The Structural and the Semantic Subject-Object and Referential-Predicative Asymmetries

Similar documents
Russell: On Denoting

Topics in Linguistic Theory: Propositional Attitudes

Puzzles of attitude ascriptions

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. [Handout 7] W. V. Quine, Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes (1956)

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a

Some observations on identity, sameness and comparison

Comments on Saul Kripke s Philosophical Troubles

ATINER's Conference Paper Series PHI Scope of Semantic Innocence

Affirmation-Negation: New Perspective

Class #9 - The Attributive/Referential Distinction

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Coordination Problems

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

Quine: Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes

Factivity and Presuppositions David Schueler University of Minnesota, Twin Cities LSA Annual Meeting 2013

Comments on Carl Ginet s

ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS

(1) a phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything e.g. the present King of France

10. Presuppositions Introduction The Phenomenon Tests for presuppositions

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames Draft March 1, My theory of propositions starts from two premises: (i) agents represent things as

Presupposition and Rules for Anaphora

PROPOSITIONAL ATTITUDE REPORTS

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

A Linguistic Interlude

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

Supplementary Section 6S.7

Keeping track of individuals

Todays programme. Background of the TLP. Some problems in TLP. Frege Russell. Saying and showing. Sense and nonsense Logic The limits of language

Draft January 19, 2010 Draft January 19, True at. Scott Soames School of Philosophy USC. To Appear In a Symposium on

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Class #7 - Russell s Description Theory

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 DE RE AND DE DICTO: AGAINST THE CONVENTIONAL WISDOM 1. Kenneth A. Taylor Stanford University

Conference on the Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, PUCRS, Porto Alegre (Brazil), June

Kant on the Notion of Being İlhan İnan

The Two Indexical Uses Theory of Proper Names and Frege's Puzzle

Analyticity and reference determiners

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

propositional attitudes: issues in semantics

Brainstorming exercise

Reference and Naturalism. Akeel Bilgrami. Very slightly revised version of a paper first published with the title Why Holism is

Direct and Indirect Belief

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. P. F. Strawson: On Referring

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 1)

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

KAPLAN RIGIDITY, TIME, A ND MODALITY. Gilbert PLUMER

Propositional Attitudes and Mental Acts. Indrek Reiland. Peter Hanks and Scott Soames have recently developed similar views of propositional attitudes

CHAPTER 1 A PROPOSITIONAL THEORY OF ASSERTIVE ILLOCUTIONARY ARGUMENTS OCTOBER 2017

Reconsidering Raising and Experiencers in English

Linguistic Society of America

CONTENT INSIDE OUT. Joseph Mendola s Anti-Externalism 1 defends internalism,

To Appear in Philosophical Studies symposium of Hartry Field s Truth and the Absence of Fact

Reference and Reflexivity

1 Clarion Logic Notes Chapter 4

Be Bound or Be Disjoint! Andrew Kehler and Daniel Büring. UCSD and UCLA

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

Pronominal, temporal and descriptive anaphora

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

Philosophers of language have lavished attention on names and other singular referring

Theories of propositions

Durham Research Online

Frode Bjørdal ON BELIEFS. 1. Introduction

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames. sentence, or the content of a representational mental state, involves knowing which

Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social

Artificial Intelligence Prof. P. Dasgupta Department of Computer Science & Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

6 Davidson, Heidegger, and Truth

John Buridan. Summulae de Dialectica IX Sophismata

17. Tying it up: thoughts and intentionality

hates the woman [who rejected him i hates the woman [who rejected Peter i ] is hated by him i ] (Langacker 1969: 169) (2) (3) (4a) (4b) (4) a. S b.

