I'd Like to Have an Argument, Please.

Similar documents
PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments

Argument and Persuasion. Stating Opinions and Proposals

Pastor-teacher Don Hargrove Faith Bible Church September 8, 2011

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000)

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

Critical Thinking. The Four Big Steps. First example. I. Recognizing Arguments. The Nature of Basics

PHILOSOPHY ESSAY ADVICE

Logic -type questions

The Completeness of the Scriptures

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS

Introduction to Philosophy

MPS 17 The Structure of Persuasion Logos: reasoning, reasons, good reasons not necessarily about formal logic

Logic Practice Test 1

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Relevance. Premises are relevant to the conclusion when the truth of the premises provide some evidence that the conclusion is true

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Three Kinds of Arguments

Logic: A Brief Introduction. Ronald L. Hall, Stetson University

A REVIEW OF THE DEAVER-FOX DEBATE. Part 1

How to Write a Philosophy Paper

Skim the Article to Find its Conclusion and Get a Sense of its Structure

Full file at

Deduction by Daniel Bonevac. Chapter 1 Basic Concepts of Logic

III. RULES OF POLICY (TEAM) DEBATE. A. General

SHORT ANSWER. Write the word or phrase that best completes each statement or answers the question.

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation. Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017

Recall. Validity: If the premises are true the conclusion must be true. Soundness. Valid; and. Premises are true

Handout 1: Arguments -- the basics because, since, given that, for because Given that Since for Because

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

Self-Refuting Statements

Example Arguments ID1050 Quantitative & Qualitative Reasoning

How to Argue Without Being Argumentative

ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano

Tactics in Conversation

Am I free? Freedom vs. Fate

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

The Cosmological Argument

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Please visit our website for other great titles:

What is an argument? PHIL 110. Is this an argument? Is this an argument? What about this? And what about this?

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

Chapter 9- Sentential Proofs

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims).

Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument

Portfolio Project. Phil 251A Logic Fall Due: Friday, December 7

Part II: How to Evaluate Deductive Arguments

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

Attacking your opponent s character or personal traits in an attempt to undermine their argument

2013 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved. 1

5.3 The Four Kinds of Categorical Propositions

Tactics for an Ambassador: Defending the Christian Faith

Alan Shlemon. Stand to Reason

LOGIC Lesson 10: Univocal, Equivocal, Analogical Terms. 1. A term in logic is the subject or the predicate of a proposition (a declarative sentence).

Introduction Symbolic Logic

Some Templates for Beginners: Template Option 1 I am analyzing A in order to argue B. An important element of B is C. C is significant because.

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

1 Chapter 6 (Part 2): Assessing Truth Claims

Lecture 4: Deductive Validity

The way we convince people is generally to refer to sufficiently many things that they already know are correct.

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic?

FOLLOWING CHRIST IN THE WORLD

Video: How does understanding whether or not an argument is inductive or deductive help me?

The Field of Logical Reasoning: (& The back 40 of Bad Arguments)

Argument. What is it? How do I make a good one?

The following materials are the product of or adapted from Marvin Ventrell and the Juvenile Law Society with permission. All rights reserved.

National Quali cations

Many cite internet videos, forums, blogs, etc. as a major reason*

Ima Emotivist (EM) X is good means Hurrah for X! Moral judgments aren t true or false. We can t reason about basic moral principles.

WHY SHOULD ANYONE BELIEVE ANYTHING AT ALL?

b. Use of logic in reasoning; c. Development of cross examination skills; d. Emphasis on reasoning and understanding; e. Moderate rate of delivery;

Arguments and Their Evaluation T. K. Trelogan

Heilewif s Tale Teacher s Guide SE. Thomas Aquinas and Scholasticism by Mary Waite

Lesson 2 Faith and Knowledge [Part 2] Apologetics Press Intermediate Christian Evidences Correspondence Course

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

Mark Anthony D. Abenir, MCD Department of Social Sciences & Philosophy University of Santo Tomas

Tutorial A03: Patterns of Valid Arguments By: Jonathan Chan

Ethics and Science. Obstacles to search for truth. Ethics: Basic Concepts 1

Richard Carrier, Ph.D.

