URI: from the 2013 edition of the FCT Project PTDC/FIL-FIL/121209/2010. Edited by João Branquinho and Ricardo Santos

Similar documents
A presupposition is a precondition of a sentence such that the sentences cannot be

Mandy Simons Carnegie Mellon University June 2010

The projection problem of presuppositions

ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS

Presupposition and Accommodation: Understanding the Stalnakerian picture *

Lexical Alternatives as a Source of Pragmatic Presuppositions

Presupposition Projection and At-issueness

Towards a Solution to the Proviso Problem

Presupposition and Rules for Anaphora

Pragmatic Presupposition

On Conceivability and Existence in Linguistic Interpretation

Satisfied or Exhaustified An Ambiguity Account of the Proviso Problem

Lecture 9: Presuppositions

Experimental Investigations of the Typology of Presupposition Triggers

The main plank of Professor Simons thoroughly pragmatic account of presupposition

Class #9 - The Attributive/Referential Distinction

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

10. Presuppositions Introduction The Phenomenon Tests for presuppositions

Presupposition: An (un)common attitude?

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

Topics in Linguistic Theory: Propositional Attitudes

Backgrounding and accommodation of presuppositions: an experimental approach

Two restrictions on possible connectives

Lecture 1. Yasutada Sudo 12 January 2018

Denying the antecedent and conditional perfection again

(Draft, forthcoming in Organon F)

Theories of propositions

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

91. Presupposition. Denial, projection, cancellation, satisfaction, accommodation: the five stages of presupposition theory.

Presuppositions (Ch. 6, pp )

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Russell: On Denoting

Presupposition projection: Global accommodation, local accommodation, and scope ambiguities

A Linguistic Interlude

Assertion and Inference

Factivity and Presuppositions David Schueler University of Minnesota, Twin Cities LSA Annual Meeting 2013

Lying and Asserting. Andreas Stokke CSMN, University of Oslo. March forthcoming in the Journal of Philosophy

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Andrei Marmor: Social Conventions

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Philosophy 1760 Philosophy of Language

COMPARING CONTEXTUALISM AND INVARIANTISM ON THE CORRECTNESS OF CONTEXTUALIST INTUITIONS. Jessica BROWN University of Bristol

Week Nine: Pragmatics, Metaphysics and Possibility

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

Presupposition: Introduction

In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a

ZHANG Yan-qiu, CHEN Qiang. Changchun University, Changchun, China

What is Presupposition Accommodation, Again?

REVISTA DE LIBROS. Assertion. New Philosophical Essays, by JESSICA BROWN and HERMAN CAPPELEN (EDS.), OXFORD, OXFORD UP 2011, 320 pp.

Comments on "Lying with Conditionals" by Roy Sorensen

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Horwich and the Liar

CLASSIC INVARIANTISM, RELEVANCE, AND WARRANTED ASSERTABILITY MANŒUVERS

A set of puzzles about names in belief reports

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. P. F. Strawson: On Referring

Explicit performatives revisited

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 1)

Interactions with Context. Eric Swanson. B.A., Bard College (1997) M.A., Yale University (1999) M.A., Tufts University (2001)

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Philosophical reflection about what we call knowledge has a natural starting point in the

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Expressing Credences. Daniel Rothschild All Souls College, Oxford OX1 4AL

John Mikhail on Moral Intuitions

On the Aristotelian Square of Opposition

Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Content and Modality: Themes from the Philosophy of Robert Stalnaker, edited by

Introduction: Belief vs Degrees of Belief

Manuel García-Carpintero. Assertions in Fictions: An Indirect Speech Act Account

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Counterfactuals and Causation: Transitivity

Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Terence CUNEO, The Normative Web. An Argument for Moral Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008, 263 pp., 46.99, ISBN

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

Promises and Threats with Conditionals and Disjunctions

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp.