Why the Traditional Conceptions of Propositions can t be Correct

Moral Expressivism and Sentential Negation. Neil Sinclair

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Language, Meaning, and Information: A Case Study on the Path from Philosophy to Science Scott Soames

A set of puzzles about names in belief reports

Lecture 9: Presuppositions

HS01: The Grammar of Anaphora: The Study of Anaphora and Ellipsis An Introduction. Winkler /Konietzko WS06/07

Singular Propositions and Singular Thoughts

A Model of Decidable Introspective Reasoning with Quantifying-In

russell s theory of propositions

Class 8 - The Attributive/Referential Distinction

Philosophy 1760 Philosophy of Language

The Metaphysics of Propositions. In preparing to give a theory of what meanings are, David Lewis [1970] famously wrote:

In this section you will learn three basic aspects of logic. When you are done, you will understand the following:

Critical Appreciation of Jonathan Schaffer s The Contrast-Sensitivity of Knowledge Ascriptions Samuel Rickless, University of California, San Diego

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Russell on Descriptions

Figure 1: Laika. Definite Descriptions Jean Mark Gawron San Diego State University. Definite Descriptions: Pick out an entity in the world (Figure 1)

Kripke s revenge. Appeared in Philosophical Studies 128 (2006),

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

On the Aristotelian Square of Opposition

Logophors, variable binding and the interpretation of have. *

Against Sainsbury and Tye s Originalism

The projection problem of presuppositions

Transcription:

UCLA Working Papers in Linguistics, Theories of Everything Volume 17, Article 29: 243-252, 2012 The Structural and the Semantic Subject-Object and Referential-Predicative Asymmetries Adèle Mercier Introduction Kripke s Puzzle about Belief shows how difficult it can be to state what others believe. We can only do so in our language, but our language imposes presuppositions on others that they may not share. Kripke concludes that the reason lies in the nature of the realm being entered ; that our normal practices of attributing belief are questionable ; that the situation of the puzzle seems to lead to a breakdown of our normal practices of attributing belief and even of indirect quotation. Kaplan concurs, cautioning us about always accepting as legitimate the demand for reports in indirect discourse: since certain expressions have non-translational semantics, we should expect difficulties in making indirect reports of speech and thought involving indexicals, expressives, and other translation-resistant expressions. There are good and obvious reasons why reporting others states of mind should be difficult. After all, we don t read minds. I offer here some reflections that suggest, pace Kripke and Kaplan, that language may contain more available means for indirect reporting of beliefs than customarily appreciated. What makes our normal practice of attributing beliefs questionable or not always legitimate may pertain, not to a difference of realm being entered, but to our insufficient sensitivity to existing semantic subtleties already at play in our language. 1 Subject-Object Asymmetries in Syntax and Semantics Subject-object asymmetries are legion in syntax, and have been well-studied. We find subject-object asymmetries in multiple questions: I don t remember who SUBJ found what OBJ. * I don t remember what OBJ who SUBJ found [t OBJ ]. Relativizations out of objects, but not subjects, require DO-support: What OBJ did John SUBJ find [t OBJ ]? * What OBJ John SUBJ found [t OBJ ]? * Who SUBJ did find a hat OBJ? Who SUBJ found a hat OBJ? That-trace effects occur with subjects but not objects: * Who SUBJ do you think that [t SUBJ ] found a hat OBJ? What OBJ do you think that John SUBJ found [t OBJ ]? 2012 Adèle Mercier This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of a Creative Commons Non-Commercial License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/3.0/).