FREEDOM OF CHOICE. Freedom of Choice, p. 2

Of sin, the depravity of man, and the wrath of God (J. Peterson)

The Art of Critical Thinking

Aquinas Cosmological argument in everyday language

I. What is an Argument?

C. Problem set #1 due today, now, on the desk. B. More of an art than a science the key things are: 4.

Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism. The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which asserts that the meaning of a

stage 2 Logic & Knowledge

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

v o i c e A Document for Dialogue and Study Report of the Task Force on Human Sexuality The Alliance of Baptists

Powerful Arguments: Logical Argument Mapping

Mr Vibrating: Yes I did. Man: You didn t Mr Vibrating: I did! Man: You didn t! Mr Vibrating: I m telling you I did! Man: You did not!!

2. Public Forum Debate seeks to encourage the development of the following skills in the debaters: d. Reasonable demeanor and style of presentation

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.

A Note on Straight-Thinking

Deduction. Of all the modes of reasoning, deductive arguments have the strongest relationship between the premises

Transcription:

I'd Like to Have an Argument, Please. A solid argument can be built just like a solid house: walls first, then the roof. Here s a building plan, plus three ways arguments collapse. July/August 2002 I want to teach you how to assess a basic argument. How can you know if an argument is a good one or not? There s no magic to this. The tools of thinking are simple ones. Anyone can employ them skillfully with a little practice. If you have the right equipment you can make a lot of progress even if you don t consider yourself an intellectual whiz-kid. Think of an argument like a simple house, a roof supported by walls. The roof is the conclusion and the walls are the supporting ideas. In the lingo of logic, the walls are called premises and the whole structure of the building is called a syllogism. Syllogisms have a particular form and contain certain facts. When the form is right and the facts are true we say that the argument is sound, that the walls are strong enough to support the roof. The conclusion is true, resting securely on its supporting foundation. Our goal in clear thinking is to see if the walls are solid or can be knocked down. If the walls go down, the roof goes flat and the argument is defeated. A House with No Walls First, an observation. Some arguments are not really arguments at all. In terms of our house illustration, many people try to build their roof right on the ground. Instead of erecting solid walls, the supporting ideas that hold the conclusion up, they simply assert their conclusion and pound the podium. An argument is different from an assertion, though. An assertion simply states a point. An argument gives supporting reasons why the point should be taken seriously. The reasons become the topic of mutual discussion or analysis. But if there are no reasons, there s little to discuss. Opinions are opinions, not proof. A mere point of view cannot be taken seriously as worthy of belief. That requires reasons. Roofs are useless when they re on the ground. In the same way an assertion without evidence doesn t do any work. I frequently get calls from people who think they re giving me an argument, when all they re doing is forcefully stating a point of view. They sound compelling, but a closer look reveals an emperor with lots of bluster, but no bloomers. My job is to recognize that the roof is laying flat on the ground and simply point it out.

