Theories of the mind have been celebrating their new-found freedom to study

Similar documents
Elements of Mind (EM) has two themes, one major and one minor. The major theme is

Two books, one title. And what a title! Two leading academic publishers have

Chalmers, "Consciousness and Its Place in Nature"

Please remember to sign-in by scanning your badge Department of Psychiatry Grand Rounds

The readings for the course are separated into the following two categories:

Machine Consciousness, Mind & Consciousness

Thomas Nagel, "What is it Like to Be a Bat?", The Philosophical Review 83 (1974),

PHILOSOPHY OF MIND (7AAN2061) SYLLABUS: SEMESTER 1

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 3 D A Y 2 : I M M A T E R I A L I S M, D U A L I S M, & T H E M I N D - B O D Y P R O B L E M

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person

Formative Assessment: 2 x 1,500 word essays First essay due 16:00 on Friday 30 October 2015 Second essay due: 16:00 on Friday 11 December 2015

This is, of course, quite correct; one cannot argue for narrow states of mind simply from the existence of error. Descombes goes on:

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

Experiences Don t Sum

Higher-Order Approaches to Consciousness and the Regress Problem

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

INTENTIONAL OBJECTS 1. Tim Crane

What, Then, is Consciousness?

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 4 : I M M A T E R I A L I S M, D U A L I S M, & T H E M I N D - B O D Y P R O B L E M

Phenomenology: a historical perspective. The purpose of this session is to explain the historical context in which

Consciousness, Theories of

UNIVERSITY OF CALICUT SCHOOL OF DISTANCE EDUCATION. (2011 Admn. onwards) VI Semester B.A. PHILOSOPHY CORE COURSE CONTEMPORARY WESTERN PHILOSOPHY

Qualia Ain't in the Head Review of Ten Problems of Consciousness: A Representational Theory of the Phenomenal Mind by Michael Tye

V3301 Twentieth-Century Philosophy PHIL V TR 2:40pm-3:55pm- 516 Hamilton Hall - Fall Professor D. Sidorsky

Tony Chadwick Essay Prize 2006 Winner Can we Save Qualia? (Thomas Nagel and the Psychophysical Nexus ) By Eileen Walker

Supervenience & Emergentism: A Critical Study in Philosophy of Mind. Rajakishore Nath, Indian Institute of Technology Bombay, India

Thinking About Consciousness

Annotated Bibliography. seeking to keep the possibility of dualism alive in academic study. In this book,

Naturalism vs. Conceptual Analysis. Marcin Miłkowski

Philosophy A465: Introduction to Analytic Philosophy Loyola University of New Orleans Ben Bayer Spring 2011

Franz Brentano s attempt to distinguish mental from physical phenomena by

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Department of Philosophy TCD. Great Philosophers. Dennett. Tom Farrell. Department of Surgical Anatomy RCSI Department of Clinical Medicine RCSI

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

The Mind-Body Problem

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Subjectivity, Objectivity, Intersubjectivity: Phenomenology and Analytical Philosophy 1

The knowledge argument

Realism and instrumentalism

Craig on the Experience of Tense

The knowledge argument purports to show that there are non-physical facts facts that cannot be expressed in

24.09 Minds and Machines spring an inconsistent tetrad. argument for (1) argument for (2) argument for (3) argument for (4)

Metaphysics & Consciousness. A talk by Larry Muhlstein

THE NATURE OF MIND Oxford University Press. Table of Contents

Summary of Sensorama: A Phenomenalist Analysis of Spacetime and Its Contents

Elements of Mind. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind. Tim Crane

Philosophy of Mind (MIND) CTY Course Syllabus

On Dispositional HOT Theories of Consciousness

Introduction. Bernard Williams

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 1

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

In his pithy pamphlet Free Will, Sam Harris. Defining free will away EDDY NAHMIAS ISN T ASKING FOR THE IMPOSSIBLE. reviews/harris

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

REPLY TO BURGOS (2015)

Wilhelm Dilthey and Rudolf Carnap on the Foundation of the Humanities. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Course Areas. Faculty. Bucknell University 1. Professors: Richard Fleming, Sheila M. Lintott (Chair), Gary M.

Today we re gonna start a number of lectures on two thinkers who reject the idea

This authoritative translation by John Cottingham of the Meditations is taken from the much acclaimed three-volume Cambridge. Descartes: Meditations

Philosophy of Mind (104) Comprehensive Reading List Robert L. Frazier 27/11/2013

Philosophy Courses-1

R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press

Part One. On Being Alienated

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Lecture 8 Property Dualism. Frank Jackson Epiphenomenal Qualia and What Mary Didn t Know

Heterophenomenology: Heavy-handed sleight-of-hand

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia

Philosophy Courses-1

Two Dogmas of Reductionism: On the Irreducibility of Self-Consciousness and the Impossibility of Neurophilosophy

The Zimboic Hunch By Damir Mladić

On the Conceivability of Zombies

Philosophy (PHILOS) Courses. Philosophy (PHILOS) 1

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?


Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

At the Frontiers of Reality

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

2002. The Knowledge Argument Against Dualism, Theoria Vol. LXIII, pp The Knowledge Argument Against Dualism YUJIN NAGASAWA

A Unified Theory of Consciousness

Knowledge of the mind and knowledge of the brain

Chapter Six. Putnam's Anti-Realism

Introductory PHIL 100 Introduction to Philosophy 1. Logic A study of the principles of reasoning. PHIL 103 Logic 1 PHIL 201 Symbolic Logic 1

There are two explanatory gaps. Dr Tom McClelland University of Glasgow

David Chalmers on Mind and Consciousness Richard Brown Forthcoming in Andrew Bailey (ed) Philosophy of Mind: The Key Thinkers.

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica

Title II: The CAPE International Conferen Philosophy of Time )

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Magic, semantics, and Putnam s vat brains

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Philosophy. Philosophy 491. Department Offices. Faculty and Offices. Degree Awarded. Program Student Learning Outcomes

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Transcription:

The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates edited by Ned Block, Owen Flanagan and Güven Güzeldere Cambridge: Mass.: MIT Press 1997 pp.xxix + 843 Theories of the mind have been celebrating their new-found freedom to study consciousness. Earlier this century, when the methodology of psychology was still under the influence of behaviourism the view that psychology can only study observable behaviour the superstition and magic of consciousness (in John Watson s words) was not the proper object of scientific investigation. But now, there are respectable journals devoted to the study of consciousness, there are international interdisciplinary conferences on the subject, and some of the world s leading scientists notably Roger Penrose and Francis Crick have stepped in to have their say about the nature of consciousness. In Anglo-American (or analytic ) philosophy too, consciousness is one of the topics of the moment. For various different reasons, the first three-quarters of this century saw little attention paid to the investigation of consciousness in analytic philosophy. Frege s massively influential work in the philosophy of language, mathematics and logic was premised on the rejection of psychologism: the doctrine that logic and meaning should be explained in psychological terms. Frege showed no interest in questions of the nature of psychological reality, and thought it irrelevant to the philosophical investigations around which he built his system. In his Tractatus, Wittgenstein shared Frege s anti-psychologism. The logical positivists an influential group of philosophers working in Vienna in the 1920s and 30s rejected questions about consciousness for very different reasons. They were committed to verificationism, the doctrine that the only meaningful claims are those which can be scientifically tested. Questions about consciouness were considered beyond the reach of scientific investigation, and therefore meaningless. In so far as psychology could be a genuine science, it must be behaviouristic, since only public, observable behaviour could be the subject of precise testing. This behaviourism remained at the heart of W.V. Quine s influential work, along with an independent suspicion of the

coherence of philosophers talk of the mind as a kind of theatre, with its objects laid out in an inner realm for inspection by the inner eye of consciousness. We find a similar suspicion about the inner in the work of the postwar British philosophers of mind, Gilbert Ryle (The Concept of Mind) and Wittgenstein, in his later work. Ryle explicitly attacked something he called Descartes myth and Wittgenstein is sometimes taken as opposing the Cartesian picture of the mind. These targets have little in common with Descartes actual views, and the Cartesian view is often formulated either in a way that makes the view so massively implausible that it is hard to see why anyone would bother attacking it, or in a way that is insufficiently precise as to make it unworthy of further discussion. What opponents of Cartesianism want to attack is a collection of the following ideas: the mind is a thing, the mind is not necessarily linked to the body or to the environment outside the mind, the mind is an inner theatre, the mind knows its own contents with a special authority, by means of a mechanism of inner sense or introspection. Many anti-cartesians want to say instead that the mind is not a thing, but a kind of activity, it is essentially embodied and linked to its environment, and the contents of the mind are not known in a special or authoritative way. It is perhaps not surprising, then, that with all these different conceptual forces at work, it was hard to make a place for the study of consciousness within analytic philosophy. Things were different in the so-called Phenomenological tradition in philosophy, the tradition which (like the analytic tradition) has its roots in 19th century central Europe, but with the work of Husserl, Merleau-Ponty, Sartre and Heidegger, somehow ended up with a very different set of preoccupations from those of the analytic tradition. Phenomenology literally means the theory of phenomena or appearances, but in Husserl s hands it became the name for a specific approach to mental appearances, or how our minds strike us. To exaggerate somewhat, Husserl s view was that at the foundation of philosophy, consciousness was the only thing which could be studied. The world must be bracketed (i.e. no substantial assumptions must be made about the underlying nature of things) and the starting

