Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

Similar documents
From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

The Human Deficit according to Immanuel Kant: The Gap between the Moral Law and Human Inability to Live by It. Pieter Vos 1

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Kant and his Successors

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

INTENTIONALITY, NORMATIVITY AND COMMUNALITY IN KANT S REALM OF ENDS

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical

The Modern Moral Individual In Hegel's Phenomenology Of Spirit

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

My project in this paper is to reconsider the Kantian conception of practical reason. Some

DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

CONSTRUCTIVISM IN ETHICS

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton

The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation

Natural Goodness, Rightness, and the Intersubjectivity of Reason: A Reply to Arroyo, Cummisky, Molan, and Bird-Pollan

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Korsgaard and the Wille/Willkür Distinction: Radical Constructivism and the Imputability of Immoral Actions

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena

O Neill and Korsgaard on the Construction of Normativity

In this paper I offer an account of Christine Korsgaard s metaethical

6AANA032 Nineteenth-Century Continental Philosophy Syllabus Academic year 2013/14

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

AUTONOMY, TAKING ONE S CHOICES TO BE GOOD, AND PRACTICAL LAW: REPLIES TO CRITICS

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

A Comparative Study of the Ethics of Christine M. Korsgaard and Jean-Paul Sartre

Communicative Rationality and Deliberative Democracy of Jlirgen Habermas: Toward Consolidation of Democracy in Africa

GOD'S SILENCE IN THE DIALOGUE ACCORDING TO MARTIN BUBER

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

François Laruelle and the Non-Philosophical Tradition

On the Normative Aspects of Globalisation Nkiruka Ahiauzu

Sidgwick on Practical Reason

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

Kantian Constructivism, Baseball and Christian Ethics. part of it, about physics, about morality or some of its parts, about reasons or normativity.

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY

PHL271 Handout 2: Hobbes on Law and Political Authority. Many philosophers of law treat Hobbes as the grandfather of legal positivism.

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2013 Russell Marcus

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Animals in the Kingdom of Ends

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Outcomes Assessment of Oral Presentations in a Philosophy Course

The Ethics of Self Realization: A Radical Subjectivism, Bounded by Realism. An Honors Thesis (HONR 499) Kevin Mager. Thesis Advisor Jason Powell

obey the Christian tenet You Shall Love The Neighbour facilitates the individual to overcome

Practical Reason and the Call to Faith: Kant on the Postulates of Immortality and God

ON THE INCOMPATIBILITY BETWEEN ARISTOTLE S AND KANT S IMPERATIVES TO TREAT A MAN NOT AS A MEANS BUT AS AN END-IN- HIMSELF

Violence as a philosophical theme

Autonomy and the Second Person Wthin: A Commentary on Stephen Darwall's Tlie Second-Person Standpoints^

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have

This is a repository copy of Divine Commands and Secular Demands: On Darwall on Anscombe on Modern Moral Philosophy.

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Spring 2011 Russell Marcus

38 Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. [Ak 4:422] [Ak4:421]

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

IMMANUEL KANT Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals [Edited and reduced by J. Bulger, Ph.D.]

From Robert Stern, Understanding Moral Obligation: Kant, Hegel, Kierkegaard (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), pp.

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Kantianism: Objections and Replies Keith Burgess-Jackson 12 March 2017

Stabilizing Kant s First and Second Critiques: Causality and Freedom

Philosophers in Jesuit Education Eastern APA Meetings, December 2011 Discussion Starter. Karen Stohr Georgetown University

Dignity, Contractualism and Consequentialism

Iowa Journal of Cultural Studies

Manuscript for talk at Sheffield April 4 th Draft only. Hans Fink: Løgstrup on Personal Responsibility and Moral Obligation

Secularization in Western territory has another background, namely modernity. Modernity is evaluated from the following philosophical point of view.

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

I found that a lot of things that attracted me to mathematics, rigorous reasoning

Empty, Useless, and Dangerous? Recent Kantian Replies to the Empty Formalism Objection * Fabian Freyenhagen

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Constructivism, Intrinsic Normativity, and the Motivational Analysis Argument

Is Morality Rational?

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Justice and Ethics. Jimmy Rising. October 3, 2002

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

WHY DOES KANT THINK THAT MORAL REQUIREMENTS ARE CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVES?