If you find yourself stymied in a discussion, you may be looking for an argument that s not there. Ask yourself, "Did they give me an argument or just make an assertion?" If the latter is true then say, "Well, that s an interesting opinion. What s your argument? Why should I believe what you believe? How did you come to that conclusion? Give me your reasons." Don t let them flatten you by dropping a roof on your head. Make them build walls underneath their roof. Ask for reasons or facts to support their conclusion. Three Ways an Argument Can Go Bad Any real argument, as opposed to an assertion, has three parts. It has a particular form, it affirms particular facts, and it uses particular words or terms to make its point. When an argument goes bad, the problem is either in the form, the facts, or the terms. First, an argument s form can be bad. Let me give you an example. Take this syllogism: "All men are cheerful. John is a man. Therefore, John is cheerful." This is a simple argument containing two statements (premises) and a conclusion. The conclusion is dependent on the first two statements. The first is the major premiseall men are cheerful. The second is the minor premisejohn is a man. The final statement is the conclusionjohn is cheerful. Notice the form of this argument. It s clear that if the facts of the first statement are true, that all men are cheerful, and if the facts of the second statement are true, that John is a man, then the conclusion follows naturally. If you accept the truth of the first two statements, the truth of the third is automatic. One "follows" from the other. When the form is correct we say the argument is "valid." What about this one: "All men are cheerful. Jane is not a man. Therefore, Jane is not cheerful." A moment s reflection shows this doesn t work. Even if it were true that all men are cheerful and Jane is not a man, it still wouldn t follow that Jane is not cheerful. Women can be cheerful, too. We use the term "fallacy" to describe an argument that has a faulty construction. There are different types of fallacies listed in logic books, and I won t detail them here. Many of them, though, are obvious upon a little reflection. Just ask yourself, "Does it follow that because A and B, therefore C?" Does it follow that (A) because all men are cheerful, and (B) Jane is not a man, that (C) Jane is therefore not cheerful? When the form is bad, when the conclusion does not follow from the premises, it s called a non sequitur, Latin for "it does not follow." Non sequiturs cannot be trusted. It may be Jane is not cheerful, but you can t know that from the information provided. Even when the form is right there still may be problems. Facts can also make an argument go bad. Accurate form (a valid argument) does not guarantee that the statements themselves are accurate. What if it s not true that all men are cheerful? Maybe some are gloomy. What if John is not a man, or not even human? Maybe John is a robot or the name of Socrates pet Schnauzer. Take the argument, "All unicorns live in Ireland. Pegasus is a unicorn. Therefore, Pegasus lives in Ireland." Acknowledging that the form is valid (it is) doesn t at the same time commit you to the existence of unicorns or tell you anything about where they live. The factual questions about unicorns is a separate issue. If the facts in the statements are wrong, then the argument still fails even though the form is right. Clear thinking requires we look closely at the facts as well as the form. The statements themselves must be true.

The third way an argument can go wrong is in the terms. The meanings of the words may not be clear. This is called "equivocation." Basically, equivocation means a vagueness, ambiguity, or uncertainty. If somebody states her opinion very clearly and then under challenge becomes less sure of her position, we say she s equivocating. She waffles; she s uncertain. Sometimes words are equivocal. They are unclear, uncertain, or may have multiple meanings that become confused with each other in the discussion. This creates problems for an argument. Look at this example: "All men are cheerful. John is a man. Therefore, John is cheerful." The word "man" may be equivocal. It s unclear whether "man" means a grown male or simply a member of the male gender. The phrase "all men are cheerful" could refer to all adult males and exclude boys. Our argument would falter through equivocation if we meant this: "All men [adult males] are cheerful. Little Johnny is a man [male gender]. Therefore, little Johnny is cheerful." See the problem? What is meant by "men" in the first sentence isn t the same as what is meant by "man" in the second sentence. There is confusion, equivocation, on the term "man". Here s a real-life theological example: "Jesus is God. Mary is the mother of Jesus. Therefore, Mary is the mother of God." The form here seems correct, the conclusion follows from the premises. It also seems that the individual statements are true. But something s wrong here. God is not the kind of being that has a mother. Where did we go wrong? The problem becomes more obvious when we take it a step further: "Mary is the mother of God. God is a trinity. Therefore, Mary is the mother of the Trinity." This, of course, is patently false. But why is there a problem if the form is sound and the facts are in order? The problem lies with the terms. There s an equivocation here on the phrase "Jesus is God." Jesus is a very unusual individual. Yes, He is God, but He s also fully human. Jesus is one person with two natures, the nature of God and the nature of man. When we say Jesus is God, we are not saying His humanity is divine. That would be a contradiction. We are saying He is God in that He has a divine nature. Mary is the mother Jesus in the sense that she s the mother of His physical body. She is the mother of His humanity, not the mother of His divinity. Equivocation on these terms, the lack of clarity, makes false a seemingly sound conclusion. The facts are right. The form is right. But the conclusion is false because the meanings of the terms are ambiguous. They re equivocal. Recently I got a call from a gentleman who said, "Jesus is God. God is a trinity. Therefore, Jesus is a trinity." He thought he constructed his argument right, but clearly the conclusion is false. Therefore there must be something wrong with the facts. Either Jesus is not God or God is not a trinity. Of course, this was his point. He was challenging the notion of the Trinity on logical grounds. My caller s error, though, was not in the form or the facts of the argument, but in an equivocation in the words. When Christianity teaches that Jesus is God, it doesn t mean that Jesus and God are identical. Jesus has the nature of God, but He is not everything that God is. God subsists in three persons; Jesus is only one person.

