Solutions for Assignment 1

Similar documents
Extra Syntax Exercises 5

Introduction to Transformational Grammar, LINGUIST 601 December 3, Wh-Movement

Reminder: Yes-no questions

CAS LX 522 Syntax I Fall 2000 November 6, 2000 Paul Hagstrom Week 9: Binding Theory. (8) John likes him.

Reconsidering Raising and Experiencers in English

Extraposition and Covert Movement

Category Mistakes in M&E

Some Anaphoric/Elliptical Constructions of English

Logophors, variable binding and the interpretation of have. *

Final Exam due on December 13, 2001

Review of Philosophical Logic: An Introduction to Advanced Topics *

Exercises Introduction to morphosyntax

What is infinitival to?

Anaphora Resolution in Biomedical Literature: A

WH-Movement. Ling 322 Read Syntax, Ch. 11

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

Some observations on identity, sameness and comparison

ACD in AP? Richard K. Larson. Stony Brook University

A set of puzzles about names in belief reports

Phil 413: Problem set #1

Exhaustification over Questions in Japanese

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

Competition and Disjoint Reference. Norvin Richards, MIT. appear; Richards 1995). The typical inability of pronouns to be locally bound, on this

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 1)

Supplementary Section 6S.7

Be Bound or Be Disjoint! Andrew Kehler and Daniel Büring. UCSD and UCLA

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

A Typology of Clause Combining

The structure of this lecture. 1. Introduction (coordination vs. subordination) 2. Types of subordinate clauses 3. Functions of subordinate clauses

Discourse Constraints on Anaphora Ling 614 / Phil 615 Sponsored by the Marshall M. Weinberg Fund for Graduate Seminars in Cognitive Science

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

Reference Resolution. Announcements. Last Time. 3/3 first part of the projects Example topics

ANAPHORIC REFERENCE IN JUSTIN BIEBER S ALBUM BELIEVE ACOUSTIC

hates the woman [who rejected him i hates the woman [who rejected Peter i ] is hated by him i ] (Langacker 1969: 169) (2) (3) (4a) (4b) (4) a. S b.

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:

(2480 words) 1. Introduction

On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University

In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a

Puzzles of attitude ascriptions

Ethical non-naturalism

HS01: The Grammar of Anaphora: The Study of Anaphora and Ellipsis An Introduction. Winkler /Konietzko WS06/07

Satisfied or Exhaustified An Ambiguity Account of the Proviso Problem

Article selection and anaphora in the German relative clause Julian Grove and Emily Hanink University of Chicago

A Freezing Approach to the Ish-Construction in English

Chisholm s Paradox in Should-Conditionals

Johns Hopkins Math Tournament 2018 Proof Round: Fuzzy Knights and Knaves

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS

Reference Resolution. Regina Barzilay. February 23, 2004

A Short Course in Logic Example 3

3. Negations Not: contradicting content Contradictory propositions Overview Connectives

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Aboutness and Justification

Two Puzzles About Deontic Necessity

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

Areas of Specialization and Competence Philosophy of Language, History of Analytic Philosophy

WH- MOVEMENT IN PALESTINIAN ARABIC

Is Content Holism Incoherent? 1. Kirk A. Ludwig Department of Philosophy University of Florida Gainesville, FL

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames Draft March 1, My theory of propositions starts from two premises: (i) agents represent things as

The structure of this lecture. 1. Introduction (coordination vs. subordination) 2. Types of subordinate clauses 3. Functions of subordinate clauses

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Presuppositions (Ch. 6, pp )

On "deep and surface. anaphora. Eunice Pontes

Conditions on Propositional Anaphora

Subject Index. Index

Presupposition projection: Global accommodation, local accommodation, and scope ambiguities

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

1 ReplytoMcGinnLong 21 December 2010 Language and Society: Reply to McGinn. In his review of my book, Making the Social World: The Structure of Human

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

Lecture 9: Presuppositions

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Prior on an insolubilium of Jean Buridan

