Outline of the Apology 1. I. Prologue: knowledge is very valuable, though sometimes esteemed too highly. F, 319

Similar documents
COPLESTON: Quite so, but I regard the metaphysical argument as probative, but there we differ.

CRITICAL QUESTIONS FOR CHRISTIANS

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

Notes on Bertrand Russell s The Problems of Philosophy (Hackett 1990 reprint of the 1912 Oxford edition, Chapters XII, XIII, XIV, )

Today s Lecture. René Descartes W.K. Clifford Preliminary comments on Locke

Philosophy 168. Descartes Fall, 2011 G. J. Mattey. Introductory Remarks

By J. Alexander Rutherford. Part one sets the roles, relationships, and begins the discussion with a consideration

Today s Lecture. Preliminary comments on the Problem of Evil J.L Mackie

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Skepticism and Toleration in Early Modern Philosophy. Instructor: Todd Ryan Office: McCook 322 Office Phone:

Michael Zank, STM PhD Associate Professor of Religion 147 Bay State Road, Room 407

Templates for Writing about Ideas and Research

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

CARTESIANISM, NEO-REIDIANISM, AND THE A PRIORI: REPLY TO PUST

The Metaphysics of Perfect Beings, by Michael Almeida. New York: Routledge, Pp $105.00

Relativism and the Nature of Truth

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Phenomenology, Empiricism, and Science

SCHEDULE OF SEMINAR READINGS First Semester, DATE FRESHMAN SOPHOMORE JUNIOR SENIOR. Cervantes: Don Quixote, Part I. Cervantes: Don Quixote

Pierre Bayle Life and Main Writings.

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 5d God

Topics and Posterior Analytics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

DOES ETHICS NEED GOD?

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

Moral Argument. Theistic Arguments: The Craig Program, 4. Edwin Chong. God makes sense of the objective moral values in the world.

What Does Academic Skepticism Presuppose? Arcesilaus, Carneades, and the Argument with Stoic Epistemology

Answering Common Objections To Christianity John Kelsey

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

Philosophy of Religion: Hume on Natural Religion. Phil 255 Dr Christian Coseru Wednesday, April 12

Higher-Order Epistemic Attitudes and Intellectual Humility. Allan Hazlett. Forthcoming in Episteme

Critique of Cosmological Argument

b. Use of logic in reasoning; c. Development of cross examination skills; d. Emphasis on reasoning and understanding; e. Moderate rate of delivery;

Sophie s World. Chapter 4 The Natural Philosophers

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

Critical Thinking: Present, Past and Future 5 April, 2015

Chapter Summaries: Three Types of Religious Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Introduction. 1 Bertrand Russell, The Problems of Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, n.d.), 7.

Delton Lewis Scudder: Tennant's Philosophical Theology. New Haven: Yale University Press xiv, 278. $3.00.

CONTENTS. INTRODUCTORY Chapter I ETHICAL NEUTRALITY AND PRAGMATISM

Epistemology. Diogenes: Master Cynic. The Ancient Greek Skeptics 4/6/2011. But is it really possible to claim knowledge of anything?

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

THE GOD OF QUARKS & CROSS. bridging the cultural divide between people of faith and people of science

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

PHIL-176: DEATH. Lecture 15 - The Nature of Death (cont.); Believing You Will Die [March 6, 2007]

INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

Arrogant? ISBN:

Humanities 3 V. The Scientific Revolution

Philosophical Review.

2. Public Forum Debate seeks to encourage the development of the following skills in the debaters: d. Reasonable demeanor and style of presentation

Syllabus PHIL 1000 Philosophy of Human Nature Summer 2017, Tues/Wed/Thurs 9:00-12:00pm Location: TBD

Richard van de Lagemaat Relative Values A Dialogue

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

Table of x III. Modern Modal Ontological Arguments Norman Malcolm s argument Charles Hartshorne s argument A fly in the ointment? 86

Is There Immediate Justification?

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

richard swinburne Oriel College, Oxford University, Oxford, OX1 4EW

2014 THE BIBLIOGRAPHIA ISSN: Online First: 21 October 2014

Module 1-4: Spirituality and Rationality

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

Do you have a self? Who (what) are you? PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2014


Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument

The Chalcedonian Formula Without Confusion and Without Separation in the Light of the Documents Issued by the International Theological Commission

History of Political Thought I: Justice, Virtue, and the Soul

Either God wants to abolish evil and cannot, or he can but does not want to, or he cannot and does not want to, or lastly he can and wants to.