REASONS AND REFLECTIVE ENDORSMENT IN CHRISTINE KORSGAARD S THE SOURCES OF NORMATIVITY ERIC C. BROWN. (Under the direction of Melissa Seymour-Fahmy)

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

Cosmopolitan Theory and the Daily Pluralism of Life

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Transcription:

Robert Stern Understanding Moral Obligation. Kant, Hegel, Kierkegaard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2012. 277 pages $90.00 (cloth ISBN 978 1 107 01207 3) In his thoroughly researched and tightly argued new book, Robert Stern proposes that the standard story of Kant as an ethical constructivist in particular, the idea that Kant rejected value realism as a threat to autonomy is seriously misleading. An historically more sensitive reading shows that Kantian autonomy was not meant to explain the origin of moral values but their obligatory character, their capacity to bind the will as law. Having established this point in Part I, Stern uses it to provide an alternative to the standard story of the post-kantian tradition of ethics. Part II first details Schiller s attempt to soften the paradoxes of Kant s hybrid theory by bringing natural goodness and moral obligation into alignment, and follows with an examination of Hegel s social command theory of obligation. Part III then explores Kierkegaard s strategies for showing the moral limits of autonomy (whether individual or social) and sketches the Dane s own divine command theory of moral obligation. The book concludes with an extensive review of the dialectical situation engendered by this historical trajectory: How far should considerations of autonomy drive one from a divine command theory to a Kantian hybrid theory? How far should considerations of dualism drive one from a hybrid theory to a Hegelian social command theory? And how far should considerations of complacency drive one from a social command theory to a Kierkegaardian divine command theory? (220). In the end we can see that these positions are finely balanced against each other in a kind of dialectical circle, where each move has advantages and disadvantages (221). Thus the significant challenge of properly theorising and accounting for moral obligation remains as a problem that is still to be resolved (253). It would be hard to overstate the care with which Stern develops each move in the argument that leads to this conclusion, and it would be utterly impossible to reproduce these moves in a brief review. But some sense for the book s riches can perhaps be gleaned by exploring in outline each of the questions just raised. 1) How far should considerations of autonomy drive one from a divine command theory to a Kantian hybrid theory? Stern motivates this question in his opening chapter, where he argues, against Rawls and others, that Kant s argument from autonomy (the idea that moral normativity cannot derive from a source outside the will, such as desire) cannot rule out valuerealism, since such realism need not be grounded in desire. If it is grounded in something like rational moral intuition, then a realist can accept Kant s claim that reason must be given a commanding role in morality while arguing that it is through reason that the agent discerns and is motivated to act by moral values. Indeed, as Stern argues, there is a sense in which Kant must be seen as a value realist: the existence of a rational being seems to be an objective end with absolute value (26 30). Kant s method of inquiring into the principle of morality prior to an inquiry into the good is designed to avoid confusing two very different things moral goodness and well-being or happiness but this does not undermine the moral realist s claim that the Formula of Humanity must have some value underlying it as what grounds its validity 410