God of the gaps: a neglected reply to God s stone problem

Kai von Fintel. Massachusetts Institute of Technology. The background for this squib is the ongoing debate about whether natural language

By the Time Viewing relative progress or completion

Theories of propositions

Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators. Christopher Peacocke. Columbia University

Identifying Anaphoric and Non- Anaphoric Noun Phrases to Improve Coreference Resolution

2 Two accounts of German FP-Syntax. Reis (2005): On the Syntax of so-called Focus Particles in German. A reply to Büring and Hartmann 2001

DEFINING ONTOLOGICAL CATEGORIES IN AN EXPANSION OF BELIEF DYNAMICS

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Topics in Linguistic Theory: Propositional Attitudes

Illustrating Deduction. A Didactic Sequence for Secondary School

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

Vagueness and supervaluations

Russell on Denoting. G. J. Mattey. Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156. The concept any finite number is not odd, nor is it even.

08 Anaphora resolution

KNOWLEDGE AND THE PROBLEM OF LOGICAL OMNISCIENCE

Predict the Behavior. Leonardo Caffo. Propositional Attitudes and Philosophy of Action. University of Milan - Department of Philosophy

Advanced Topics in Metaphysics (L6/7) Alex Grzankowski Autumn 2016

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Believing Epistemic Contradictions

Predict the Behavior. Propositional Attitudes and Philosophy of Action

yes Head of chain in posidon where Case is assigned Head of chain in posidon where theta- role is assigned Foot of chain in posidon no somedmes

Transcription:

Syntax 380L August 30, 2001 Solutions for Assignment 1 The highest grade in this assignment was 95/95. The median grade was 77/95. 1. Draw trees for the following sentences and for each tree list the c-command relationships that hold between the nodes in the tree. a. Na-rae likes her. S Na-rae VP Φ V likes her c-commands VP, V, ; VP c-commands c-commands V; V c-commands b. Judy thinks that Young-suk is brilliant. S 1 Φ Judy VP 1 Φ V 1 thinks CP Φ C that S 2 Youngsuk VP 2 Φ Φ V 2 is AP brilliant c-commands VP 1 and everything that VP 1 dominates; VP 1 c-commands. V 1 c-commands CP and everything that CP dominates; CP c-commands V 1. C c-commands S 2 and everything S 2 dominates; S 2 c-commands C. c-commands VP 2 and everything VP 2 dominates; VP 2 c-commands. V 2 c-commands AP; AP c-commands V 2. c. Martin s brother gave a book to Waltraud. c-commands N 1 and vice versa; c-commands VP and everything that VP dominates; VP c-commands. V c-commands NP 3 and PP and nodes dominates by NP 3 and PP; NP 3 c-commands V, PP, and the nodes dominates by PP. PP c-commands V, NP 3, and the nodes dominates by NP 3. P c-commands NP 3 and vice versa; D c-commands N 2 and vice versa.

S Φ Φ Φ Martin s N 1 brother VP V gave D a NP 3 Φ Φ N 2 book d. Karlos told Tatjana that he disliked flamenco. S 1 Φ Φ Karlos V 1 told VP 1 Φ Tatjana C that CP Φ Φ Φ PP Φ Φ P to S 2 NP 3 he Φ Φ Φ NP 4 Waltraud VP 2 V 2 disliked NP 4 flamenco c-commands VP 1 and every node dominated by VP 1 ;VP 1 c-commands. V 1 c-commands, CP and every node dominated by CP; CP c-commands V 1. c-commands V 1, CP and every node dominated by CP; CP c-commands. C c-commands S 2 and every node dominated by S 2 ;S 2 c-commands C. NP 3 c-commands VP 2 and every node dominated by VP 2 ;VP 2 c-commands NP 3. V 2 c-commands NP 4 and vice versa. 2. By determining co-reference possibilities for pronouns, determine where the following clauses occur in the structure: The question is whether the adjunction is at the level of the clause or lower in the tree. The result we find is that while sentence-initial if/when/because-clauses are adjoined to S, sentence-final if/when/because-clauses are adjoined to VP. This structural analysis was proposed for if-clauses in Iatridou (1991). a. if clauses that follow the main clause: I would be very happy [if ikyoung joined us]. The relevant judgement here is: *e i would be very happy [if Olafur i joined us]. This shows that the if-clause must be in the sister of he i.e. it cannot be right adjoined to S. This leaves open the choice between VP right-adjunction and S right-adjunction structures. 2

