FICHTE AND LEVINAS. THE THEORY OF MEANING AND THE ADVENT OF THE INFINITE.

Similar documents
(phénomenologia generalis) doive précéder la métaphysique» Correspondance, French translation :. Paris, Gallimard, 1986, p.70-71

THE FICHTEAN IDEA OF THE SCIENCE OF KNOWLEDGE. by Jean Hyppolite*

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

1/12. The A Paralogisms

NOTES ON BEING AND EVENT (PART 4)

Rosmini and phenomenology

Week 3: Negative Theology and its Problems

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte

Jacob Martin Rump, PhD Symposium: Contemporary Work in Phenomenology Boston Phenomenology Circle Boston University, 1 April 2016

METAPHYSICS IN DERRIDA AND LEVINAS

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

COMMENTS ON SIMON CRITCHLEY S Infinitely Demanding

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

From Phenomenology to Theology: You Spin Me Round *

Edmund Husserl s Transcendental Phenomenology by Wendell Allan A. Marinay

Études Ricœuriennes / Ricœur Studies, Vol 6, No 2 (2015), pp ISSN (online) DOI /errs

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

A Philosophical Study of Nonmetaphysical Approach towards Human Existence

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

I. THE PHILOSOPHY OF DIALOGUE A. Philosophy in General

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal

At the Frontiers of Reality

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

PHILOSOPHY IAS MAINS: QUESTIONS TREND ANALYSIS

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

Chapter 25. Hegel s Absolute Idealism and the Phenomenology of Spirit

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

Heidegger Introduction

3 Supplement. Robert Bernasconi

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

CHAPTER ONE. Immanence: A Life

BRANKO KLUN. University of Ljubljana. Horizon, Transcendence, and Correlation: Some Phenomenological Considerations 1

Affirmative Judgments: The Sabbath of Deconstruction

Heidegger's What is Metaphysics?

Kant s Transcendental Idealism

1/5. The Critique of Theology

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Philosophy Courses-1

Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

LES COURS DE GILLES DELEUZE

Kant and his Successors

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Critical Discussion of A. W. Moore s Critique of Kant

The Metaphysics of Existence Sandra Lehmann

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

DOSSIER Luca De Giovanni, Existence and Life LUCA DE GIOVANNI. 1. Straus s Criticism of Heidegger 2. The Allon and the Primal Animal Situation

Introducing Levinas to Undergraduate Philosophers

Philosophy Courses-1

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

The Supplement of Copula

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism

Affirmative Dialectics: from Logic to Anthropology

In this paper I will critically discuss a theory known as conventionalism

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

AN INTRODUCTION TO THE SPIRIT OF ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY

Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger

Brandom s Pragmatist Inferentialism and the Problem of Objectivity Ulrich Reichard University of Durham

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

Tuesday, November 11, Hegel s Idealism

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

KANT'S PROLEGOMENA TO ANY FUTURE METAPHYSICS CHICAGO DR. PAUL CARUS THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY

Death and Discourse: An Inquiry into Meaning and Disruption James R. Goebel California State University, Fullerton

Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica

ETHICS AND THE FUTURE OF HUMANKIND, REALITY OF THE HUMAN EXISTENCE

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

Gilles Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, trans. Mark Lester (New York: Columbia University Press, 1990 [Logique du sens, Minuit, 1969])

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Theories of the mind have been celebrating their new-found freedom to study

PROFESSOR FULTON'S VIEW OF PHENOMENOLOGY

Apriority from the 'Grundlage' to the 'System of Ethics'

I recently read a small book by the American cultural theorist, Eric Santner,

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

EVIL, SIN, FALSITY AND THE DYNAMICS OF FAITH. Masao Abe

The Copernican Shift and Theory of Knowledge in Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl.

John Haugeland. Dasein Disclosed: John Haugeland s Heidegger. Edited by Joseph Rouse. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2013.