Augustine, On Free Choice of the Will,

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Ethos, Logos, Pathos: Three Ways to Persuade

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Evidential arguments from evil

Is Faith Worth Believing?

Review. Philosophy; Page 1 of The Royal Institute of Philosophy,

Common Sense: A Contemporary Defense By Noah Lemos Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. xvi

Relative and Absolute Truth in Greek Philosophy

Why There s Nothing You Can Say to Change My Mind: The Principle of Non-Contradiction in Aristotle s Metaphysics

Evidence and Transcendence

IS IT IMMORAL TO BELIEVE IN GOD?

A Response from the ACELC to CCM Opinion dated September 3-4, 2011

ARE YOU READY? Lecture 2 Loss of Truth

Syllabus. Primary Sources, 2 edition. Hackett, Various supplementary handouts, available in class and on the course website.

Topics in Philosophy of Mind Other Minds Spring 2003/handout 2

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

Realism and anti-realism. University of London Philosophy B.A. Intercollegiate Lectures Logic and Metaphysics José Zalabardo Autumn 2009

Introduction to Philosophy

1. What arguments does Socrates use in Plato s Republic to show that justice is to be preferred over injustice?

Introduction to Philosophy

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

[MJTM 14 ( )] BOOK REVIEW

THE RISE OF MODERNITY: DESCARTES, KANT, HEGEL, + MARX

I Don't Believe in God I Believe in Science

Transcription:

Outline of the Apology 1 I. Prologue: knowledge is very valuable, though sometimes esteemed too highly. F, 319 II. Pierre Bunel s recommendation of Sebond to Montaigne s father. His natural theology as an antidote to Lutheranism and the atheism to which it leads. Montaigne s filial duties and mixed feelings about Sebond. F, 319-21 Note: Lutheranism is supposed to be dangerous because it destroys respect for authority, which was the only basis people had for their beliefs. Undermining authority leads to skepticism, which in turn leads to atheism. But Montaigne's 'defense' of Sebond will advocate radical skepticism. How can this help? III. First objection to Sebond: Christians are wrong if they try to support their faith by human reason. F, 321. Note: 2 Sebond's Natural Theology was apparently written c. 1430 and circulated widely in ms. before it was finally printed. It had already been translated into French in 1551. It was placed on the Index of Prohibited Books in 1558-59, apparently because its Prologue was thought to make stronger claims for human reason than the Church considered orthodox. Specifically, Sebond claimed that This science teaches everyone really to know, without difficulty or toil, every truth necessary to Man concerning both Man and God; and all things which are necessary to Man for his salvation, for making him perfect and for bringing him through to life eternal. And by this science a man learns, without difficulty and in reality, whatever is contained in Holy Scripture. Montaigne's translation of this passage (publ. 1569) moderated Sebond's claims: This science teaches every one to see clearly, without difficulty or toil, truth insofar as it is possible for natural reason, concerning knowledge of God and of himself, and of what he has need of for his falvation and to reach life eternal; it affords him an access to understanding what is prescribed and commanded in Holy Scripture. The emphasis here is due to M. A. Screech. IV. Reply: Initial statement of fideism. It s true that human reason is incapable of enlightening us about religious truth, but we should use whatever gifts God has given us, always remembering that faith depends, not on us, but on divine grace. F, 321. V. Digression. Critique of Christian piety. Observation of Christian behavior suggests that we do not in fact owe our Christian belief to divine grace. F, 322-326. VI. Restatement of fideism. The value of Sebond. By themselves the arguments are barren. But when faith illumines them it makes them solid. F, 326-327. 1 I ve constructed this outline to help students (and myself) find their way through the apparently trackless maze of Montaigne s Apology for Raymond Sebond. It was inspired by, and to some extent follows, previous outlines by Donald Frame (in his translation) and David Lewis Schaefer (in his The Political Philosophy of Montaigne). F, 319 refers to the pagination in Frame s translation. 2 I owe the information in this note to M.A. Screech's introduction to his translation of the Apology, Penguin, 1993, pp. xi-xiv.