Review of Peter Hanks Propositional Content Indrek Reiland

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony

The Unexpected Projection of Some Presupposition Triggers

Haberdashers Aske s Boys School

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

Qualitative versus Quantitative Notions of Speaker and Hearer Belief: Implementation and Theoretical Extensions

Pragmatic accommodation

Conference on the Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, PUCRS, Porto Alegre (Brazil), June

& TORRE, Stephan (eds.). About Oneself: De Se Thought and Communication. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016, 368pp., ISBN

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

Transcription:

pdf version of the entry presupposition URI: from the 2013 edition of the online Companion to problems of analytic philosophy 2012-2015 FCT Project PTDC/FIL-FIL/121209/2010 Edited by João Branquinho and Ricardo Santos ISBN: 978-989-8553-22-5 Copyright 2013 by the publisher Centro de Filosofia da Universidade de Lisboa Alameda da Universidade, Campo Grande, 1600-214 Lisboa Presupposition Copyright 2013 by the author All rights reserved

Presupposition Our semantic competence underwrites the validity of inferences such as the following, for both (1) and (2): (1) John infected the PC. (2) It was John who infected the PC... Someone infected the PC However, there is a difference between the syntactic constructions in (1) and (2); unlike the less marked way of expressing what we perceive as the same content in (1), the cleft construction in (2) also validates (at least, in default contexts) the same inference when placed under different embeddings, such as negation (3), conditionals (4), modals (5), and still others; presuppositions are said to be thereby projected, i.e., inherited by the embedding constructions: (3) It was not John who infected the PC. (4) If it was John who infected the PC, the Mac is also infected. (5) It may have been John who infected the PC... Someone infected the PC Other presuppositional constructions exhibit this behavior; consider the case of definite descriptions: (6) The Sants station newsstand sells The Guardian. (7) The Sants station newsstand does not sell The Guardian. (8) If the Sants station newsstand sells The Guardian, we will buy it there. (9) The Sants station newsstand may sell The Guardian... There is exactly one Sants station newsstand. This projection behavior invites the traditional characterization of presuppositions as conditions for the truth and the falsity of the sentences/propositions including them. But, as the discussion in the past decades has shown, this cannot be a correct initial characterization (even if something along such lines can be ultimately defended on a First published in 2013

2 more complex theoretical basis). In the first place, Strawson pointed out cases of what Yablo (2006) calls noncatastrophic presupposition failure. For instance, if as a matter of fact there are two newsstands in Sants station, but both of them sell The Guardian, many people feel that (6) is nonetheless true; on the other hand, if there is no newsstand there, many people feel that (10) is false, not just neither true nor false: (10) I waited for you for two hours at the Sants station newsstand. Secondly, presuppositions are not projected in some cases; hence, they are not there globally, but they are still there, somehow, locally. They cannot be in those cases conditions for the truth and falsity of the whole claim, and thus the intuitive test we are considering does not witness their nonetheless local presence: (11) If someone infected the PC, it was John who did it. (12) Someone infected the PC, and it was John who did it. Finally, conventional implicatures, which intuitively differ from presuppositions, share their projection behavior with presuppositions in the embeddings we have considered; following Potts (2007), I use non-restrictive wh-clauses as illustrative examples: (13) John, who infected the PC, teaches in Oxford. (14) It is not the case that John, who infected the PC, teaches in Oxford. (15) If John, who infected the PC, teaches in Oxford, he will attend the conference. (16) It may be the case that John, who infected the PC, teaches in Oxford... John infected the PC Geurts (1999, 6-8) uses the projection behavior illustrated by (3)- (5) and (11)-(12) as an intuitive test to characterize presuppositions; even though he acknowledges that the test is defeasible, I think the fact that conventional implicatures also pass it shows that it is not

Presupposition 3 even a good intuitive characterization, aside from its defeasibility. Von Fintel (2004, 271) proposes an alternative hey, wait a minute test to distinguish presupposition and assertion, which, even if also far from perfect, appears to be better. Consider the following dialogues, with # being an indication of conversational impropriety or infelicity: (17) It was not John who infected the PC. (18) # Hey, wait a minute, I had no idea that John did not infect the PC. (19) Hey, wait a minute, I had no idea that someone infected the PC. (20) It is not the case that John, who infected the PC, teaches in Oxford. (21) # Hey, wait a minute, I had no idea that John does not teach in Oxford. (22) # Hey, wait a minute, I had no idea that John infected the PC. Intuitively, this is why von Fintel s test provides a better initial characterization of presuppositions. As opposed both to asserted contents and conventional implicatures, presuppositions are presented as information already in possession of the conversational participants. Asserted content is presented as new information for the audience, and the same applies to conventionally implicated contents, even if the latter are somehow backgrounded relative to the main assertion. This is why targeting the asserted or conventionally implicated content with the hey, wait a minute objection does not feel right, whereas objecting in that way to the presupposed content does. In other words, presuppositions are presented as part of the common ground, while asserted and conventionally implicated contents are presented as new information. Von Fintel s test, whether or not it is ultimately acceptable, is a useful, if rather blunt, instrument for isolating the phenomenon of presupposition. It shows that the skepticism expressed by writers such as Böer & Lycan (1976) and Levinson (1983) who argue for a form of the eliminativist view about presuppositions to be described below in part on the basis of the alleged miscellaneous character of 2013 Edition