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

A Multitude of Selves: Contrasting the Cartesian and Nietzschean views of selfhood

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Transcription:

FICHTE AND LEVINAS. THE THEORY OF MEANING AND THE ADVENT OF THE INFINITE. Isabelle Thomas-Fogiel Université de Paris 1, Panthéon-Sorbonne Université de Montréal Canada. INTRODUCTION : Many are the points of contact or the comparable elements in Fichte's philosophy and today's phenomenology. Most notable among them is that Fichte was the first to use the word "phenomenology" in a positive sense. Indeed, Lambert, who first introduced this word into philosophy 1, defined phenomenology as the science of illusions and considered it as strictly preparatory to the unveiling of truth. This is the meaning retained by Kant when, in his letter to Lambert, he toyed with the idea of calling "Phenomenology" the Critique of Pure Reason 2. This negative sense has even left its trace in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit since this text presents itself as an account of the illusions of conscience. Fichte differs from these philosophers and defines phenomenology positively as the science of the appearing (Erscheinungslehre). The Appearing (Erscheinen) never is the mere appearance of illusion (Schein). The phenomenon is not "fake" but the truth; it is this appearance beyond which nothing is conceivable, whether it be a thing in itself, a deeper world, or transcendence. The philosophy as phenomenology, which completes the theory of truth 3, was conceived as a "return" to the appearing ; in other words as a description of the field of the appearing. In this respect, one may assert that the criticism Husserl aims at Descartes 4 doesn't apply to Fichte who has thematized philosophy along this double line : the foundation of principles (the theory of truth) and the description of what appears (phenomenology). With Fichte as with Husserl, philosophy's two fundamental motives the "epistemic" and the "phenomenological " are complementary and not mutually exclusive, while one may easily demonstrate that, in Descartes, one has the "epistemic" without the "phenomenological", and in Heidegger we 1 in 1764 2 See his letter to Lambert of 2 septembre 1770. 3 in its strictest sense, see WL 1804, Die Wissenschaftslehre, zweiter im jahre 1804, Meiner, Philosophische Bibliothek, Hamburg, 1986, which is divided in two parts : A phenomenology and a Theory of truth. 4 in his Cartesian Meditations 10. Husserl said that Descartes doesn't cross the threshold that leads to phenomena and hence misses phenomenology. 1

have the "phenomonological" as against the "epistemic". Fichte's and Husserl's common desire that philosophy should be a rigorous science articulating in a peaceful and unified way a theory of truth and a description of phenomena seems to call for a systematic comparison of these two philosophers 5. One may wonder, then, why I haven't chosen to do just this which would no doubt represent a major challenge in the way of confronting Fichte with phenomenology? Why have I chosen to confront Fichte with an philosopher who apparently is utterly aloof from the Fichtean theme of philosophy as rigorous science? To put it differently, why have I selected a phenomenologist who has criticized the "intellectualist" and "theoreticist" Husserl, and who has denounced his desire to constitute philosophy as a rigorous science as one of the remains of the old metaphysical mode of thinking? In what manner may Levinas be compared with Fichte when, as early as his Théorie de l'intuition, he has favored the "existential" over the "epistemic", the description of the appearing over the determination of principles, the concreteness of man over the transcendental ego. Well, he may be compared with Fichte, because some central themes in his philosophy are also to be found in Fichte's first among which are the critique of representation and the description of the Other and the themes of the finite and the infinite. But he also must be compared because these themes are central to both philosophies, however radically different they remain as regards to the question of philosophy's status. Such is the identity and the difference I wish to foreground here today, in order to better raise the question of the "transcendental" in phenomenology. Indeed, as we'll see, what is essentially at stake in this comparison between Fichte and Levinas is the question of the meaning and status of the transcendental in phenomenology. Finally, Fichte is closer to Husserl than Levinas because he is a transcendantal s philosopher. Before seeing this point, I must show first : How identical are Fichte and Levinas : 1/ HOW IDENTICAL ARE FICHTE AND LEVINAS? One must first try to establish how identical Fichte and Levinas are since they are seldom compared. However three central and constitutive elements in Levinas's thought are to be found in almost identical form in Fichte's philosophy. These three elements are the critique of representation, the description of the Other, and the extension to non-æsthetic realms of the 5 for which Hyppolite's article "La doctrine de la science chez Fichte et Husserl ", Paris, PUF, 1954, early paved the way. 2