244 Mercier Parasitic gaps are sanctioned with object, but not with subject, relativization: Which article OBJ did John SUBJ file [t OB ] without reading [t OBJ ]? * Who SUBJ filed which article OBJ without reading [t OBJ ]? Such subject-object asymmetries are given structural explanations. In GB theory, the distinctions are expressed in sentence structure, the subject being an external argument, the object an internal argument of the VP, and the above effects are attributed to various violations: subjacency, case filters, theta-theory, the Empty Category Principle. Subject-object asymmetries are also legion in semantics, where they have also been well studied. Klima (1964) remarks on the ambiguity of (1.a) versus the unambiguity of (1.b): (1.a) He required that she marry [no one OBJ ]. (1.b) He required that [no one SUBJ ] marry her. Kayne (1981) questions the intelligibility of (2.a) versus the unproblematic (2.b): (2.a) * In all these years he suggested that [not a single term paper SUBJ ] be written. (2.b) In all these years he suggested that they write [not a single term paper OBJ ]. May (1985) notes the distributive readings of (3.a) and (4.a) and their lack in (3.b) and (4.b): (3.a) What OBJ did everyone bring [t OBJ ]? (3.b) Who SUBJ brought everything? (4.a) Who(m) OBJ did everyone talk to [t OBJ ]? (4.b) Who SUBJ talked to everyone? Whether well or incompletely understood, these are well-attested phenomena. 2 Subject-Object Metalinguistic Asymmetries It is a simple rule of logic that from knowledge of P, and knowledge of Q, we can infer knowledge of P&Q. Beliefs, as we know, are more complicated. As Kripke s Puzzle shows, Pierre can assent to, and thus be reported disquotationally as believing that P: and that Q: P Londres SUBJ est jolie. [translation: London is pretty.] Q London SUBJ is not pretty. while not as believing that P & Q, at least as a belief reported in English: P&Q London SUBJ is pretty and London SUBJ is not pretty.

The Structural and the Semantic Subject-Object and Referential-Predicative Asymmetries 245 (Pierre might assent to a report of his belief as that London is not pretty but Londres is. But as Kripke points out, we are hard pressed to identify how this belief would differ in content from the previous, disavowed. We might say that Pierre believes: and!x (x est jolie et x = Londres)!y (y is not pretty and y = London) but it is wholly unclear how these beliefs differ.) The phenomenon extends to definite descriptions, not just proper names. Thus Pierre can be reported as believing that P: P [La ville de Londres] SUBJ est jolie. [translation: The city of London is pretty.] and as believing that Q: Q [The city of London] SUBJ is not pretty. while not as believing that P & Q: P&Q [The city of London] SUBJ is pretty and [the city of London] SUBJ is not pretty. This well-known puzzle, about how distinct co-designative names, London and Londres, feature in belief, really is a puzzle, and I shall not purport to solve it. A different, complementary, puzzle involves identical differently-designative names. Certain features of this one have not, to my knowledge, been noticed. I know two people named Edward L. Keenan, so I can truthfully say: (5.a) (5.b) I believe that ELK SUBJ is a linguist at UCLA. I believe that ELK SUBJ is a historian at Harvard. It would be syntactically awkward some sort of binding violation? to report my belief as: (6.a) * Adèle believes that ELK SUBJ is a linguist at UCLA and ELK SUBJ is a historian at Harvard. It would be false and/or semantically anomalous to report my beliefs as: (6.b) Adèle believes that ELK SUBJ is a linguist at UCLA and a historian at Harvard. It s hardly better to report my belief as: (6.c) * Adèle believes that ELK SUBJ are a linguist at UCLA and a historian at Harvard. But note the improvement with: (7.a) Adèle believes that a linguist at UCLA and a historian at Harvard are ELK OBJ. or even better:

246 Mercier (7.b) Adèle believes that a linguist at UCLA and a historian at Harvard are {each/both} ELK OBJ. Now, (7.a) may be ambiguous, between one reading where a single ELK is both a linguist at UCLA and a historian at Harvard a reading better instantiated by: (7.c) Adèle believes that the linguist at UCLA and the historian at Harvard are {each/both} ELK OBJ, and another where there are two ELKs. But interestingly, (7.a) and (7.b) both have a metalinguistic reading that works, where the name ELK stands for a name-type, rather than a referential name token. The metalinguistic reading is predicative: the copula is understood as the is of predication is an ELK, or ELK x, in the sense that we can say that there are many Edwards in the world; it is not referential: the copula is not understood as the is of identity (= ELK). This metalinguistic effect is predictably missing from (6.b) and (6.c), where ELK appears in a canonically referential position, and, for the same reason, no more available in (6.d): (6.d) Adèle believes that ELK {each/both} are a linguist at UCLA and a historian at Harvard. The metalinguistic reading from subject position can only be induced with considerable lexical specification: (6.e) Adèle believes that two ELKs {each/both} are {respectively} a linguist at UCLA and a historian at Harvard. or even with outright metalinguistic intention: (6.f) Adèle believes that two persons named ELK {each/both} are {respectively} a linguist at UCLA and a historian at Harvard. The metalinguistic reading from subject position is induced by clearly transforming a referential name token (ELK) into a predicative name-type (ELKs), or an outright predicate (persons named ELK ). These judgments are fully generalizable. (8.a) Pierre believes that Paderewski SUBJ is a pianist and a politician. (9.a) Pierre believes that London SUBJ is both the pretty city and the ugly city. are false (or unattributable to Pierre); but (8.b) Pierre believes that a pianist and a politician are {both, each} Paderewski OBJ. is true, on the available metalinguistic reading. The case of London/Londres confirms, negatively, the availability of the metalinguistic reading (only) in object position. For it is not true to say: (9.b) Pierre believes that the pretty city and the ugly city are {both, each} London OBJ.

The Structural and the Semantic Subject-Object and Referential-Predicative Asymmetries 247 but it is not true is precisely for metalinguistic reasons: since he thinks of the pretty city under the French name Londres and of the ugly city under the English name London, Pierre lacks (at least for the purpose of this example) the required metalinguistic predicate is a London or Londons. This feature is not essential to the puzzle however. The same puzzle arises even without different languages. Monolingual Peter could think London is pretty because he saw pictures of it in a book, and that (another) London is ugly as he wanders through it, in which case, on its metalinguistic reading, the belief attribution would be true: (9.c) Peter believes that the pretty city and the ugly city are {both, each} London OBJ. Note that the verb to be is essential to the metalinguistic reading. It is unavailable under the semantically related ressembles or is similar to, which induce a referential interpretation: (10.a) Adèle believes that a linguist at UCLA and a historian at Harvard are {each/both} ELK..b {both, each} resemble ELK..c are {each/both} similar to ELK. (11.a) Pierre believes that a pianist and a politician are Paderewski..b resemble Paderewski..c are similar to Paderewski. (12.a) Peter believes that the pretty city and the ugly city are London..b resemble London..c are similar to London. Note that is identical to renders the sentence false, for the same reason, while the is of predication yields true (metalinguistic) belief attributions: (10.d) Adèle believes that a ling. at UCLA and a historian at H are {each/both} identical to ELK..e are {each/both} an ELK. (11.d) Pierre believes that a pianist and a politician are identical to Paderewski..e are a Paderewski. (12.d) Peter believes that the pretty city and the ugly city are identical to London..e are a London. The difference between the is of predication and the is of identity is, of course, the ontological categories that flank the is : is of identity: is the or is NP = x, for x denoting an object is of predication: is a Fx, for F denoting a property The reason the is of predication is required to yield true belief attributions in the above cases is because only metalinguistic attributions can be true, and these involve beliefs about properties (being an ELK), not objects (ELK). Kripke s puzzle is not a puzzle only when it relates a believer to a property (being a Paderewski), rather than an object (Paderewski). The puzzle occurs because Pierre harbours a confusion about the reference of Paderewski, and Peter of London (in particular, that there are not two such objects but one). And the difficulty in stating Adèle s belief is the complementary one, precisely that she knows that ELK does have