Note: This is, I think, the only passage in Montaigne's Apology which tells us anything about what Sebond's arguments actually were. VII. Second objection to Sebond: his arguments are weak. F, 327. Note: There's an important but puzzling statement here about the tendency people have to interpret other men's works in accordance with their own prejudices. In particular, readers predisposed to atheism are inclined to misread works innocent of atheism as atheistic. It's not clear what the argumentative point of this statement is. Perhaps Montaigne is replying to critics of Sebond who charged him with atheism, on the ground that he had encouraged atheism by offering bad arguments for theistic belief. Sebond did make very strong claims for his arguments, and we can imagine a reader responding: these arguments are very poor; if they're the best theists can do, then theism must be, at best, unsupported by reason, and at worst, simply false. Note that Montaigne has previously said (F, 320) that he doesn't think it's possible for anyone to give better arguments for theism than Sebond has given. On this reading, Montaigne would be defending Sebond by claiming that those critics who see his arguments as leading to atheisn must have a predisposition in favor of atheism. Perhaps, though, Montaigne is making a preemptive strike against people who might criticize his own work as leading to atheism. We've already seen one possible ground for that criticism (above, Note to II). On this reading Montaigne would be defending himself, not Sebond. (These alternative readings do not seem mutually exclusive.) VIII. Reply: we must crush human arrogance and pride; unaided reason is worthless; Sebond s arguments may be weak, but they are no worse than anyone else s. F, 327-418 A. In praise of animals. Their abilities, both intellectual and moral, often equal or surpass ours. F, 330-358. Note: This portion of the Apology is great fun to read, and interesting in its own right, as an antidote to Pico's "Oration," but doesn't seem to me to contribute substantially to Montaigne's overall argument. So I may cut it from the final version of the work. I would welcome advice about that. B. In praise of folly (1). Man s knowledge cannot make him happy. The ignorant often have more satisfactory lives than the learned. F, 358-367 Note: In titling this and the following section I am deliberately inviting a comparison with Erasmus. These sections seem very much in his spirit. C. In praise of folly (2). Man s knowledge cannot make him good. Curiosity is the natural and original evil in man." F, 367-370 Note particularly the statement: "To Christians it is an occasion for belief to encounter something incredible. It is the more according to reason as it is contrary to human reason. (F, 368) This suggests a very strong form of fideism: that faith requires belief, not merely in propositions which reason cannot prove or even make probable, but in propositions which reason can disprove or at least make highly improbable. I believe this very strong form of fideism let's call it radical fideism is now regarded as heretical in the Catholic Church.

Whether or not that's true, you can see why radical fideism might be thought to encourage atheism. If someone holds that Christian belief requires you to go, not merely beyond reason, but against reason, he is apparently asking for a sacrifice of rationality which some people might not be willing to make. Montaigne's pyrrhonism, which is still to be defined, might make radical fideism unnecessary. If the principle of equipollence holds, then reason can't make Christian doctrine even improbable. D. Man has no knowledge and cannot attain knowledge. F, 370-418. Note: this very long section of the work seems to reverse the assumptions which have governed the argument of sections VIII.B and VIII.C, which evidently took knowledge to be possible and merely denied the claim made in the Prologue ( I), that knowledge is valuable, even if overrated. 1. Introduction to pyrrhonism, distinguishing it from dogmatism and academic skepticism. F, 371-375 Note the special meaning attached to the term dogmatism. Anyone who makes any claim to certain knowledge in the sciences counts as a dogmatist. This includes three of the major ancient schools of philosophy: the Peripatetics, the Epicureans, and the Stoics. Presumably, though Montaigne does not say this explicitly, it would also include the scholastics, to the extent that they follow Aristotle. Montaigne does not mention Plato here, but later statements (e.g., at F, 377) suggest that he would not count Plato as a dogmatist. Pyrrhonism is defined by its goal of not making any judgments whatever, apparently because the pyrrhonists find that for any question they consider, the arguments in favor of one answer to the question seem to be as strong as, but no stronger than, the arguments for rejecting that answer. Cf. the quote from Cicero on F, 373. This is what is known as the principle of equipollence. If pyrrhonism is not to be self-refuting, it must treat the principle of equipollence not as a judgment of how things are, but as a statement about how things seem to the pyrrhonist. The pyrrhonist goal of suspending judgment does not require them to refrain from saying how things seem. 2. Vanity of the dogmatists. F, 375-80. Note the reference to Aristotle as "the prince of dogmatists." We get a nice statement here of one of Montaigne's central arguments for skepticism: The widest field for reprehensions of philosophers among one another is derived from the contradictions and differences in which each one of them finds himself entangled, either on purpose, to show the vacillation of the human mind around all matters, or unwittingly, forced by the mobility and incomprehensibility of all matters. (F, 378)

