World Hunger and Poverty

Similar documents
24.03: Good Food 2/15/17

The Discount Rate of Well-Being

Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World

Peter Singer, Famine, Affluence, and Morality

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

CRITIQUE OF PETER SINGER S NOTION OF MARGINAL UTILITY

ETHICS AND GLOBAL POVERTY

Judging Subsistence Rights by their Duties Eric Boot

How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good)

Are Humans Always Selfish? OR Is Altruism Possible?

The Non-Identity Problem from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984)

Introduction. In light of these facts, we will ask, is killing animals for human benefit morally permissible?

Foundations of Bioethics

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

What must I do? Give most of your possessions to the poor

RETHINKING THE GOOD. Moral Ideals and the Nature of Practical Reasoning. Larry S. Temkin

Naturalist Cognitivism: The Open Question Argument; Subjectivism

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

Philosophical Ethics. Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics)

Professional Ethics. Today s Topic Ethical Egoism PHIL Picture: Ursa Major. Illustration: Cover art from Ayn Rand s The Fountainhead

Ethics is subjective.

"Book Review: FRANKFURT, Harry G. On Inequality. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2015, 102 pp., $14.95 (hbk), ISBN

Is It Morally Wrong to Have Children?

Philosophy 2: Introduction to Ethics. Instructor: Erick Ramirez. Office location: Kenna 207

Defending Limits on the Sacrifices We Ought To Make For Others

Princeton University Press and Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy &Public Affairs.

SATISFICING CONSEQUENTIALISM AND SCALAR CONSEQUENTIALISM

1. PETER SINGER. Famine, Affluence, and Morality First published, in Philosophy and Public Affairs 1:3 (.spring 1972):

Basics of Ethics CS 215 Denbigh Starkey

Dave Ramsey Budget Percentages. ~ Finances ~ NOTES

Moral Reasons, Overridingness, and Supererogation*

CHAPTER 5. CULTURAL RELATIVISM.

Ethics and Poverty. By Peter Singer

Phil 114, February 29, 2012 Sir Robert Filmer, Observations Concerning the Originall of Government

Quinn s DDE. 1. Quinn s DDE: Warren Quinn begins by running through the familiar pairs of cases:

WHEN is a moral theory self-defeating? I suggest the following.

Q2) The test of an ethical argument lies in the fact that others need to be able to follow it and come to the same result.

Rawlsian Values. Jimmy Rising

Quinn s Doctrine of Doing and Allowing (DDA)

The Moral Relevance of the Past (Hanna)

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

THE EIGHT KEY QUESTIONS HANDBOOK

The ethical principles of effective altruism

Criticizing Arguments

If Natural Entities Have Intrinsic Value, Should We Then Abstain from Helping Animals Who Are Victims of Natural Processes? 1

CMSI Handout 12 Marcello Antosh

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

Against Individual Responsibility (Sinnott-Armstrong)

THREE IT IS AN ACT OF LOVE TO: Feed the Hungry OPENING PRAYER

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

A Social Practice View of Natural Rights. Word Count: 2998

Suicide. 1. Rationality vs. Morality: Kagan begins by distinguishing between two questions:

Poverty and Hope Appeal 2017 Sunday School Resources

Review of Jean Kazez's Animalkind: What We Owe to Animals

Peter Singer, Practical Ethics Discussion Questions/Study Guide Prepared by Prof. Bill Felice

Ethical Theory. Ethical Theory. Consequentialism in practice. How do we get the numbers? Must Choose Best Possible Act

Controversial Ethics as a Foundation for Controversial Political Theory

Course Syllabus Political Philosophy PHIL 462, Spring, 2017

On the Separateness of Individuals, Compensation, and Aggregation Within Lives

in Social Science Encyclopedia (Routledge, forthcoming, 2006). Consequentialism (Blackwell Publishers, forthcoming, 2006)

Quiz 1. Criticisms of consequentialism and Kant. Consequentialism and Nonconsequentialism. Consequentialism in practice. Must Choose Best Possible Act

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

DEONTOLOGICAL ETHICS

Equality of Capacity AMARTYA SEN

UTILITARIANISM AND CONSEQUENTIALISM: THE BASICS

REQUIRED DOCUMENT FROM HIRING UNIT

ACSJC Discussion Guide: Encyclical of Pope Benedict XVI Caritas in Veritate

Against Collective Consequentialism

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

Romans. Small t truths and Big T Truths: Biblical Thinking in a Fallen World Part 2 Chapter 12:1-2

INTRODUCTORY HANDOUT PHILOSOPHY 13 FALL, 2004 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY---ETHICS Professor: Richard Arneson. TAs: Eric Campbell and Adam Streed.

