What should I believe? Only what I have evidence for.

Similar documents
Does God exist? The argument from evil

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

What should I believe? What should I believe when people disagree with me?

Today we begin our discussion of the existence of God.

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Aquinas Cosmological argument in everyday language

Against Plantinga's A/C Model: Consequences of the Codependence of the De Jure and De Facto Questions. Rebeka Ferreira

Creation & necessity

Am I free? Free will vs. determinism

Proofs of Non-existence

Justified Inference. Ralph Wedgwood

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

Warrant, Proper Function, and the Great Pumpkin Objection

Sensus Divinitatis or Divine Hiddenness? Alvin Plantinga and J. L. Schellenberg on Knowledge of God

Does Reformed Epistemology Produce Rational Justification? The issue pertaining to religious justification is a thought-provoking endeavor that

Chapter III. Critical Responses: Foundationalism and. the Reformed Objection to Natural Theology

Copan, P. and P. Moser, eds., The Rationality of Theism, London: Routledge, 2003, pp.xi+292

Does God exist? The argument from miracles

INHISINTERESTINGCOMMENTS on my paper "Induction and Other Minds" 1

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Mackie vs Plantinga on the warrant of theistic belief without arguments

Does God exist? The argument from evil

David E. Alexander and Daniel Johnson, eds. Calvinism and the Problem of Evil.

Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs?

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

Well, how are we supposed to know that Jesus performed miracles on earth? Pretty clearly, the answer is: on the basis of testimony.

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

5 A Modal Version of the

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

The Zimboic Hunch By Damir Mladić

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

PHLA10 Reason and Truth Exercise 1

Ethical non-naturalism

Sounds of Love Series. Mysticism and Reason

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

Epistemology. PH654 Bethel Seminary Winter To be able to better understand and evaluate the sources, methods, and limits of human knowing,

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

Presuppositional Apologetics

DOUBT, CIRCULARITY AND THE MOOREAN RESPONSE TO THE SCEPTIC. Jessica Brown University of Bristol

Puzzles for Divine Omnipotence & Divine Freedom

the negative reason existential fallacy

The Skeptic and the Dogmatist

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

RESPECTING THE EVIDENCE. Richard Feldman University of Rochester

The free will defense

COUNTERING ATHEISM. How to Respond To Common Arguments Against the Existence of God. Atheist Argument #1

24.09 Minds and Machines Fall 11 HASS-D CI

First Principles. Principles of Reality. Undeniability.

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

By submitting this essay, I attest that it is my own work, completed in accordance with University regulations. Minh Alexander Nguyen

What we want to know is: why might one adopt this fatalistic attitude in response to reflection on the existence of truths about the future?

Joshua Blanchard University of Michigan

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Introductory Matters

Bootstrapping and The Bayesian: Why The Conservative is Not Threatened By Weisberg s Super-Reliable Gas Gauge

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

Summer Preparation Work

A problem in the one-fallacy theory

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Intuition, Self-evidence, and understanding 1. Philip Stratton-Lake

The St. Petersburg paradox & the two envelope paradox

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

This handout follows the handout on Hume on causation. You should read that handout first.

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, of philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

Free Won't [This Title Was Predetermined] and philosophy. For religious followers, free will is often considered a paradox. If God is all-seeing and

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

Critical Thinking. The Four Big Steps. First example. I. Recognizing Arguments. The Nature of Basics

Plantinga, Pluralism and Justified Religious Belief

Conditionals II: no truth conditions?

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

Have you ever sought God? Do you have any idea of God? Do you believe that God exist?

WHY SHOULD ANYONE BELIEVE ANYTHING AT ALL?

A guide to Anscombe s Intention, 1-31

What is an argument? PHIL 110. Is this an argument? Is this an argument? What about this? And what about this?

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

Hume. Hume the Empiricist. Judgments about the World. Impressions as Content of the Mind. The Problem of Induction & Knowledge of the External World

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Now consider a verb - like is pretty. Does this also stand for something?

Kelly James Clark and Raymond VanArragon (eds.), Evidence and Religious Belief, Oxford UP, 2011, 240pp., $65.00 (hbk), ISBN

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Trinity & contradiction

WEEK 4: APOLOGETICS AS PROOF

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014

Transcription:

What should I believe? Only what I have evidence for.