4 the phenomenon is prima facie unreasonable. The intuitions unveiled by the Hey, wait a minute test are quite robust, and robustly related to grammatical constructions like those we have used for illustration, as can be established by considering variations on them, or others in the list given by Levinson (1983, 181-5). The robustness of the intuitions suggests at least prima facie that presupposing is a sufficiently natural kind, amenable to a precise characterization. A philosophically adequate definition, if it is good, should elaborate on the preceding intuitive explanation for why von Fintel s characterization succeeds where the others previously considered fail. In a series of papers, Stalnaker (1973, 1974, 2002) has provided an influential account of the phenomenon of presupposition. The account has been slightly modified along the way; here we will just present the core aspects Simons (2003) provides a helpful sympathetic discussion of the evolving details. Stalnaker s proposal is in the spirit of Grice s account of phenomena such as conversational implicature in particular and meaning in general: it purports to explain those phenomena as a specific form of rational behavior involving communicative intentions, avoiding irreducibly social notions such as conventions or (socially construed) norms. Stalnaker bases his analysis on a notion of speaker presupposition, which he then reluctantly (for reasons to be indicated presently) uses to provide a notion of sentence presupposition. Speaker presupposition is explained in terms of common beliefs about what is accepted by the conversational partners; and common belief follows the pattern of Schiffer s and Lewis proposals about it and about common knowledge: p is common belief in a given group G just in case (almost) everybody in G believes p, believes that (almost) everybody in G believes p, and so on. Acceptance is in its turn defined by Stalnaker (2002, 716) as a category of mental states which includes belief, but also some attitudes (presumption, assumption, acceptance for the purposes of argument or enquiry) that contrast with belief and with each other. To accept a proposition is to treat it as true for some reason. The need to invoke acceptance in the definition derives from many cases in which, intuitively and according to our initial characterization above, p is presupposed while not commonly believed. Thus, consider Donnellan s example: the secret conspirator asks the usurper s minions, Is the king in his countinghouse? Here the speaker does not believe

Presupposition 5 that the intended referent is king, nor perhaps that there is a king, and hence does not believe that these propositions are commonly believed in the context, but nonetheless it is presupposed that the referent is king and that there is exactly one king. (This characterization of what is presupposed in this case, involving a referential use of the description, is along the lines of García-Carpintero s (2000) identification presuppositions for cases of reference.) Nonetheless, acceptance cannot be invoked all the way down; the account is given in terms of common belief about what is commonly accepted, because only the more specific category of belief has the required explanatory links with behavior. This is thus the final account. We first define a proposition p to be in the common ground in a group G CGG(p) and then we define speaker presupposition: (CGG) CGG(p) if and only if it is common belief in G that everybody accepts p. (SpP) Speaker S presupposes p (relative to G) if and only if S believes that CGG(p). Stalnaker (1973, 451; 1974, 50) then defines a notion of sentence presupposition in terms of this: (SnP) Sentence S presupposes p if and only if the use of S would for some reason be inappropriate unless the speaker presupposed p. Stalnaker (1978) complements this analysis of presuppositions with an equally deservedly influential analysis of assertion, on which an assertion is a proposal to update the common ground, which, if accepted, is added to it (i.e., it then becomes common belief that every participant accepts it); and he combined the two accounts to suggest intuitively plausible explanations of some aspects of the projecting behavior we presented in the previous section. This (together with the related independent work of Lauri Karttunen) was the origin of the new important tradition of Dynamic Semantics (DS), developed for instance in Heim (1983), Beaver (2001) or von Fintel (2004). This tradition has the resources to provide the philosophical account requested before. Unlike the traditional account of presuppositions as conditions on the truth and falsity of claims, it can explain the 2013 Edition