During the Welsh revival, one of the hymns that was sung at every service was "Count Your Blessings." We are familiar with the great hymn:

Sidgwick on Practical Reason

think that people are generally moral relativists. I will argue that people really do believe in moral

Summary of Locke's Second Treatise [T2]

Yom Kippur Sermon: Tikkun Olam

Rawls versus utilitarianism: the subset objection

Philosophy Courses Fall 2016

Justice and Ethics. Jimmy Rising. October 3, 2002

Our responsibility towards future generations. Lars Löfquist, Theology Department

Reality, Resistance & Respect

There are various different versions of Newcomb s problem; but an intuitive presentation of the problem is very easy to give.

Yet that is in tension with our sense of reality, isn t it? Our sense of reality is often echoed in the words of John D. Rockefeller, the American

Making Decisions on Behalf of Others: Who or What Do I Select as a Guide? A Dilemma: - My boss. - The shareholders. - Other stakeholders

Challenges to Traditional Morality

The Bible on Poverty

Critical Reasoning and Moral theory day 3

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Dying Young as Tragedy: An Ally of, or an Alternative to, Fair Innings?

SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY from the BEGINNING 1/05

Universities of Leeds, Sheffield and York

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

Animal Disenhancement

Ethics Handout 19 Bernard Williams, The Idea of Equality. A normative conclusion: Therefore we should treat men as equals.

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

Transcription:

World Hunger and Poverty Some Facts & Figures Many people live in dire poverty; some people live in (comparatively) great affluence. About 767 million people (10.7% of the world population) live in extreme poverty, < US$1.90 /day About 2.1 billion people (~30%) live on < US $3.10 /day (World Bank, 2016) The richest 0.6% of world population hold 39.3% of the world s wealth; the bottom 95% hold 28.4% (OECD, 2012) 1

2

There are also, of course, inequalities of wealth (and inequalities of welfare) within political communities. Yet many/most modern states accept that governments have least some responsibility, often grounded in distributive justice, to minimize, or at least manage, intrastate inequalities. Basic Questions At the global level, a basic moral question: Are economically advantaged people morally obligated to participate in some redistributive scheme so that some of their wealth goes to less economically advantaged people? If so, what best explains this obligation? One way to think of this would be in terms of a duty of beneficence (i.e., to help those in need) a duty that features in several different moral theories 3

Beneficence Assuming we have a duty of beneficence, we can ask: Scope I.e. to whom is the duty owed? People existing the present only or future generations as well? Content I.e., how strong is the duty? In effect, how much do we owe to others (expressed, say, as a percentage of wealth or comparison to our own needs and wants) Strength Is a (global) duty of beneficence an overriding duty, a less-stringent duty, or is it possibly just superogatory? Hardin: Lifeboat Ethics Garrett Hardin offers a broadly C argument: The scope, content, and strength of any putative duty of aid must be assessed in terms it long-range consequences. Hardin: The likely long run consequences of a policy of aid will be worse for everyone (currently wealthy and currently poor alike). So, we have no duty of aid. In fact, we have a C duty not to provide aid. 4

The Lifeboat Metaphor Think of rich states as lifeboats full of rich people and poor states are (much more crowded) lifeboats full of poor people. The central problem of lifeboat ethics : What should the passengers on a rich lifeboat do? There are three basic possibilities 1. Unlimited Sharing (i.e., let on to the lifeboat everyone who wants to, perhaps motivated by Christian or Marxian ideals) Hardin: This will lead to immediate catastrophe (there won t be enough to go around, the lifeboat will founder) 2. Selective Sharing (i.e., admit some people on to the lifeboat, e.g., on the basis of first come, first served or according to need or according to talent). Analogue: Aid programs such as a World Food Bank Hardin: This will make things worse in the long through the Tragedy of the Commons and the Ratchet Effect 3. No Sharing: Hardin s recommendation 5

The Tragedy of the Commons (TOC) When people make use of a commons (i.e., unowned) resource, it is instrumentally rational for them to maximally exploit it right up to the point were is it ruined. E.g., the classical case of shepherds on a commons pasture vs. private holdings If everyone restrained themselves from overexploitation, the commons might be preserved. But is not rational to restrain oneself if there is no payoff for doing so (or no price for not doing so). The Ratchet Effect Uncontrolled (e.g., unregulated) human reproduction creates a TOC. If aid is supplied (e.g., through a World Food Bank), impoverished people will generally accept it (it would be irrational not to). Aid will stave off present emergencies But, unless reproduction is controlled, it will also lead to higher populations of poor people such that future emergencies will be worse this iterates indefinitely into the future until global catastrophe. 6