We closed last time by considering an objection to Moore s proof of an external world. The objection was that Moore does not know the premises of his proof, because he cannot prove them. This objection relies on the following principle: Proof/Knowledge If you cannot prove something, you do not know it. While intuitively appealing, this principle faces two apparently decisive objections.

Proof/Knowledge If you cannot prove something, you do not know it. The first is that the principle seems to imply that knowledge is impossible. Suppose (for reductio) that I know some claim P1. It follows from Proof/ Knowledge that I must be able to prove P1; so it follows from Proof/ Knowledge that there must be some other claims call them P2 and P3 which I know to be true and from which P1 follows. Let s focus on P2. If I know it, then from Proof/Knowledge it follows that I must be able to prove it. But then there must be some other claims call them P4 and P5 which I know to be true and from which P2 follows. Let s now focus on P4.. Actually, let s not. Can you see a pattern here?

Proof/Knowledge If you cannot prove something, you do not know it. Proof/Knowledge says that, for every claim I know to be true, I must know some other claims to be true which can be used to prove the first one. But then one of two things must be true. First option: this process never comes to an end. To know any claim, I must know infinitely many others. But I don t know infinitely many things. So, if we take this first option, I don t know anything.

Proof/Knowledge If you cannot prove something, you do not know it. But then one of two things must be true. Second option: the process goes in a circle, so that (for example) P is used to prove Q, and Q is used to prove R, and R is used to prove P. But it does not seem as though this sort of circular reasoning can yield knowledge. Imagine, for example, that one argued like this: God exists. There are miracles. Therefore, God exists. If God exists, then there are miracles. If there are miracles, then God exists.

Proof/Knowledge If you cannot prove something, you do not know it. This might remind you a bit of Aquinas first cause argument. Just like a chain of causes, every chain of reasoning must either be infinite, circular, or have some unproven premise. But the first two can t explain our knowledge, and, if Proof/Knowledge is true, the last one can t either. So, if Proof/Knowledge is true, then knowledge is impossible.

Proof/Knowledge If you cannot prove something, you do not know it. Here is the second problem with using Proof/Knowledge as an argument against Moore (or anyone else). It seems that one can legitimately use this principle in an argument only if one knows it to be true. And if one knows Proof/Knowledge to be true, then (by Proof/Knowledge itself) one must have a proof of it. But what could that be?

So it seems as though we can know things that we cannot prove, and (for parallel reasons) that we should sometimes believe things that we cannot prove. But, you might think, there must be some rules which govern responsible belief formation; one can t reasonably just believe anything. This point can be brought out by examining one of the world s fastest growing religions: Pastafarianism.

This point can be brought out by examining one of the world s fastest growing religions: Pastafarianism. < A ChrisFSMas tree

As you might guess, many Pastafarians take a somewhat less than serious attitude toward the tenets of Pastafarianism (though some apparently do not). But suppose that someone were a serious Pastafarian. We would, I take it, be inclined to think that there is something irrational about his beliefs. And this might be so even if we could not come up with any decisive argument against Pastafarianism. In that case, it seems, we would want to provide some sort of standard for rational belief, and claim that Pastafarianism does not meet that standard.

In that case, it seems, we would want to provide some sort of standard for rational belief, and claim that Pastafarianism does not meet that standard. Proof/Knowledge was a failed attempt to provide such a standard; can we do better? To do so, it seems, we have to allow that it is sometimes rational to believe claims which one cannot prove. But which ones? A historically influential answer singles out two classes: claims which are self-evident, or obvious; and claims which your sense experiences tell you to be true. This is the view which, in the reading for today, Alvin Plantinga calls foundationalism.

This is the view which, in the reading for today, Alvin Plantinga calls foundationalism. Foundationalism You do not know a claim unless (i) you have a good argument for it, or (ii) your sense experience tells you that it is true, or (iii) it is self-evident. Foundationalism looks to be an improvement on Proof/Knowledge. Like that principle, it can also be cast as a claim about what it is rational to believe, or what you ought to believe, rather than as a claim about knowledge.