248 Mercier dual reference. Belief attributions succeed in such cases only when they are about predication ( are {both} ELKs ), not reference (ELK). Puzzling belief attributions find an outlet in reports from the object, rather than subject, position, as the above subject-object asymmetries reveal. But these subject-object asymmetries are not amenable to structural explanations. The difference between is the and is a is not cashed out in structural or syntactic terms (structurally they are both derived from VP V + NP), but in semantic (or functional or logical or ontological) terms: the first denotes an object, the second a property. We tentatively conclude then that, despite appearances, the above facts are not truly subject-object asymmetries after all. The distinction between a subject and an object are expressed in sentence structure, the subject being an external argument, the object an internal argument of the VP. The effective distinction here is not structural but semantic: it is that between a referential and a predicative interpretation of structural positions. It is true that the subject position canonically in first-order language receives a referential interpretation, and the object in a VP whose head is the is of predication receives a predicative interpretation. But these are canonical regularities, not explanations, as we show below. 3 Referential-Predicative Expressive Asymmetries Interestingly (although predictably, given the present analysis), the metalinguistic referential-predicative effects displayed above also appear in derogation inheritance. Imagine, as per Kaplan (1999), cretinous UC Regents saying: (13) That bastard Kaplan was promoted. Clearly, (13) carries a presupposition about K, namely that he is a bastard (in the expressive, not the literal, sense). It is clear that whoever reports the Regents belief thusly: (14) The UC Regents believe [that bastard Kaplan] SUBJ was promoted. inherits the derogatory presupposition. The only way to report the Regent s belief without inheriting the derogation is by saying: (15) The UC Regents believe Kaplan is a bastard OBJ who was promoted. This effect is strikingly robust. While the speaker inherits the derogation (big time!) in the referential: (16) The UC Regents believe the REF g-d-d-mned f-ing bastard Kaplan was promoted. the inheritance is cancelled in the predicational: (17) The UC Regents believe that Kaplan is a PRED g-d-d-mned f-ing bastard who was promoted. which acquires a metalinguistic reading. (17.a) UCR stupidly believe that K is a PRED g-d-d-mned f-ing bastard who was promoted.

The Structural and the Semantic Subject-Object and Referential-Predicative Asymmetries 249.b UCR just believe, for no reason at all, that K is a g-d-d-mned f-ing bastard who was promoted..c Those cretin UCR believe that K is a g-d-d-mned f-ing bastard who was promoted. The referential-predicative distinction explains judgments of presupposition inheritance in belief reports better than a subject-object asymmetry. The speaker inherits the derogation with a referential NP in both subject and object position: (18.a) The UC Regents believe [that REF bastard Kaplan] SUBJ should not have been promoted..b The UC Regents believe the Phil Dept should not have promoted [that REF bastard Kaplan] OBJ. The speaker does not inherit the derogation with a predicative NP in object position: (19.a) The UC Regents believe that Kaplan should not have been promoted for [being a PRED bastard], although derogation-inheritance can be induced by discourse-perspective changing elements such as basically and such : (19.b) The UC Regents believe that Kaplan should not have been promoted for being basically a bastard..c The UC Regents believe that Kaplan should not have been promoted for being such a bastard. The speaker does inherit the derogation of a predicative-like NP in subject position: (19.d) The UC Regents believe that [a bastard named Kaplan] should not have been promoted..e The UC Regents believe that [a bastard like Kaplan] should not have been promoted. But a bastard named Kaplan and a bastard like Kaplan are not truly predicative, but referential NPs, witness: (20.a) [A bastard named Kaplan] REF showed up at the Regents office this morning..b [A bastard like Kaplan] REF showed up at the Regents office this morning. The speaker does not inherit the derogation of a truly predicative NP in subject position: (19.f) The UC Regents believe that [a/any bastard named Kaplan] PRED should never be promoted.