b. if clauses that precede the main clause: [If ikyoung joined us], I would be very happy. The relevant judgements here are: [If Olafur i joined us], he i would be very happy. [If he i joined us], Olafur i would be very happy. They show that the subject of the main clause does not c-command the if-clause and that the subject of the if-clause does not c-command the main clause. The only structure possible here is left adjunction to S i.e. [ S [if-clause] [ S :::]]. c. because clauses that follow the main clause: Faye left [because Tim was singing]. The argumentation and results are identical to (2a) i.e. VP-adjunction to the right, not S-adjunction to the right. d. because clauses that precede the main clause: [Because Tim was singing], Faye left. The argumentation and results are identical to (2a) i.e. S-adjunction to the left. 3. Some constituents seem to be discontinuous i.e. different parts of the constituent do not form a continuous string. By using coreference possibilities for the emphasized pronoun and name determine possible structural locations for the bracketed constituent. One mistake some of you made was to re-order the constituents in the sentences in 3 in such a fashion that the discontinuity vanished. This was not the right way to go about attacking this problem. Once you changed the word order, you ended up analyzing a completely different sentence one that was devoid of the problem that is of theoretical interest in the following examples - the problem of discontinuous constituents. This exercise and the next was based on examples and discussion in Liberman (1974) and Guéron and May (1984). a. Extraposed Relative Clause i. She told many people about the concert [who Mary made nervous]. Since she cannot refer to Mary, she must c-command Mary. Note that [who Mary made nervous] does not form a constituent with the concert, or even with many people about the concert. Thus the only choices are right adjunction to S and right adjunction to VP. Right adjunction to S would mean that the extraposed relative clause would not be c-commanded by she. ence right adjunction to VP is the only option. ii. I told her that many people attended last year s concert [who made Mary nervous]. Suggested structures: embedded S-adjunction: I [told her [that [[many people [attended [last year s concert]]] [who made Mary nervous]]]] embedded VP-adjunction: I [told her [that [many people [[attended [last year s concert]] [who made Mary nervous]]]]] iii. I told her that the concert was attended by many people last year [who made Mary nervous]. 3