Singer: The Life You Can Save Peter Singer argues, also on C grounds, for a conclusion that is directly opposed to Hardin s. On C grounds, we have a general obligation to reduce suffering. Many of us who are comparatively well-off could sacrifice at least some of our wealth without making ourselves appreciably worse off. Yet if we all made even relatively small sacrifices, this could greatly improve the conditions of others Saving a Life Singer's famous thought experiment: On your way to work you pass a small pond and see a young child who seems likely to drown if you don't wade in and pull him out. If you pull him out, though, you will ruin your new shoes, dirty your suit, and be late for work. What should you do? Common Intuition: You should try to save the child. If you don t, you will have done something morally wrong 7

Implication: The situation with global poverty is analogous. We morally ought to donate relatively small amounts of money to save those who are dying from starvation, easily treatable diseases, etc. If intuition is doing the work in the case of the drowning child, this could instead be generalized and formalized 1. Suffering and death from lack of food, shelter, and medical care are bad. 2. If it is in your power to prevent something bad from happening, without sacrificing anything nearly as important, it is morally wrong not to do so. 3. By donating to aid agencies, you can prevent suffering and death from lack of food, shelter, and medical care, without sacrificing anything nearly as important. 4. If you do not donate to aid agencies, you are doing something morally wrong. 8

Some Possible Objections We're all entitled to our beliefs. Yes, but this doesn t entail moral relativism. If we see someone torturing an animal, we don t simply say oh well, you are entitled to follow your beliefs. We have a right to our hard-earned money. Yes, but just because you have a right doesn t mean that you can t also have moral duty constraining your exercise of that right. Libertarianism (Narveson): We have a duty to compensate those we have wronged, but we have doing nothing wrong to world s poor. Haven t we? Cf. supporting corrupt regimes, exploitative TNCs, climate change.etc. Aid breeds dependency Yes, it can, so we should give aid directly to the poor only in emergencies. In general, we should give aid to agencies/institutions that will promote long-term economic development 9

Charity begins at home. I.e., we have special relationships with our families and communities and we should be morally permitted to favour them. This is natural. And, of course, if your family or friends need aid to anything like the degree that the world s poor do, it would be permissible to give to them first. For most of us in the developed, however, that is simply not realistic. Arthur: Hunger and Obligation John Arthur (Binghampton) argues (on what turn out to be basically SCT grounds) that Singer s argument is, in effect, incomplete. Singer s argument is founded on commitment to equal moral consideration of all. (Cf. impartiality) But, in addition to equality, morality involves commitments to entitlement, including rights and considerations of desert. 10

Greatest Moral Evil Rule (GMER) Arthur: Singer s argument depends on this principle If it is in our power to prevent something bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance, we ought, morally, to do it (663) It follows immediately from the GMER that we are morally entitled to keep what we have only if there is no way for us prevent greater evil by giving it away. I.e., taken literally, the GMER is very demanding if we spend money on toys for ourselves while others starve, we are, by the lights of GMER, treating others as if their happiness/suffering matter less than ours. I.e., we give special consideration to ourselves, denying the moral equality of others. But, again, a commitment to equality is only a part of morality ( our moral code ). It can be countered by considerations of right and desert 11

E.g., we could conceivably make someone much better off by letting him use our body (donating a kidney or an eyeball): One eyeball/kidney isn t that much worse than two, but much better than none, so the GMER, on its own, would mandate donation. But: Rights. You have a ( natural, negative) right to your body, so others have no entitlement to use it. Donating an eyeball is not morally obligatory, it is superogatory. You may have a ( not natural ) positive right to receive aid from me if I promised or we entered into a contract. But apart from some such agreement, no such right exists. Also: Desert. X is a highly industrious farmer who has worked hard to produce a crop surplus; Y is a lazy farmer who spends his time fishing. Does X morally owe some or all of his surplus to Y, simply because Y will suffer he doesn t give it to him? Arthur: This doesn t mean that rights and entitlements simply trump equality considerations. We may even consider revising our moral code to give priority to equality. But we need some account or other of how to balance off these considerations. 12

Arthur: Yet if we are considering reform, we should bear in mind the purposes of morality (per SCT): To promote our welfare and that of others. We will agree to support a moral code only if it is practical i.e., if actually delivers its promised benefits, if the demands that it makes on ourselves and others aren t excessive in relation to those benefits only if it is rational for (nearly) everyone to support. Giving priority to equality would undermine these conditions for support. Upshot: Our code expects us to help people in need as well as to respect negative and positive rights. But we are also entitled to invoke our own rights as a justification for not giving to distant strangers when the cost to us is substantial... (670) 13