problematics of the sublime as relating the finite and the infinite. I shall first analyse these three points. a) The Critique of Representation While it is well known that Levinas sees his philosophy as a critique of metaphysical objectivism 6, Fichte's involvement with such themes is not really self-evident. And yet, the totality of Fichte's philosophy may be read as a critique of representation 7. Indeed, Fichte questions Kant's equation, according to which to know is to represent, and to represent is to make the object figurable. For Kant, figuration defined as circumscription or as the ascription of a limit is the condition of possibility of knowledge. In this context, knowledge refers to the figure, to delineation, and to the limit. For Kant, to know is to represent, and to represent is to make the object visible thanks to the schema that imposes a form, a contour in other words, that creates a figure. Figuration becomes the sign of true knowledge, the nonfigurable remains in the realm of falsehood and deception. Fichte happens to question the linking of figure and knowledge and of the limit and representation, and formulates the existence of modes of knowledge that go beyond a mere representation as figuration. Concerning the determination of principles what he defines as the "doctrine of truth" in the 1804 Wissenschaftslehre Fichte unveils a cognitive process which he calls the illimitation of the limit. By this, he describes the movement of reason that makes infinite that which is given as finite. One may illustrate this process with the example of the triangle. I form a mental representation of a triangle. The triangle, defined by its limits, is finite by essence. But this "line", or "limit", must be included into some vaster "space" in order to appear as a line or a limit. Indeed, were I unable to think beyond the mere limits of the triangle, it would not appear to me as a triangle that is to say, as a finite figure. In other words, I must constitute a horizon within which the triangle may appear as a limit. By establishing this perimeter (Umfang) within which the limit may appear, the I, says Fichte, "illimits the limit." It becomes clear that, in order to be properly thought, an object has to be thus infinitized. To know is not solely to limit and to set boundaries to an object. To know also consists in "infinitizing" and "illimiting". b) The Phenomenological description of the Other 6 For exemple in his : Ruine de la représentation, 1959, published in En découvrant l existence avec Husserl et Heidegger, Paris, Vrin 1974. 7 This critique which, as with Levinas, opens onto the specific thinking of the Other. See I. Thomas-Fogiel : Critique de la représentation, Etudes sur Fichte, Paris, Vrin 2000. 3

This cognitive process, which Fichte describes at the level of the "doctrine of truth", will find an equivalent at another level, which in the 1804 WL he calls phenomenology or the doctrine of phenomena. In other words, Fichte makes a phenomenological description that illustrates a process previously unveiled as inherent to reason in his epistemic elucidation of principles. What I am referring to, here, is his description of the appearing of the Other, as found in his Fondations of Natural Right. This text is the exact phenomenological equivalent of the illimitation of the limit described in the first WL (GWL 1794). First, Fichte reminds us what is traditionally understood by "understanding" a phenomenon. He writes that "to understand is to fix, to delimit and to determine." The limit, or the act of drawing a limit, is a condition of understanding. But the whole demonstration that follows will try to establish that one may not understand the appearing of the Other, that one may not bound it within limits, or give it a definitive outline. The last stage in the description will make clear that a limit cannot be imposed or found. The face of the Other is precisely that which cannot be delimited and seems to outgrow all ascribable limits. By attempting to determine the Other, one draws a limit that one will need to trespass immediately afterwards. Every progress in the analysis outgrows a limit. Every moment in the demonstration rolls back the limit a little further. As successive attempts to reductively delimit fail, the Other becomes less clearly visible and the limits recede. As the demonstration progresses, what was initially to be delimited and understood becomes ever less visible. The face of the Other resists all limitation or delineation. And this necessary failure to reduce the face of the Other to a mere figure is precisely whence, for Fichte, true knowledge may emerge. Indeed, it is because the body of the Other (Leib, chair) does not let itself be fixed or determined that it may be thought as the locus where the infinite of freedom expresses itself. Because he is a bearer of the infinite, the Other cannot be reduced to limits. This is the reason why the demonstration must always roll back the limit and effect its illimitation and this illimitation of the limit is what gives access to the knwowledge of the Other as a free being. In this context, the illimitation of the limit becomes one of the modalities of knowing. It then becomes rather easy to compare Fichte's precise description with Levinas's developments against objectivating thought, against "representation", which he means to surpass in order to account for the irruption of the Other 8. Alterity, conceived as a trace of the infinite, is what allows to outflank traditional 8 The irruption of the Other, such as one may find it exemplified in the face of the Other whose, "only meaning is irrecusable" : Autrement qu'être,, Paris, Le Livre de poche,, 1978, p. 240. We translate. 4