embedded VP-adjunction: I [told her [that [[the concert] [[[was attended [by many people]] [last year]] [who made Mary nervous]]]]]. In both (a.ii) and (a.iii), the extraposed relative clause could in principle attach to several locations: the matrix S, the matrix VP, the embedded S, and the embedded VP. Since her cannot refer to Mary, we can conclude that her must c-command the extraposed relative clause. In other words, the extraposed relative clause must be in the same clause as the NP that it semantically modifies. This constraint is known as the Right Roof Constraint and was first noted in Ross (1967). We are still left with the question of whether the extraposed relative clause in (a.ii) and (a.iii) are adjoined to embedded S or to the embedded VP. The case of (a.iii) is easy - there we can show that the extraposed relative clause must be adjoined to the VP because of the following example: *I told Bill that she i was criticized by many people last year [who made Mary i nervous]. If adjunction to the embedded S was a possibility in (a.iii), we would expect coreference to be possible in the above example. Ruling out adjunction to the embedded S in (a.ii) is not that easy. So far all the cases of extraposed relative clauses we have seen have involved adjunction to VP. owever, they have also all involved direct objects and prepositional objects and not subjects. So we cannot use the evidence from those cases to adjudicate (a.ii), which involves extraposition from subject. Therefore we will leave the issue unsettled for now. b. Result Clause i. She told so many people about the concert [that Mary made Bill nervous]. [[She told so many people about the concert] [that Mary made Bill nervous]]. ii. I told her that that so many people attended last year s concert [that I made Mary nervous]. [[I told her that that so many people attended last year s concert] [that I made Mary nervous]]. iii. I told her that that the concert was attended by so many people last year [that I made Mary nervous]. [[I told her that that the concert was attended by so many people last year] [that I made Mary nervous]]. The situation with Result Clauses seems to be quite distinct. They involve adjunction to S. The evidence for this comes from the fact that her can refer to Mary in all of (b.iiii). Note also that Result Clauses are different from extraposed relative clauses in that they can appear in a clause different than the NP they are intuitively related to. 4. The following sentences are ambiguous. The two readings for the first sentence are provided. Indicate the two readings for the second sentence and then provide a structural account for the ambiguity of these sentences. a. Mary claimed that Bill was so weird that he ate ants. Reading 1: Mary s claim: Bill is so weird that he eats ants. In other words, according to Mary, Bill eats ants and this demonstrates how weird he is. Reading 2: Mary claimed that Bill was very weird. This annoyed Bill and so just to prove a point he ate ants. Note that Bill s eating ants is not part of what Mary said. 4

b. Mary claimed that Bill was so weird that we didn t invite him to dinner. Reading 1: Mary s claim: Bill is so weird that we didn t him for dinner. In other words, according to Mary, our not inviting Bill for dinner is related to his high degree of weirdness. Reading 2: Mary claimed that Bill was weird to a very high degree. er claim was responsible for our not inviting Bill. Structural account: Reading 1: Adjunction to the embedded S: Mary claimed that [[Bill was so weird] [that we didn t invite him to dinner]]. The result clause is part of the claim. Reading 2: Adjunction to the matrix S: [[Mary claimed that Bill was so weird] [that we didn t invite him to dinner]]. The result clause is not part of the claim. Evidence: She claimed that Bill was so weird that we didn t invite Mary for dinner. If she is interpreted as referring to Mary, Reading 1 is unavailable. This is so because on Reading 1 (but not on Reading 2), the matrix subject c-commands into the Result Clause. 5. Determine whether the following statements are true or false. If you believe a statement to be false, provide a counterexample. If you believe a statement to be true, provide an informal proof detailing why the statement follows. a. if node ff dominates node fi and node fi dominates node fl, then node ff dominates node fl. True. We will use the fact that ff dominates fi if and only if ff contains fi. Therefore if ff dominates fi, then ff contains fi and if fi dominates fl, then fi contains fl. But if ff contains fi and fi contains fl, then ff contains fl. Working back, we can conclude that ff dominates fl. b. if node ff c-commands node fi and node fi c-commands node fl, then node ff c-commands node fl. False. ere is a counterexample: Φ ff fi fl ff c-commands fi and fi c-commands fl. owever ff does not c-command fl. Some of you noted that the above made (5b) partly false and partly true because there were also cases where there are cases like the following:. Φ ff. Φ Φ fi. fl 5

owever, it is important to note that statements are either true or false - mathematical truth is not gradable. The existence of a single counterexample is enough to show that a statement is false. On the other hand, no number of examples is sufficient to show that a mathematical statement is true. For that we need a proof. References Guéron, J., and R. May (1984) Extraposition and Logical Form, Linguistic Inquiry 15:1, 1 32. Iatridou, S. (1991) Topics in Conditionals, Doctoral dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, Massachusetts. Distributed by MIT Working Papers in Linguistics. Liberman, M. (1974) On Conditioning the Rule of Subject-Auxiliary Inversion, in E. Kaisse and J. ankamer, eds., Papers from the Fifth Annual Meeting of the North Eastern Linguistics Society, arvard University, Cambridge MA. Ross, J. (1967) Constraints on Variables in Syntax, Doctoral dissertation, MIT. 6