parts, and Presentism * TRENTON MERRICKS. Noûs 33 (1999):

IA Metaphysics & Mind S. Siriwardena (ss2032) 1 Personal Identity. Lecture 4 Animalism

Dominc Erdozain, "The Problem of Pleasure. Sport, Recreation and the Crisis of Victorian Religion" (2010)

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Critical Study of Michael Jubien, Ontology, Modality, and the Fallacy of Reference

Anti-Metaphysicalism, Necessity, and Temporal Ontology 1

Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

A Posteriori Necessities

Mereological Nihilism and the Special Arrangement Question

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

abstract: What is a temporal part? Most accounts explain it in terms of timeless

Coordination Problems

Theories of propositions

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

A Model of Decidable Introspective Reasoning with Quantifying-In

Sider, Hawley, Sider and the Vagueness Argument

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

Puzzles of attitude ascriptions

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Oxford University Press and The Analysis Committee are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Analysis.

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

Naturalist Cognitivism: The Open Question Argument; Subjectivism

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Compositional Pluralism and Composition as Identity 1. Kris McDaniel. Syracuse University

Who is a person? Whoever you want it to be Commentary on Rowlands on Animal Personhood

5 A Modal Version of the

The Argument from Vagueness for Modal Parts

The Argument from Vagueness for Modal Parts

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

ARMSTRONGIAN PARTICULARS WITH NECESSARY PROPERTIES *

Natural Kinds: (Thick) Essentialism or Promiscuous Realism?

Unnecessary Existents. Joshua Spencer University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

A Posteriori Necessities by Saul Kripke (excerpted from Naming and Necessity, 1980)

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

A Note on a Remark of Evans *

First Truths. G. W. Leibniz

Chalmers on Epistemic Content. Alex Byrne, MIT

PRESENTISM AND PERSISTENCE

Promiscuous Endurantism and Diachronic Vagueness

Composition and Vagueness

Lawrence Brian Lombard a a Wayne State University. To link to this article:

Armstrongian Particulars with Necessary Properties

Am I free? Freedom vs. Fate

Intrinsic Properties Defined. Peter Vallentyne, Virginia Commonwealth University. Philosophical Studies 88 (1997):

Yuval Dolev, Time and Realism, MIT Press, 2007

The Resurrection of Material Beings: Recomposition, Compaction and Miracles

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

Why Four-Dimensionalism Explains Coincidence

Postscript to Plenitude of Possible Structures (2016)

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Aalborg Universitet. A normative sociocultural psychology? Brinkmann, Svend. Publication date: 2009

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

There might be nothing: the subtraction argument improved

Citation for published version (APA): Petersen, T. S. (2011). What Is Legal Moralism? Sats, 12(1), DOI: /sats.

DANCY ON ACTING FOR THE RIGHT REASON

Improper Parts, Restricted Existence, and Use: Three Arguments against Ted Sider's Four- Dimensionalism

Propositions as Cambridge properties

Transcription:

Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi Hansson Wahlberg, Tobias Published in: Axiomathes DOI: 10.1007/s10516-009-9072-5 Published: 2010-01-01 Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Hansson Wahlberg, T. (2010). Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi. Axiomathes, 20(4), 511-514. DOI: 10.1007/s10516-009-9072-5 General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. L UNDUNI VERS I TY PO Box117 22100L und +46462220000