Foundationalism You do not know a claim unless (i) you have a good argument for it, or (ii) your sense experience tells you that it is true, or (iii) it is self-evident. Foundationalism also seems to explain what is wrong with (serious) Pastafarianism. Given that there seem to be no good arguments in favor of the existence of the Flying Spaghetti Monster, we have no sensory evidence of its existence, and its existence is not selfevident, we should not be Pastafarians. Could Foundationalism also be used as an argument against more standard forms of religious belief? It can. (This is what Plantinga calls the evidentialist objection to religious belief.)

Foundationalism You do not know a claim unless (i) you have a good argument for it, or (ii) your sense experience tells you that it is true, or (iii) it is self-evident. It can. (This is what Plantinga calls the evidentialist objection to religious belief.) 1. Foundationalism is true. 2. We have no good argument for God s existence. 3. We have no sense experience of God. 4. God s existence is not self-evident. C. We do not know that God exists. (1,2,3,4) Note that, if we recast Foundationalism as a claim about what it is reasonable or rational to believe, we could give a parallel argument for the conclusion that it is not reasonable or rational to believe in God.

Foundationalism You do not know a claim unless (i) you have a good argument for it, or (ii) your sense experience tells you that it is true, or (iii) it is self-evident. 1. Foundationalism is true. 2. We have no good argument for God s existence. 3. We have no sense experience of God. 4. God s existence is not self-evident. C. We do not know that God exists. (1,2,3,4) One might of course reject premise (2) of the evidentialist objection. But Plantinga gives us an argument that, even if (2) turns out to be true, premise (1) and hence Foundationalism should be rejected.

Foundationalism You do not know a claim unless (i) you have a good argument for it, or (ii) your sense experience tells you that it is true, or (iii) it is self-evident. For we can ask: do we know that Foundationalism is true? An argument by dilemma can be given that we cannot. Is foundationalism true? Yes No Then, again, we cannot know it. Then we cannot know it.

Foundationalism You do not know a claim unless (i) you have a good argument for it, or (ii) your sense experience tells you that it is true, or (iii) it is self-evident. So we do not know Foundationalism to be true. 1. Foundationalism is true. 2. We have no good argument for God s existence. 3. We have no sense experience of God. 4. God s existence is not self-evident. C. We do not know that God exists. (1,2,3,4) But that is a premise of the Evidentialist argument. So we do not know premise (1) of that argument to be true. So the argument can be rejected.

Foundationalism You do not know a claim unless (i) you have a good argument for it, or (ii) your sense experience tells you that it is true, or (iii) it is self-evident. But even if this is an effective rebuttal to the evidentialist objection, it does not tell us whether Foundationalism is true or false. Plantinga s second argument is an attempt to show directly that Foundationalism is false. This is based on the possibility that everyone besides you is a zombie.

This is based on the possibility that everyone besides you is a zombie. A zombie (in the philosophical sense) is not a bloodthirsty undead monster. A zombie is a creature who is externally indistinguishable from a human being, but lacks consciousness. We can ask: how do you know that everyone besides you is not a zombie, in this sense? This question is sometimes called the problem of other minds. Your senses don t tell you one way or another whether the person to whom you are talking is conscious. And it is not selfevident that the person is conscious. So, if Foundationalism is true, it looks like we can know that other people are conscious only if we can give a good argument for the claim that they are conscious. Can we?

So, if Foundationalism is true, it looks like we can know that other people are conscious only if we can give a good argument for the claim that they are conscious. Can we? Here is an argument you might give: I know that I am conscious, and I observe that in my case there is a correlation between my conscious states and my outward bodily movements. But I also notice that the outward movements of the bodies of other people are similar to my own. So it is reasonable for me to believe that, just as there is a correlation between outward movements and conscious states in my case, so there is such a correlation in the case of other people. Hence it is reasonable for me to believe that they too are conscious. This argument which is sometimes called the argument from analogy sounds plausible. But it faces a serious problem.

An inductive argument is an argument which generalizes from cases. Here is an example of an inductive argument: 1. The sun came up today. 2. The sun came up yesterday. 3. The sun came up the day before yesterday. - C. The sun will come up tomorrow. Is this argument valid? In general, inductive arguments are not valid but it does seem as though they can give us good reason to believe certain claims which go beyond our sense experience.