philosophical thought to finally feel the eros of genuine thought 9. What we have in both Fichte and Levinas is this idea that objectifying representation may and must be outgrown by a thinking of the infinite of which the face of the Other is a manifestation. This irruption of the infinite in the field of philosophical thought must now be the focus of our attention. c) The Infinite in Philosophy Let us first recall what, to my mind, is one of the most significant propositions of the Wissenschaftslehre, namely, that the movement of knowledge is the process of the sublime. The sublime is not to be relegated to the sole domain of the æsthetic: the sublime is the dynamics of the mind. Promoting the concept of the sublime to the level of a gnoseological process is what is done by each WL, and this promotion always guides us from the critique of objectifying knowledge to the definition of a knowledge beyond representation. In Kant's Third Critique, the sublime is defined as an attempt to "present the infinite". In this context, the sublime is beauty 's counter-concept 10. The beautiful harks back to ideas of contours, delineation and limits, while the sublime proceeds inversely and attempts to present the infinite. The sublime presents itself as an anti-figure. But while the process of the sublime is an attempt to present the infinite, it is obviously not a positive presentation. It is quite telling, in this respect, that the statement Kant presents as an example of the sublime should be the Second Commandment 11. Because the infinite cannot be contained in a finite figure, the sublime is a sign of the failure of figuration, of objectifying representation, and of the circumscription within defined limits. The sublime is this moment when figuration is being recused ; since the sublime's task is to interweave the finite and the infinite into one self-same act, representation is not to be resorted to, it is to be questioned.. In other words, for Kant, the sublime questions the representable, while Fichte sees it as the very sign of the ongoing process of knowledge. If, among many possible other examples, one focuses on the structure of the WL Nova Methodo, the dynamics is that of the sublime. In the very first paragraphs, Fichte explains that the I cannot immediately apply the predicate "infinite" to himself in other words, the infinite of freedom cannot be represented without being determined and limited 12. Thus the contradiction between freedom and representation is born. It is the moment 9. "The face, against contemporary ontology, brings up a notion of truth that is not the unveiling of some impersonal neutrality" : Totalité et infini, Le livre de poche, 1974, p. 43. We translate. 10 since beauty always proceeds from the object's form or figure, and the figure is a delimitation. 11 : "You shall not make for yourself a graven image, or any likeness of anything that is in heaven above, or that is in the earth beneath, or that is in the water under the earth." 12 But this limitation seems to require that an object or a figure be constituted which, being inserted within precise limits, may become apprehensible. 5

of failure for the kantian analysis of the sublime. But this is a fruitful failure that breeds new concepts, such as the concept of the end and the categorical imperative. The interrelation of the finite and of the infinite as dynamics of freedom and of the knowledge of freedom, is not some unreachable ideal but the very process by which truth is being engendered. Intermediate concepts 13 are the truths given to us by this movement of rationality. Thus the infinite is not a being that stands without thought anymore, a being that thought would need to objectify, to determine, to limit, and hence, inevitably, to negate. The infinite is the very process of thought. The infinite is what reason generates through its very praxis. And now, of course, this decisive importance of the infinite obviously is one of the main characteristics of Levinas's thought. Being an ethical notion par excellence, the infinite, for Levinas, is the ultimate condition of possibility which is itself a radical transcendence, extreme difference, absolute alterity. Contrary to the classical philosophies of identity and totality, Levinas aims to foreground a philosophy of difference, of the Other and of the infinite (see Totalité et infini). Thus emerges a true similarity between the two philosophies that hinges on this capital point that is the thinking of the infinite, or, to be more precise, that the thinking is the infinite. We may now consider that the two philosophers' identity becomes assured. They share the same critique of representation, the same phenomenological description of the Other, the same value given to the infinite and the same promotion of the sublime. All these points are so central in their philosophies that one is now tempted to ask, not what makes their thoughts comparable but what makes them different. Naturally, the difference is radical and it explains why the two philosophers have never truly been either assimilated or compared. But this very difference, again, finds its source in a new and fundamental proximity that makes the comparison fruitful. It is this proximity I now wish to describe and I will later deal with how these two philosophers are radically opposed. 2/ THE SIMILARITY OF THE TWO AUTHORS' THEORY OF MEANING a) Fichte's Theory of Meaning Indeed, Levinas and Fichte share another decisive position: they both reject a strictly semantic theory of truth and try to make the Saying emerge within the Said within what is being said. To demonstrate this, one must first sum up what is Fichte's theory of meaning. The 13 For example the concept of the end, the categorical imperative, space and the Other in the WL Nova Methodo 6