point for philosophy was the precise characterisation of things as they appear before the mind an approach which contrasts strikingly with the logical positivists view that descriptions of consciouness should play no part in scientific philosophy at all. However, it was hard for analytic philosophy to resist the intuitive intellectual pull of the problems of consciousness, and whatever the merits of Ryle s and Wittgenstein s attacks on the Cartesian picture, it is plain that to believe in consciousness, and to believe it raises philosophical problems, is not the same as being a Cartesian in this sense. An influential essay which invigorated analytic discussions of consciousness was Thomas Nagel s What is it Like to be a Bat?, in which Nagel argued that consciousness is what makes the mind-body problem really intractable... without consciousness the mind-body problem would be much less interesting. With consciousness it seems hopeless. Since Nagel s article was published in 1974, analytic philosophers of mind have largely moved away from the behaviouristic positions of Ryle and Quine, and the problems of consciousness has become one of their main preoccupations. The Nature of Consciouness brings together fifty essays, mostly reprinted from other sources, and mostly by philosophers, on the various problems of consciousness. The book contains a long, highly readable introduction by Güven Güzeldere, and divides into ten sections, on such subjects as the metaphysics of consciousness, consciousness and content (ie mental representation) and consciousness and science. One hundred pages are devoted to some useful survey articles from the psychological and neuropsychological literature. Many of the articles will be familiar to those working in the field, but they are helpfully arranged here, with responses and counter-responses following on from key articles. Without doubt, this is the biggest, and best, anthology of writings on the philosophy of consciousness currently available. It will be an invaluable resource for scholars and research students. With any anthology, one will have reservations about what gets left out, and what gets put in. The writings of the Phenomenologists Brentano, Husserl, Merleau-

Ponty and Sartre are completely ignored, which is perhaps understandable given the volume s aim to be as up-to-date as possible. But it does leave the unfortunate impression that these philosophers were working in such a different tradition that we analytic philosophers do not need to consider them. In fact, such talk of traditions is normally rather vague, and has the effect of cutting off potentially fruitful lines of investigation. The truth of the matter is that contemporary philosophy of mind will find more to discuss in the work of Merleau-Ponty (for example) than it will in Wittgenstein s Tractatus. But one cannot expect everything from an anthology that attempts to cover issues in depth. A more just criticism of the volume concerns its conception of the problem-area, even within analytic philosophy. For one odd thing about this book is that its size is not an indication of the wide range of its contents. As the above quote from Nagel indicates, one major question about consciousness is part of the mindbody problem: how are mental and physical phenomena related? The difficulty consciousness poses is that it is hard to understand how a mere physical thing, the brain, can produce something which seems so unphysical as consciousness. How can the manifest existence of consciousness be reconciled with the physicalist view that everything is fundamentally constituted by purely physical matter? It is fair to say, I think, that about half of the essays in this book are concerned directly with this question, and many more are concerned with it indirectly. But there are other questions too. There are questions which do not directly address the issue of physicalism, but are concerned with how to properly characterise the phenomena of consciousness. For instance, there is little in this anthology about how perceptual experience should be understood (four papers), or bodily awareness (one paper) or conscious thought (two papers). Or if these subjects are discussed, the main interest is in their bearing on the question of phsyicalism. Yet unless the phenomena of consciousness themselves are investigated in more depth, it is hard to understand a pervasive feature of the debate about consciousness: how there seems to be deep and irreconcilable disagreement about the obvious.

To take one example: many philosophers think that the consciousness of a mental state should be understood in terms of the state s having certain qualitative properties, or qualia. Qualia are defined as those properties which give a mental state its characteristic feel. Given this, it is hard to see how there can be disagreement about the existence of qualia; as Ned Block once said, echoing a remark of Louis Armstrong s about jazz, if you have to ask what qualia are, you ain t never going to get to know. But there is such disagreement: a whole section of this anthology is devoted to the nature and existence of qualia. Some (like Daniel Dennett) deny the existence of qualia; others (like Gilbert Harman) think that what people call qualitative features are really representational features. How can we make sense of this disagreement? Given the innocuous way qualia were introduced into the debate, how can anyone deny that there are qualia? And how, in general, can there be disagreement about how conscious experience seems to us? It is curious how little illumination is shed on this question by the essays in this otherwise excellent anthology. Tim Crane Department of Philosophy University College London Gower Street London WC1E 6BT