Download date: 29. Jun. 2018

Published in Axiomathes, (2010), Vol. 20, No. 4, pp. 511-514. Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi Tobias Hansson Wahlberg Lund University Abstract In this paper I answer Aranyosi s (2009) criticism of my Is Phosphorus Hesperus? (2009). In the Abstract of his reply to my Is Phosphorus Hesperus? (2009), Aranyosi writes Hesperus is Phosphorus has to be true, if it is true, regardless of which theory of persistence one is committed to (2009, p. 223). By saying this he implies that I argued that the truth of the conditional If Hesperus is Phosphorus is true, then Hesperus is Phosphorus is necessarily true hinges on which theory of persistence is true. But this I did not do. Supposing that the names are rigid designators, surely the identity statement is necessarily true if it is true, regardless of which theory of persistence is true. 1 What I did argue was that the truth of the antecedent (i.e. Hesperus is Phosphorus is true ) can be questioned assuming the conjunction of (a) the perdurance theory of persistence and (b) the thesis of unrestricted mereological composition 2 : someone endorsing (a) and (b) may hold that the proper referent of Hesperus is the aggregate of the temporal parts of Venus which are visible in, and only in, the evening, and that the proper referent of 1 However, if the names are non-rigid designators, then the consequent may be false even if the antecedent is true (see Kripke, 1980, p. 3). 2 According to the perdurance theory of persistence, an entity perdures iff it persists by having distinct temporal parts at distinct times (see Lewis, 1986, p. 202). The thesis of unrestricted mereological composition says that whenever there are some things, no matter how disparate and unrelated, there is something composed of just those things (again see Lewis, 1986, p. 211). 1

Phosphorus is the aggregate of the temporal parts of Venus which are visible in, and only in, the morning. In the main text Aranyosi argues that there is simply no question about the truth of the identity statement, even assuming (a) and (b). He illustrates this by considering spatial analogous. He mentions, for example, his mother s name Aranka : there is no question of whether Aranka refers to his mother, the whole person, or only to her visible skin. Same with the Moon : there is no question of whether the Moon refers only to the visible front (as seen from Earth) of the celestial object orbiting the Earth or to the whole spatial object, the far side included. Moreover, Aranyosi writes: It would also be strange for an attorney to object to my testimony in court, after I have affirmed that I saw through a keyhole, by clearly seeing his face the accused being present in some location, that what I saw was only his face, not the whole of the accused. (p. 224) These alleged spatial analogous Aranyosi takes to refute the idea that Hesperus and Phosphorus refer to distinct (and temporally scattered) proper parts of Venus. But do they refute this? Take the court case first. The attorney s objection may be understood in an epistemological way and in a metaphysical way, the latter being the relevant one here. 3 Taken in the latter way, the attorney should be understood as objecting: It is not the case that you see an entity x purely on the basis of seeing a proper part of x!. Understood in this way, the objection is indeed rather strange: I share Aranyosi s intuition that if you see a proper part of an entity x, then you see x, at least derivatively i.e. in virtue of seeing a proper part of x. 4 But I never denied this in the original paper. On the contrary, I explicitly wrote: Granting the suggested outlook, then, what we see shining on a particular early morning is a common proper part of at least two distinct things: of Venus and of Phosphorus (i.e. we see Venus and Phosphorus derivatively ) (Hansson 3 Taken in the epistemological way, the attorney should be understood as saying: But how do you know that you saw the accused person in the location if you only saw (or thought you saw) his face? In this epistemological sense, the objection seems pretty fair because the experiential content of the observation does not rule out that what was actually seen was, for example, just a photograph of the face of the accused, held up by the real criminal in front of the key hole. 4 I would deny, though, that you see an entity x directly, or non-derivatively, purely on the basis of seeing a proper part of x. Also, it seems to me that if one adds the whole of to seeing x then one signals that the subject sees x directly, or at least every exterior part if not every interior part of x directly. So if the latter was what Aranyosi said in court, then I believe he said something false. 2