Wissenschaftslehre s base a theory of meaning on the Saying (Sagen) and the Doing (Tun) 14. The Saying (Sagen) is here to be understood as being the contents of a philosopher's speech say, Kant or Spinoza. So, if it is in the WL1804 WL that we find the expression adequation between Tun und sagen, we have equivalents in WL 1794 with the expression the conformity between the explication and what is explicated 15, or of course what is done and the "doing" ; or the famous opposition between The posited ( for example Setzen or Ich gesetze,) and the positing ( Setzend) 16 etc. This Fichtean Saying may thus be compared to what pragmatics, beginning with Austin, has called the "propositional content". As for the Doing, it must be strictly understood as the act or the status of the enunciation: it is not what Kant says but, as proposed in the 1804 WL, "what he presupposes in order to be able to say what he says." 17 Thus in the proposition "I am not speaking," the Saying is what this proposition says, while the Doing is what makes it possible ; in other words, the very act of speaking. In this case, one immediatly notes that this very act falsifies the propositional content. In other words, the fundamental principle of Fichte's theory is what, after Austin and Recanati, we now call the performative non-contradiction or pragmatic identity. Fichte thus develops a true and precise theory of meaning, based on the notions of Saying and Doing, which Levinas will develop as the theory of the Saying and the Said. The way they both account for the Saying within the Said is a capital point. Levinas will also recuse all semantic theories of meaning and he will introduce the dimension of the Saying within the Said. However, his theory of meaning will end up being the symetrical reverse of Fichte's. This is why we'll need to examine Levinas's theory. b) Levinas's Theory of Meaning It is in Autrement qu'être that Levinas uses the categories of the Said and the Saying in order to develop what he calls "the very signifiance of meaning." (la veritable signifiance de la signification ) 18 Always eager to get rid of Husserl's "objectivism", he attempts to refute 14 It is the expression of WL 1804, Die Wissenschaftslehre, zweiter im jahre 1804, For example p. 191, and also Introductions of 1798. About this relation between Tun und sagen in 1804, see I.Thomas-Fogiel, Fichte, réflexion et argumentation, Paris, Vrin 2004. 15 Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre als Handschrift fûr seine Zuhörer (1794 = WL1794), Hambourg, Meiner, Philosophische Bibliothek, 1979, p. 131. 16 See 1794, Meiner p 131, and so the beginning of Wissenschafltslehre Nova methodo or Fondations of Natural Right, etc. 17 Die Wissenschaftslehre, zweiter im jahre 1804, Meiner, p. 18. French editors : Aubier-Montaigne, Paris 1967, translate by D...Julia «l on étudie Kant ici non comme l ont fait tous les kantiens sans exception en collant à la lettre [ ] mais en s élevant de ce qu il dit réellement à ce qu il ne doit pas mais devrait présupposer pour pouvoir dire ce qu il dit» p.34. 18 Autrement qu être, Paris, le livre de poche, 1978 p. 17 7