The argument from analogy for the conclusion that other people are conscious seems to be an inductive argument: it generalizes from my own case to the case of other people. But it is a very weird argument of this sort: it is induction from a single case. Is this sort of inductive reasoning a good way to reason? Compare the following: Yesterday, I saw my first sushi roll. It had salmon in it. So, I think that all sushi rolls must have salmon in them. This is pretty clearly a bad piece of reasoning. But then the question is: why isn t the inductive argument for the conclusion that other people are conscious just as bad?

But it is hard to see how we could argue that other people are conscious, other than on broadly inductive grounds. Foundationalism You do not know a claim unless (i) you have a good argument for it, or (ii) your sense experience tells you that it is true, or (iii) it is self-evident. So it seems as though, if Foundationalism is true, we cannot know whether other people are conscious. But that, Plantinga thinks, is very implausible. Hence, he thinks, Foundationalism is false.

This is good news for someone who wants to oppose the evidentialist objection to religious belief. But it leaves us without the thing we wanted: some explanation of why Pastafarianism is irrational. We have two different claims for which we lack good arguments: the claim that other people are conscious, and the claim that there is a Flying Spaghetti Monster. And yet it is reasonable to believe the first, but not the second. What explains the difference? (And which one, the traditional religious believer might ask, is the belief that God exists more like?) Let s say, borrowing a term from Plantinga, that a belief which is not based on argument is a basic belief. We know that some basic beliefs are rational (like belief in other minds) and that other basic beliefs are irrational (Pastafarianism). Let s call a rational basic belief properly basic. Then our question is what makes some beliefs but not others properly basic.

This is a difficult question to answer. Here is what Plantinga says about it: [one] can properly hold that belief in the Great Pumpkin is not properly basic, even though he holds that belief in God is properly basic and even if he has no full fledged criterion of proper basicality. Of course he is committed to supposing that there is a relevant difference between belief in God and belief in the Great Pumpkin, if he holds that the former but not the latter is properly basic. But this should prove no great embarrassment; there are plenty of candidates. [he] may concur with Calvin in holding that God has implanted in us a natural tendency to see his hand in the world around us; the same cannot be said for the Great Pumpkin, there being no Great Pumpkin and no natural tendency to accept beliefs about the Great Pumpkin. Here Plantinga seems to be suggesting that a belief is properly basic if we have a natural tendency to believe it. This seems to put belief in God though perhaps not specifically Christian belief on the side of other minds rather than on the side of Pastafarianism, which is what Plantinga wants.

But of course this is as Plantinga recognizes too simple. After all, we seem to have a natural tendency to believe that the sun moves around the earth but we can hardly rationally take that on board as a basic belief. The reason why is obvious: we have a great deal of evidence that this belief is false. Let s call this evidence a defeater for the belief that the sun moves around the earth. Then we might reformulate Plantinga s suggestion as follows: a belief is properly basic if we have a natural tendency to believe it, and it has no defeaters (or, if it does, that those defeaters are outweighed by reasons counting in favor of the belief).

Our question, then, is whether belief in God has defeaters. And one might think that it does: one might think, for example, that the amount and kind of evil we find in the world is a defeater for the belief that there is an omnipotent and all-good being. In this case, we might think that belief in God is properly basic for children and adults who have never thought the problem of evil through, but not properly basic for intellectually sophisticated adults like the students in this class. We ve now found a candidate criterion to distinguish belief in God though, again, perhaps not Christian belief from belief in the flying spaghetti monster. The claim is that we have a natural tendency to believe in God and no defeaters for this belief (or defeaters that are outweighed). One might reject the idea that there are no defeaters for belief in God but then one is arguing that religious belief is irrational, not because of a lack of evidence, but rather because there are arguments against it. But we already knew that one could challenge the rationality of religious belief on that basis. That s consistent with claiming that there is no special problem for religious belief which follows from a lack of evidence for God s existence.

In order for us to get anywhere, it has to sometimes be rational to believe a claim without argument. But, as the FSM shows, this is not always rational. The question of when it is rational to believe without argument when it is rational to take a belief as basic is an important and difficult one.