One question we will need to discuss is whether the fact of persistent disagreement among those who claim to have certain knowledge indicates that no party to the dispute has certain knowledge. 3. Vanity and variety of philosophical opinions a. Concerning God and immortality ( F, 380-400) Of particular interest in this section are several passages suggesting that a proper appreciation of God s infinite power would diminish our confidence in various truths philosophers have usually regarded as necessary and a priori certain. These include: the principles that nothing is made of nothing, that God cannot die, that he cannot go back on his word, that he cannot make 2 x 10 be more or less than 20, etc. (F, 389-393, passim) These foreshadow Descartes deceiving God hypothesis and his doctrine of the creation of the eternal truths. Also of interest here are the long account of what human reason (= Epicurus?) might say to Plato about the immortality of the soul (F, 385-86) and Montaigne s use of the liar paradox to cast doubt on basic principles of logic. (F, 392) b. Concerning our knowledge of man and nature. (F, 400-18) Of particular interest in this section is Montaigne s return to the subject of the human soul and its claim to immortality, which seems to conclude that only faith teaches us that we are immortal, that reason teaches our mortality. (F, 405-417) Also important are the discussions of the mind-body problem (F, 402-03) and of the problem of identifying principles which can legitimately be taken as first principles (F, 403-405) IX. Warning to the Princess: pyrrhonism is a dangerous and desperate remedy. F, 418-20 Here we learn that Montaigne has been writing this work for an unnamed Princess, who is supposed to favor Sebond. Modern scholarship seems agreed that the princess was Margaret of Valois. Particularly noteworthy here is Montaigne's concession that pyrrhonism is a dangerous weapon to use in defending orthodoxy. X. Man can have no knowledge, not even the limited, probabilistic knowledge claimed by moderate (academic) skepticism (F, 420-436) A. Moderate skepticism stated: we have limited knowledge, based on sense perception; though we cannot have certainty, we can at least make distinctions of probability; and we can make progress in knowledge. (F, 420-21) B. Moderate skepticism rejected: how can men judge likeness to truth if they do not know truth? men are in agreement about nothing; the fact that opinions are constantly changing (both in the individual and in the scientific community) shows that our cognitive faculties

are unreliable; our opinions depend on the state of the body and the passions of the soul; the philosophers disagree about everything, but especially the sovereign good. (F, 421-436) Note: In the text I circulated I made the break between X.A and X.B come on F, 422, and had X.B start with the words "The position of the Pyrrhonians " On reflection I think the rebuttal of academic skepticism really starts a bit earlier, on F, 421, beginning with the words "Man is as capable of all things as he is of any " XI. Doubts about pyrrhonism? What then will philosophy tell us in our need?... I cannot have my judgment so flexible. F, 436-437 Note: Here Montaigne addresses a classic problem for pyrrhonist philosophers, how can the skeptic live his skepticism? Living our daily lives seems to require us to make judgments about what the truth is. (If I step forward, am I going to go off the precipice which seems to be in front of me?) The classic pyrrhonist solution was to follow custom or the laws of your country. Montaigne seems here to have reservations about that solution. There is a typo in the first full paragraph on F, 437: for it prince read a prince XII. Back to pyrrhonism. (F, 437-443) On the folly of natural law. The laws take their authority from possession and usage. Relativity of sense perception to the circumstances of the perceiver. Arbitrary nature of textual interpretation. XIII. On the senses as a basis for knowledge. If there is knowledge, it must come from the senses. But perhaps we lack senses we might have had, senses which would give us a different picture of the world than we have with our existing perceptual apparatus. They might give us knowledge of qualities we now call occult. They might correct perceptions we have on the basis of our existing senses (as we sometimes use one existing sense to correct another). Examples of perceptual error. There is no agreement between us and the animals, or among ourselves. (F, 443-54) XIV. The problem of the criterion and other foundational issues. (F, 454-455) The senses cannot decide our disputes: "To judge the appearances that we receive of objects, we would need a judicatory instrument; to verify this instrument, we need a demonstration; to verify the demonstration, an instrument: there we are in a circle." But neither can reason, since the appeal to reason leads to an infinite regress. XV. Changing man can know neither changing things, nor unchanging God. (There are two typos in the circulated subheading for this section.) Both we and the putative objects of our knowledge are constantly changing (God excepted). Under such conditions we can know nothing. After the first paragraph this is an extensive quotation from Plutarch. (F, 455-57) XVI. Conclusion: Man is nothing without God. He can overcome his human limitations only with divine assistance.