250 Mercier The facts here too are robust. The speaker inherits the derogation with referential NPs in: (21.a) John wonders which REF nigger/redneck/floozie was it who was not promoted..b John thinks it was the REF tall nigger/redneck/floozie who was not promoted..c Mary believes that that REF floozie who bewitched her husband should never be promoted. The speaker does not inherit the derogation with predicative NPs: (22.a) John wonders whether it was a PRED nigger 1 /redneck/floozie who was not promoted..b Mary believes that it was a PRED floozie who bewitched her husband. 4 Referential-Predicative Presuppositional Asymmetries The projection problem, so-called by Kartunen and Peters, is the problem of how to compute the presuppositions of a complex sentence. K & P propose a cumulative model, where the presuppositions of each clause add up to constitute the presuppositions of the whole sentence. This model is defective, as shown briefly below. The standard presupposition in the sentence: (23) Keenan will come to the conference too. is that: 23-PRSP Someone other than Keenan will come to the conference. But if we embed (23) into a logically complex sentence, the presupposition of the whole sentence changes. The presupposition of the sentence: (24) If Keenan REF will come to the conference, Kaplan will come too. is that: 24-PRSP Kaplan is not Keenan. 2 Here, too is anaphoric on the previous clause. The presupposition differs depending on whether the anaphoric clause contains a referential or a predicative expression. The sentence: presupposes: (25) If the REF semanticist from UCLA comes to the conference, Kaplan will come too. 1 Some (David Kaplan, Jennifer Hornsby) think words like nigger are useless because they can never be used without derogation. Supporters of this view will of course find the speaker derogatory in (22.a) but this will not be a case of presupposition inheritance of the sort discussed here, but a direct case of using a derogatory word. I disagree with the view of essentially useless words, even as it refers to nigger, witness John Lennon s moving and non-derogatory: Woman is the nigger of the world. 2 This insight is due to Saul Kripke (Kripke Conference, Barcelona Dec 2005).

The Structural and the Semantic Subject-Object and Referential-Predicative Asymmetries 251 25-PRSP Kaplan is not the semanticist from UCLA. whereas the sentence: (26) If a PRED semanticist from UCLA comes to the conference, Kaplan will come too. does not carry that presupposition. The referential-predicative distinction accounts also for the following presuppositions or lack thereof. The sentence: (27) If Kaplan comes to the conference, the REF semanticist from UCLA will come too. presupposes: 27-PRSP Kaplan is not the semanticist from UCLA. whereas the sentence: (28) If Keenan comes to the conference, a PRED semanticist from UCLA will come too. does not carry that presupposition. Conclusion A semantic picture, attributable to Aristotle, Mill, and direct reference theorists, conceives of the logical structure of sentences in terms of reference the subject of the sentence functioning to denote an object and predication the predicate functioning to ascribe a property to that object. Frege brought attention to puzzling dimensions of that view, concluding that proper names themselves had not only a reference, but a predicative sense (while Russell did away with reference altogether). (Correcting Russell,) Donnellan showed that not just proper names but definite descriptions had both a referential use and a predicative (attributive) use. The understanding of logical structure in terms of semantic function has by and large been ejected from linguistic theorizing, replaced in GB by structural, syntactic, analyses (although categorial grammars retain some of this understanding through rules of functional application.) The foregoing facts suggest that the referential-predicative distinction is psychologically real. A closer look at how this distinction operates deeply in our linguistic judgments may shed some light on subtleties affecting belief attributions. All of which is respectfully and lovingly submitted in honour of a true teacher and friend. Acknowledgements The ideas discussed in this paper were first presented in May 2006 at a Workshop in Philosophy of Language at UQAM, in Sept 2007 at a colloquium at Queen s University, and in Sept 2008 at a colloquium at Carleton University. Thanks to participants for discussion. Special thanks for probing discussion and encouragement to Eros Corazza, Stephen Davis, Josh Mozersky, Nancy Salay, Arthur Sullivan and Richard Vallée.

252 Mercier References David Kaplan (1999), The meaning of ouch and oops. Ms. 2004 version. Los Angeles: University of California. Richard S. Kayne, Two notes on the NIC. In Adriana Belletti, Lucia Brandi & Luigi Rizzi (eds.), Theories of Markedness in Generative Grammar. Scuola Normale Superiore: Pisa, 1981. Edward Klima, Negation in English. In Jerry A. Fodor & Jerrold Katz (eds.), The Structure of Language: Readings in the Philosophy of Language. Prentice Hall: New Jersey, 1964, p. 285. Robert May, Logical Form: Its structure and derivation. MIT Press, 1985. Affiliation Adèle Mercier Department of Philosophy, Queen s University & LOGOS, University of Barcelona adele.mercier@gmail.com