6 selective projection behavior we have seen to be characteristic of presuppositions, and it can distinguish them from conventional implicatures, accounting also for the adequacy of von Fintel s test; last but not least, when properly elaborated it also has the resources to explain the phenomenon of noncatastrophic presupposition failure (cf. von Fintel 2004). Geurts (1999, 17), however, is right in pointing out the important conceptual differences between the DS tradition and Stalnaker s viewpoint. Renouncing Stalnaker s Gricean reductive aims, in this tradition presuppositions are taken to be, both with respect to their triggering and projecting behavior, a constitutive feature of the semantics of natural language expressions. Geurts (1999, 14) distances himself from DS, on account of its betrayal of Stalnaker s truly pragmatic stance, and, like Stalnaker, he helps himself to a notion of expression-presupposition, defined in normative terms on the basis of the pragmatic notion of speaker presupposition. Unlike Stalnaker, however, Geurts also appeals to unexplained normative notions in characterizing speaker presupposition: a speaker who presupposes something incurs a commitment regardless whether he really believes what he presupposes (ibid., 11). What is exactly the difference between Stalnaker s pragmatic view and the semantic one provided by DS? As Stalnaker (1974, 61) notes, there are two contrasting ways of understanding the semantic/pragmatics divide. In the truth-conditional account, semantics deals with the truth-conditions of sentences, and the truth-conditional import of expressions. It is in this sense that presuppositions understood as conditions for the truth and falsity of sentences are said to be a semantic phenomenon. An important strand of Stalnaker s early defense of a pragmatic account, as he notes, is to oppose such a semantic conception; for reasons mentioned before (noncatastrophic failure, projection behavior), this opposition was well taken. However, the truth-conditional way of tracing the semantic/ pragmatic divide is not theoretically useful, because it displaces from the purview of semantics facts that should be studied together with those it keeps there (cf. García-Carpintero (2001, 2004, 2006)): among others, semantically driven context-dependence, semantics for conventional indicators of speech acts such as the interrogative and imperative mood, and perhaps in addition some presuppositional

Presupposition 7 facts. On a different constitutive understanding of the divide, linguistics in general purports to theoretically characterize the constitutive facts about natural languages (in an indirect way of putting this, the linguistic competence of speakers), and semantics is the part thereof dealing with meaning facts constitutive of natural languages. This is the conception of the divide that Grice (1975) had in mind when he tried to account for the apparent asymmetric, non-truthconditional behavior of conjunction or referential uses of descriptions as generalized conversational implicatures, i.e., as pragmatic features. Although his views here are complex (cf. Bezuidenhout (2010)), this also appears to be Grice s (1981) own view on the presuppositional phenomena discussed here. After noting the two different interpretations of the divide, Stalnaker (1974, 61) points out that he is mainly arguing for a pragmatic account of presuppositions only on the irst understanding, but notes also that his arguments have repercussions for the other: while he is open to the possibility that in some cases one may just have to write presupposition constraints into the dictionary entry for a particular word (ibid.), he conjectures that one can explain many presupposition constraints in terms of general conversational rules without building anything about presuppositions into the meanings of particular words or constructions (ibid.). In fact, although as seen above Stalnaker (reluctantly, as it was said) introduced a notion of sentence presupposition (SnP) in his early writings, and still assumes it in recent work, he repeatedly expresses qualms about it, because of the unexplained appeal to the normative notion of inappropriateness, and because it suggests the existence of a mysterious relation X between sentences and propositions worthy of analysis, while we don t need the mysterious relation X to describe the phenomena, and it does not make any contribution to explaining them (2002, 712-3). We find claims along these lines already in his earlier writings: the facts can be stated and explained directly in terms of the underlying notion of speaker presupposition, and without introducing an intermediate notion of presupposition as a relation holding between sentences (or statements) and propositions (1974, 50). We may say that Gricean generalized conversational implicature accounts of referential uses of descriptions (such as the one in Kripke (1977)) or manifest non-truth-conditional 2013 Edition