What was missing here was a clarification of terms. The clarification had to be made, and the equivocation removed, for this attack on the Trinity to be defeated. Some of the assessment of an argument is based on the clarity of the concepts involved. This is why precision with words is critical to clear thinking. Invisible Walls Sometimes it s very difficult to assess an argument because the full form of the argument is not stated. The elements aren t listed one, two, three as they were above. Some of the parts are taken for granted, "understood" by the participants, in the process of conversation. This streamlines conversation, but it can also allow bad facts to go undetected. Once a homosexual said to me, "Jesus never condemned homosexuality." Though this is only one sentience, it s actually a full argument in shorthand, streamlined for brevity. The conclusion didn t need to be stated. I got the point. I was wrong for attacking homosexuality on moral grounds. Because Jesus never condemned homosexuality, it is therefore morally acceptable behavior. Notice, though, that the conclusion is not the only thing taken for granted here. The minor premise is stated and the conclusion is assumed, but what of the major premise, our first step in the argument? The unspoken major premise, the invisible wall holding up this argument, contained a serious flaw that went undetected. We discover the flaw by asking what kind of major premise is needed to make this argument work. The full argument would have to look something like this: Whatever Jesus did not explicitly condemn is morally acceptable. Jesus never explicitly condemned homosexuality. Therefore, homosexuality is morally acceptable. The form of this argument is good; nothing amiss there. But look closer at the major premise. Its facts are bad; this statement is clearly false. It doesn t seem to be true that whatever Jesus doesn t directly condemn is morally acceptable. Jesus never condemned slavery, child abuse, wife-beating, or gay-bashing, but that proves nothing. Many Christians are caught flat-footed here, sensing something is wrong, but not knowing what it is. Sometimes we have to look more closely and identify the unspoken premise. That can be done by asking a simple question: "Are you saying that if Jesus doesn t specifically condemn something, then He condones it?" When they say no (and they must, because such a view is untenable), ask, "Then what s your point?" Don t get into a fuss. Just ask the question calmly and directly. The silence that follows proves the game is up. A Jehovah s Witness once called me and said, "The Trinity isn t mentioned in the Bible." The unspoken point was obvious: "Therefore, the Trinity is not biblical." I asked, "Are you saying that anything not specifically mentioned in the Bible cannot be true?" (the invisible wall). He was in trouble here because lots of things aren t mentioned specifically in the Bible that still find support in the Scripture. The word "monotheism" isn t in the Bible, or the word "Jehovah," as a point of fact. "No," he answered. "Then what s your point?" I responded, and the argument was over.

Often times the flaw in an argument, the "fact" that s wrong, is hidden in an unspoken assumption that your opponent takes for granted. Kick the unspoken premise into the open. Usually that s all that s needed for the whole structure to come tumbling down. The Obligation of Reason To assess a genuine argument and not a mere assertion, examine the structure. Observe the form of the argument. Examine the facts. Look for hidden statements that may not have been expressed. Finally, examine the terms to see if there s any equivocation, any ambiguity or lack of clarity. If the argument is sound, if the form is valid, the facts accurate, and the terms clear and precise, then the conclusion is true. Period. In fact, the conclusion is irrefutable; it s not even possible to be mistaken. This demonstrates the compelling nature of rationality. There is a bomb-proof quality about deductive logic. If one is faced with a logically valid argument with clear terms and accurate facts, he has a rational obligation to believe the conclusion, even if he doesn t like what he finds. This is called intellectual honesty. Rationality has nothing to do with what we like; it has to do with what is true. That s why it s such a useful tool for all who are interested in knowing the way the world really is. Yours for the Kingdom, Gregory Koukl President, Stand to Reason