(39). And if that is so, then (as Stern argues at length in the following two chapters) Kant s concept of autonomy is not intended to establish the validity of the moral law, but to show how the obligatoriness of morality could be accounted for without heteronomy (40). This point is further buttressed in chapter 2, where Stern sketches the historical debate over natural law and the source of obligation, a debate that reaches well into Kant s own time. While natural law theories may hold that the obligatoriness of morality comes with the territory that moral rightness implies obligation divine command theories conceive obligation as requiring a lawgiver, whose authority is attested in the possibility of sanctions. This does not rule out the idea that what God commands is right prior to the command (God may be the author of the obligation but not the author of the law [34]), but it does raise questions about our motivational relation to the law, questions that Kant s concept of autonomy is designed to address. For instance, the issue of sanctions might make it appear that our motivation to be moral is merely prudential (50) and so heteronomous, since reason would be subordinated to our desire for reward and our interest in avoiding punishment (53). Against this, as Stern shows in some fine pages analyzing Kant s references to God in the Groundwork and elsewhere, Kant wants to establish that the bindingness of morality must be seen to come from our reason itself (62). Against the natural law tradition, the divine command theorist argues that nothing in the nature of things could impose an obligation on us, that is, a curb on our freedom. But nor can we impose such an obligation on ourselves, since that too would leave our freedom unchecked (71 73). Kant s challenge is to make sense of this latter possibility, and he does so, according to Stern, through his distinction between the holy will and the human will. A holy will is bound by the moral law but, since its inclinations are always in accord with right, that law is not experienced by it as necessitating or constraining (77). The human will, however, confronts that very law as an imperative which claims authority over our non-conforming desires and inclinations. Thus morality can be seen as having an obligating force without that force being derived from the command of a divine lawgiver. Against this background, chapter 3 explains Kant s hybrid account of moral obligation as it addresses three interrelated aspects of the problem: value realism and anti-realism, internalism and externalism regarding moral motivation, and the dispute between natural law theorists and divine command theorists. Kant s solution is hybrid because it embraces realism about what is right and wrong, and the value of rational nature on which this rests (90) while denying that this is sufficient for establishing the obligatoriness of the right. Regarding obligation, Kant is an anti-realist. No mere fact carries its own motivational force: nothing in the moral properties of the right or the good involves the kind of internal relation to motivational forces that the notion of obligation entails (94). And this is reflected in Kant s stance toward the debate between natural law and divine command theorists. With the former, Kant holds that the moral law is not authored, but he denies that obligation arises from an enlightened concern with our own good. With the latter, Kant holds that obligation requires a legislator, but he denies that such legislation must arise from a divine will. Rather it derives from the structure of our own wills in contrast to the holy will. Kant s hybrid theory is thus able to overcome the tension between obligatoriness on the one hand and autonomy on the 411

other, and in this way Kant s ethical thought takes the tradition in a new direction, even if it is not the same as the one it is said to follow on the standard story (99). But Kant s hybrid position is not without its problems, and Stern follows up the vicissitudes of this new direction in Parts II and III, each of which contains the same careful attention to historical sources and contemporary debates one finds in Part I. 2) How far should considerations of dualism drive one from a hybrid theory to an Hegelian social command theory? Beginning with Schiller, Part II considers the question of whether Kant s hybrid account presents an unattractively dualistic and conflicted picture of our nature as moral agents (104). According to Schiller, who moves the debate in an Aristotelian direction, Kant s focus on reason as a constraint on our sensuous nature threatens to undermine the very concept of autonomy (144). As a moral ideal, autonomy is better understood as the beautiful soul whose inclinations are not experienced as in conflict with its duty. Unlike Kant s holy will, however, the beautiful soul cannot count on its inclinations being in harmony with the law (118). Thus genuine autonomy involves both grace and dignity a moral vigilance that remains oriented toward the ideal of harmony (127) and leads finally to a political programme to be realized culturally and historically (129). Nevertheless, Schiller remains a transitional figure who never faces the need to offer a different solution to the problem of moral obligation, relying instead on a kind of Platonistic sublime, a transcendence beyond nature conceived as appearance (146). Hegel, in contrast, attempts to provide a more unified and immanent picture (146) and in so doing, as chapter 5 argues, does develop a new social command approach to moral obligation. Stern rejects the idea that Hegel s move to the social is meant to address the familiar charge that Kantian autonomy is an empty formalism. Hegel s claim that the legislating subject is a we not an I is equally empty unless it appeals, just as Kant did, to the antecedent value of rational nature or freedom (148 149). Thus Stern reads Hegel, too, as a value realist and argues that his concept of Sittlichkeit is not designed to address the Kantian paradox of selflegislation but rather to account for moral obligation in a way that avoids the dualism of Kant s hybrid view (150). Stern introduces his argument by explicating Kurt Baier s social command theory, according to which obligation arises by adding to a rational grasp of the morally good the demand by society to act in accordance with what one has moral reason to do (152). On this account, it is not God but society that has a legitimate authority in its own right, the rightful authority to impose such sanctions and thus to issue commands (152). Reading Hegel s concept of Sittlichkeit in these terms, Stern contrasts it with the idea that it is the social role that confers obligations. On Christine Korsgaard s account of practical identity, for instance, it is the identification of the individual with their role that explains obligatoriness, not the social pressure exerted on the individual (164). On Stern s view of Hegel, however, it is precisely this social pressure, coupled with the corresponding refusal of a concept of individual autonomy, that gives rise to obligation. [I]nsofar as this ethical substance is not alien to the subject, that is, insofar as it can be seen historically and philosophically to belong to its own essence, such obligation is not inimical to the freedom of the individual (170). But this generates a different set of problems. 412