8 asymmetries in conjunctions are not simply reductionist, but in fact eliminativist vis-à-vis semantic accounts of those phenomena, on the second understanding of the divide: although it is acknowledged that definite descriptions and conjunctions are in fact commonly used in those ways, it is claimed that a semantic theory should not encompass them. This is the way the label (Gricean) eliminativist view of the phenomenon here studied, presupposition, is understood; it applies to writers such as Böer & Lycan (1976), Levinson (1983) and, as indicated, Grice (1981). The proposal is not to deny the phenomenon altogether, but only the need for a semantic account for it. Presuppositions do exist, but they can be accounted for without including them in our theoretical constitutive characterization of natural languages. The Stalnakerian view of presuppositions, in contrast with the DS view, is ultimately eliminativist in this sense. This stance was present from the beginning, but the emphasis is stronger in more recent work: [O]ne might define a notion of sentence presupposition in terms of speaker presupposition, but [ ] the attempt to do so would be a distraction, and would not yield any theoretically useful notion (2010, 150). In recent work, Philippe Schlenker (2008, 2009) has advanced several new theoretical proposals, which he advertises as Stalnakerian alternatives to DS: both regarding the Projection and the Triggering issues, Schlenker contends that his proposals are pragmatic, not semantic. Schlenker, however, is not clear whether he has in mind the truth-conditional or the constitutive view of the semantic/pragmatic divide, but he seems to intend the first one. His Local Contexts proposal (Schlenker 2009) which offers interesting solutions to well known problems of DS theories with quantified or disjunctive sentences assumes a bivalent, non-dynamic semantics for connectives and quantifiers, and thus counts as non-semantic on the truth-conditional view. However, exactly as in DS, the account straightforwardly assumes that presuppositions are calculated in a compositional way locally, i.e., with respect to phrases that are proper parts of the whole sentence. This is probably why Stalnaker (2010, 149-151) distances himself from Schlenker s proposals.

Presupposition 9 While it seems clear that Stalnaker is right that presupposition is a pragmatic, not semantic phenomenon in the truth-conditional sense, ultimately having to do with the propositional attitudes of speakers, there are some good reasons to prefer the DS semantic account (in the constitutive sense) to his Gricean eliminativist stance, and hence to reject that presupposing is a pragmatic phenomenon also on the constitutive account. García-Carpintero (2013) mentions the fact of informative presuppositions in this regard. As Stalnaker (1973, 449; 1974, 51-2) noted in his early writings, it is common for speakers to communicate a piece of information by uttering a sentence that presupposes it. These are examples from Abbott (2008, 531, cf. sources there): (23) The leaders of the militant homophile movement in America generally have been young people. It was they who fought back during a violent police raid on a Greenwich Village bar in 1969, an incident from which many gays date the birth of the modern crusade for homosexual rights. (24) If you re going into the bedroom, would you mind bringing back the big bag of potato chips that I left on the bed? Speakers who utter sentences (23) and (24) do not typically assume their presuppositions that some people fought back during a violent police raid on a Greenwich Village bar in 1969, and that there is exactly one big bag of potato chips that the speaker left on the bed, respectively to be in the common ground. To utter sentences with those presuppositions is just an expedient resource for them to inform their audiences of such contents, plus the assertion, woven together in a terse package. That the contents are nonetheless presupposed is shown by the Hey, wait a minute! test even though a Hey, wait a minute! objection in these cases might feel, even if literally adequate, pedantic, smug, or otherwise uncooperative just like it feels to fail to grasp a manifest implicature. The examples above help us to appreciate the ordinariness of the phenomenon, but it is better to have a simpler case for discussion (Stalnaker (1974, 52, n. 2) attributes the following example to Jerry Sadock.). We assume that the speaker utters (25) in the knowledge that his audience knows nothing about his family: 2013 Edition

10 (25) I cannot come to the meeting I have to pick up my sister at the airport. The Hey, wait a minute! test shows again the presence of the presupposition that the speaker has a sister (in addition to others, such that there is a salient airport, and so on, but we will focus on this), even if, as before, precisely to the extent that speakers are entitled to assume that the presupposition will be accommodated without further ado by ordinary audiences, it would feel awkward if somebody objected to it with the Hey, wait a minute complaint. (It would feel much better if the speaker had made the utterance with my lover replacing my sister.) These are cases where speakers exploit what Lewis (1979) called the Rule of Accommodation for Presuppositions, which he characterized thus: (RA) If at time t something is said that requires presupposition p to be acceptable, and if p is not presupposed just before t, then ceteris paribus and within certain limits presupposition p comes into existence at t. Cases in which a Hey, wait a minute complaint is actually made, which the my lover variant illustrates, explain the need for the hedge: the hearer is not always prepared to accommodate. Now, the initial problem for Stalnaker s account that cases of informative presupposition pose is as follows: (i) as he (1973, 449; 1974, 51-2) acknowledges, a presupposition is present; however, (at first sight at least) (ii) the speaker does not presuppose it, on Stalnaker s characterization, because he does not believe that his audience accepts it; while (iii) the fact that cases like these are commonplace suggests that there is nothing inappropriate in their use, and certainly nothing feels inappropriate in them. Although he has been aware of the issue all along, only in recent work has Stalnaker (2002, 708-9) confronts it squarely, arguing that in fact these cases are not at odds with his account, because only at irst sight is (ii) correct: when the proper time at which the presupposition is to be accepted is considered, it turns out that the speaker is presupposing the relevant content. Although writers sympathetic to Stalnaker s pragmatic account such as Simons (2003, 267-8) and Schlenker (ms) endorse Stalnaker s suggestion to account for infor-