Husserl's semantic intentionality. Indeed, for Husserl, the Said, conceived of as a theme, as what is being said, that is, as object, tends to supersede all other aspects. Husserl's aim could be described as an attempt to obfuscate the Saying in order to promote the Said. In this respect, he would be as positivistic as the members of the Circle of Vienna. For Husserl, Levinas tells us, the correlation of the Said and the Saying is nothing but "the subordination of the Saying to the Said": "the Said dominates the Saying that enounces it." 19 But for Levinas the Saying does not vanish in apophansis": one must revise the whole western theory of meaning which is but the offshoot of the theory of objectivity, a corollary of "representationalism" and of the imperialism of "objecthood". But one may ask what is the Saying if the Said is the theme, the object, the content? It is not the act performed by the enouncing subject. For Levinas Saying is Speech addressed to the other, turned towards the other. It is before all Said, and hence before all object-oriented intentionality. The Saying will end up being defined as "supreme passivity of the exposition to the Other." This exposition by which I offer myself up to the Other makes me infinitely vulnerable. This vulnerability is born of the "sincerity" with which I give myself up to the Other. "Saying to the Other" comes before "anything Said" and conditions it. Levinas writes: "It is necessary that one reach this Saying before the Said, or that one reduce the Said to it." 20 This saying that always-already constitues me and by which I connect with the Other by sincerely exposing myself, this "here I am" is the trace of the infinite that traverses me. This "Thou" of which I am the answer, this "Thou" that makes me become an "here I am", actually is, originarly, God's call. The analysis of the Saying thus leads us to what Levinas calls "the glory of the infinite." Ultimately, the Saying is how the infinite is being said within each one of us. The successive substitutions in Autrement qu'être are clear. They lead us from the Saying to the Response to the Other, from the Response to Sincerity and from Sincerity to "the infinite saying itself". The significance is that of the Infinite, my saying bears its trace, just like Abraham's "here I am " bore God's call within itself. It is thus confirmed that Levinas's theory of meaning is the Husserl theory turned upside-down. The Saying comes before the Said. Semantics is thus relativized not by a theory of the act or a pragmatics, but by a re-thinking of the sublime, which amounts to an irruption of the infinite, that disorganizes the orderly relations between what is said and the very fact of saying it. 19 ibid. p.19. 20 ibid. p. 241 8

We may now summarize these two thinkers' theories of meaning. What they have in common is that they both take into account the Saying in the Said. They both deal with a nonsemantic dimension of meaning. But this convergence is the basis for a radical difference, for Levinas will end up producing a theory that is exactly the opposite of Fichte's. Their theories are so symmetrically opposed that the one may be seen as the other's reverse or inverted figure. The identity I described in my first part and the proximity I suggested in my second part actually lead to a radical opposition I now wish to describe. III) THE INVERTED FIGURE. IDENTITY OR PERFORMATIVE CONTRADICTION AS CONDITION FOR THE ADVENT OF THE INFINITE a) Fichte's Pragmatic Identity as Giving Access to the Infinite Fichte's theory of meaning took into account the Tun in the Sagen and foregrounded a new principle of identity that was to become a model for all philosophical statements to come. Identity, strictly considered as the adequation of the utterance and the enunciation, or as the congruence of the Saying and the Doing, must be the philosopher's goal, if the philosopher wishes to reach truth and to avoid the contradictions that have wrecked all other philosophies whether it be Spinoza's, Kant's or Jacobi's.. The contradiction is not a contradiction in terms of formal logic, whether it be the traditional logic of predicates (A is A) or propositional logic (P implies Q).. Neither is it a contradiction between two opposed elements, such as the Newtonian contradiction of physical forces that Kant called opposition, nor a contradiction between my proposition and the object it is supposed to convey. Actually, it is a contradiction between the act of saying X and what is being said of X strictly speaking, a performative contradiction. This non-contradiction is the supreme law of reason that will generate the process of infinitization and illimitation above described. The identity of the supposing (posits) and the supposed is an act we perform. It is an originary act, with neither cause nor necessity, which is by the very fact that it is effected, performed and accomplished. The freedom of the first principle is the starting point and should also be the point of arrival.. In our every concepts and productions, we must realize this identity, that is to say that, in one single act, we must think contradictory determinations. (such as the posits of freedom and the knowledge of freedom). Realizing this amounts to an effectuation of the sublime process. It does not lead to failure but to the creation of new, intermediate concepts 9