Wahlberg, 2009, p. 102; emphasis added) Nor did I base the reasoning concerning the case for the non-identity of Hesperus and Phosphorus on the obviously false idea that an entity must be directly (i.e. wholly) visible in order for a name to attach to it, e.g. in an act of naming. What about the other two refuting spatial analogous? What accounts for the fact that Aranka refers to Aranyosi s mother and not to her visible skin, I think, is (roughly) that Aranka was introduced with the explicit or implicit help of a certain satisfied sortal predicate, namely person. Presumably Aranka was named via a phrase such as Let us name her (i.e. our daughter, i.e. that person) Aranka. Since the skin (visible or not) of Aranyosi s mother is not a person, but Aranyosi s mother is, the name refers to Aranyosi s mother and not to her (visible) skin. A similar story may, I suppose, be told about the reference of the Moon. 5 The Hesperus/Phosphorus case is different in this respect. The names Hesperus and Phosphorus were probably introduced with the help of unsatisfied sortal predicates, namely is a god or is a star god (or some Greek equivalent). Since there are no gods (certainly not any star gods of the kind occurring in Greek mythology) these sortal predicates were not satisfied. Does this mean that Hesperus and Phosphorus are empty, non-referring names? Some theories of naming apparently entail this (e.g. Thomasson s, 2007, p. 48). But this seems unacceptable. Surely the names refer to something even if mistaken sortal terms were used when the names were introduced (see Kripke, 1980, n. 58, pp. 115-116). But to what do they refer? For someone endorsing (a) and (b), I think there are three main candidates to consider: (1) Venus, the whole four-dimensional space-time worm 6 ; (2) the aggregate of the temporal parts of Venus which are visible in, and only in, the morning; and (3) the aggregate of the temporal parts of Venus which are visible in, and only in, the evening. 5 Let me say the obvious: we can, and certainly do, introduce names for proper parts of things: Cerebellum, Mount Everest, Alaska, the Far Side of the Moon, etc. Also, there are names purporting to name, and predicates satisfy-able by, spatially scattered entities: the Andromeda Galaxy, the Solar System, U.S.A., university, family, species, atom, etc. 6 Presumably, Venus was also introduced with the help of an unsatisfied sortal predicate ( is a god ). But here I see no relevant reason not to take the name to refer to the whole planet, i.e. to the whole fourdimensional space-time worm (given assumption (a)), if we take the name to refer at all. 3

Now, what referent-word mapping best fits the beliefs and the mythology of the ancient Greeks? 7 According to the mythology, Hesperus and Phosphorus were halfbrothers: Hesperus father was Cephalus, a mortal, while Phosphoros was the star god Astraios; their mother was dawn goddess Eos. According to the mythology, then, Hesperus and Phosphorus were distinct. Moreover, Phosphorus, but not Hesperus, was supposed to be a dawn-bearer or light-bearer, while Hesperus, but not Phosphorus, was supposed to be an evening star. Arguably, then, the referent-word mapping that best fits the beliefs and mythology of the ancient Greeks is the one which says that Phosphorus refers to (2) and Hesperus refers to (3). At the very least, it would not be totally implausible for someone who endorses (a) and (b) to treat Hesperus is Phosphorus as false. However, I do not think that there is any reasonable choice for someone endorsing the doctrine of endurance i.e. the thesis that entities persist through time by being wholly present at distinct times as numerically the same 3D entity but to identify Hesperus and Phosphorus, at least if she does not want to treat the names as empty. All in all, contrary to the apparent view of Aranyosi, I hold that the metaphysics of persistence and composition are factors to consider when evaluating identity claims involving time. 8 References Aranyosi I (2009) Hesperus is phosphorus, indeed. Axiomathes 19(2): 223-224. Hansson Wahlberg T (2009) Is phosphorus hesperus? Axiomathes 19(1): 101-102. Kripke S (1980) Naming and necessity. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. 7 No doubt, we in the 21st century may simply decide to stipulate that Hesperus and Phosphorus refer to Venus. But the question is whether such a decision is consonant with the linguistic behaviour of the ancient Greeks (see Linsky, 1959). 8 I thank Lena Wahlberg for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper. 4

Lewis D (1986) On the plurality of worlds. Blackwell Publishing, Oxford. Linsky L (1959) Hesperus and phosphorus. Philosophical Review 68(4): 515-518. Thomasson A (2007) Ordinary objects. Oxford University Press, Oxford. 5