3) How far should considerations of complacency drive one from a social command theory to a Kierkegaardian divine command theory? Part III first takes up Kierkegaard s critique of Hegel (chapter 6, focused on the pseudonymous works) and then explores his account of moral obligation (chapter 7, focused on Works of Love). The first step is a reading of Fear and Trembling, where Stern uncovers a kind of intermediate divine command theory according to which it is not morality s goodness or rightness that derives voluntaristically from God s command, but its obligatory force. Kierkegaard nevertheless poses a radical challenge to secular ethicists because, for him, what is good or right involves transcendence and so is not necessarily graspable by reason, i.e., within the human perspective (175). This is the ethical meaning of faith (180), whose absurdity is papered over in Hegel s social command theory. Stern brings this out by analyzing the three Problems Kierkegaard develops in Fear and Trembling. The knight of faith cannot see how his duty connects to the good, as the tragic hero can; nevertheless (in contrast to voluntarism), he knows that God would not make something obligatory unless it were good in some way (183). Similarly, the knight of faith recognizes an absolute duty to God in inwardness despite the fact that such a duty is not mediated by the universal of Sittlichkeit (185). Finally, such a knight must remain silent, cannot give reasons, because he knows that in doing so his actions would inevitably start to seem unwarranted in his eyes (188). Faith is the stance in which one must acknowledge the possibility that God can grasp the good in ways that we cannot and so put us under obligations that are opaque from the human point of view (188). In the chapter s second section, devoted to Judge William s position in the second volume of Either/Or, Stern elucidates an aspect of Kierkegaard s critique of Hegel that does not depend on the aim of preserving the ethical distinctiveness of faith. The Judge s Hegelian conviction that life within Sittlichkeit will bring self-realisation to the individual (195) produces an undemanding moral complacency, a kind of ethical religion the enemy of mysticism (198) in which more cannot be asked of an individual than he is able to accomplish within the bounds of his place in society. In contrast, the Pastor s sermon ( In Relation to God We are Always in the Wrong ) suggests that the love one feels for God brings with it a consciousness of always falling short, and so also a concept of ethics as a radical demand that we cannot fulfill on our own (203). This sets the stage for Kierkegaard s account of moral obligation, exemplified by the divine command to love thy neighbor. Kierkegaard s appeal to the love commandment serves to highlight the inevitability of what Stern (following Hare) calls a moral gap, the recognition that a requirement of morality outstrips our capabilities for meeting it (206). If a moral gap is possible, it seems to entail that God is both the lawgiver and (via forgiveness) the only viable means of dealing with it (207). Though the love commandment is quite specific, the moral gap shows up wherever the universal scope of a moral demand (feed the starving!) cannot be met by an individual. (This issue and its theological implications have been treated extensively in recent Continental ethics for instance, in Levinas, and, following him, in Derrida s The Gift of Death and the fact that Stern does not engage with such writers is one of the book s few missed opportunities.) The 413

path to a divine command account can be seen by asking how, on a social command theory, any one of us, either individually or collectively, can have the kind of authority to impose such a law on ourselves or each other (213). If a concern for autonomy leads us to embrace either Kantian or Hegelian expedients here, we will have to scale back the requirements of the moral law, and we will lose notions such as divine assistance and forgiveness which are needed to bridge the moral gap and to make sense of moral universalism in a strenuous form (215). In a word, we will become morally complacent. Thus what begins with Kant as an attempt to establish the obligatoriness of the moral law in the autonomy of the human will leads back to a divine command theory. And as Stern makes clear in his philosophically acute Conclusion: From Kant to Kierkegaard and Back Again?, this understanding of the post-kantian tradition is something like an aporetic Platonic dialogue: it leaves us confronting the original problem, only a good deal wiser about what the problem is. Each position surveyed highlights an aspect of the phenomenology of moral obligation that simply cannot be excluded in any account of it, and it is fealty to these aspects, rather than any cobbled together solution, that distinguishes Stern s thoughtful contribution to the debate. Historians of philosophy and ethical theorists will find much to disagree with in it, but Stern s book is a model of how systematic philosophy can be fruitfully pursued in dialogue with historical sources without doing violence to the historical particularity of those sources. Steven Crowell Rice University 414