that all express reflexive identity. 21. For example, in the 1804 WL, the Urbegriff will serve to think the opposition between light and concept and will here again function as a hinge between the finite and the infinite. It is the realization of reflexive identity that leads to the sublime. There is thus a link, in Fichte's thought, between the identity principle, the thinking of the infinite through the infinitization process, and the production of rationally verifiable concepts. Well, things are exactly the opposite in Levinas. b) Performative Contradiction as the Access to the Infinite in Levinas For Levinas, it is the performative contradiction that allows the Infinite to irrupt into speech. The philosopher must accept the performative contradiction in order to allow the infinite to manifest itself. This is what Levinas, in Autrement qu'être, calls "the philosopher's retraction" ( dédit du philosophe 22 ). The philosopher must accept this gaping void, and should not attempt to fill it in by arguing some impossible coherence 23. The philosopher must accept this "retraction" in order to better signifiy "the nearness where the infinite occurs." Philosophy, by exhibiting its failure, by accepting this retraction, by renouncing this coherence, leaves room for another mode of expression: revelation and prophecy. The performative contradiction thus becomes the trace of God, the expression of the sublime. The performative contradiction helps us think the infinite within the finite, the unsayable at the very heart of what is said. The performative contradiction, actually, is the "presentation of the infinite" a presentation which, in Kant's words, is given in the impossibility of presentation. This "retraction of the philosopher" leads Levinas back to the prophetic utterance, and leads him to call for philosophy to be superseded in religion. The successive substitutions in Autrement qu'être and Etudes talmudiques are clear: Levinas states the performative contradiction, accepts it and overturns it and makes of our impossibility to supersede it the very trace of God in us. We should give up philosophy in favor of religion, give up Husserl in favor of Isaiah who is symptomatically mentioned in these pages of Autrement qu'être that claim the performative contradiction. The difference between the two philosophers then appears clearly. Fichte poses pragmatic identity as the condition of the advent of the infinite and the condition of philosophy. Levinas poses pragmatic contradiction as the condition of the irruption of the 21 In the WL nova methodo, for instance, the categorical imperative is the only non-contradictory way to associate freedom and knowledge, thus making it function as a hinge between the finite and the infinite. 22 Op.cit p. 19 et 20 23 Levinas writes : "Thinking the otherwise than being calls perhaps for more daring than the skeptic who does not fear to assert the impossibility of the utterance while he realizes this impossibility by the very utterance of it." in Autrement qu être p. 84 ; we translate. 10

infinite and the supersedence of philosophy (the philosopher's retraction). We thus clearly have here theories that are symmetrically opposed. And this strict inversion of the symmetrical pattern, to my mind, says something about the meaning of the transcendental in today's phenomenology. It is with this suggestion that I wish to conclude. CONCLUSION It has become rather common, today, to oppose to the transcendental Husserl, the "first" analytical and realist Husserl of the Logical investigations and the "third", "genetic" or late Husserl, somehow prefiguring today's existential themes. The introduction of Fichte in this debate will allow us to overcome these ruptures and to formulate differently the question of Husserl's coherence. Indeed, it seems to me that the three periods in Husserl's thought are the effect of his disciples' readings and not of his own. Thus, Levinas who has introduced Husserl in France and has influenced Sartre's and Derrida's interpretations of his work has greatly biased husserlian thought by stressing the rejection of the theme of philosophy as science, the rejection of reason, and the rejection of the transcendental. By promoting contradiction, Levinas chooses un-reason that leads us to religion. On the contrary, Fichte chooses reason, whose law is performative identity, and which allows to maintain the goals of a philosophy considered as science. Comparing Fichte and Levinas thus allows or even compels us in retrospect to evaluate the true meaning of Husserl's work. Should we give precedence to the latest Husserl, as Levinas does as well as Merleau-Ponty, Michel Henry and Jean-Luc Marion after him, and many other phenomenologists today, or should we attempt, along with Fichte, to ponder anew the notion of philosophy as science? Such, in my mind, is the question raised by the topic we have here been invited to reflect upon. 11