Presupposition 11 mative presuppositions in an eliminativist setting, von Fintel (2008), García-Carpintero (2013), Gauker (2008, 185) and Simons (ms.) have manifested skepticism about it. References LOGOS-Departament de Lògica, Història i Filosofia de la Ciència Universitat de Barcelona m.garciacarpintero@ub.edu Abbott, B. 2008. Presuppositions and Common Ground. Linguistics and Philosophy 21: 523-538. Beaver, D. 2001. Presupposition and Assertion in Dynamic Semantics. Stanford: CSLI. Bezuidenhout, Anne. 2010. Grice on Presupposition. In Meaning and Analysis: New Analyses on Grice. Edited by K. Petrus. Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan. Boër, S.E. and Lycan, W. 1976. The Myth of Semantic Presupposition. Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana Linguistics Club. Chierchia, G. and McConnell-Ginet, S. 1990. Meaning and Grammar. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. von Fintel, K. 2004. Would You Believe It? The King of France is Back! (Presuppositions and Truth-Value Intuitions). In Descriptions and Beyond. Edited by M. Reimer and A. Bezuidenhout. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 269-296. von Fintel, K. 2008. What Is Presupposition Accommodation, Again? Philosophical Perspectives 22: 137-170. García-Carpintero, M. 2000. A Presuppositional Account of Reference-Fixing. Journal of Philosophy XCVII (3): 109-147. García-Carpintero, M. 2001. Gricean Rational Reconstructions and the Semantics/Pragmatics Distinction. Synthese 128: 93-131. García-Carpintero, M. 2004. Assertion and the Semantics of Force-Markers. In The Semantics/Pragmatics Distinction. CSLI Lecture Notes. Edited by C. Bianchi. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, pp. 133-166. García-Carpintero, M. 2006. Recanati on the Semantics/Pragmatics Distinction. Crítica 38: 35-68. García-Carpintero, M. 2013. Insinuating Information and Accommodating Presupposition. In Brevity. Edited by L. Goldstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gauker, Christopher. 2008. Against Accommodation. Philosophical perspectives 22: 171-205. Geurts, B. 1999. Presuppositions and Pronouns. Amsterdam: Elsevier. Grice, H.P. 1975. Logic and Conversation. In Syntax and Semantics, vol. 3. Edited by P. Cole and J. Morgan. New York: Academic Press. Also in Grice, H.P. Studies in The Ways of Words. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, pp. 22-40. Grice, H.P. 1981. Presupposition and Conversational Implicature. In Radical Pragmatics. Edited by P. Cole. New York: Academic Press. Also in Grice, H.P. Studies in The Ways of Words. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, pp. 269-282. 2013 Edition

12 Heim, I. 1983. On the projection problem for presuppositions. Proceedings of the West Coast Conference on Linguistics 2: 114-126. Karttunen, L. 1974. Presuppositions and Linguistic Contexts. Theoretical Linguistics 1: 181-194. Also in Pragmatics. Edited by S. Davis. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 406-416, to which I refer. Kripke, Saul. 1977. Speaker s Reference and Semantic Reference. In Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language. Edited by P. French, T. Uehling and H. Wettstein. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 255-276. Levinson, S. 1983. Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lewis, D. 1979. Scorekeeping in a Language Game. Journal of Philosophical Logic (8): 339-59. Also in D. Lewis, Philosophical Papers, vol. 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983, pp. 233-249, to which I refer. Potts, C. 2007. Conventional Implicature: A Distinguished Class of Meanings. In Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Interfaces. Edited by G. Ramchand and C. Reiss. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 475-501. Schlenker, P. 2008. Be Articulate: A pragmatic theory of presupposition projection. Theoretical Linguistics 34: 157-212. Schlenker, P. 2009. Local Contexts. Semantics & Pragmatics 2: 1-78. Schlenker, P. 2010. Local Contexts and Local Meanings. Philosophical Studies 151: 115-142. Schlenker, P. Ms. May 2011. Maximize Presupposition and Gricean Reasoning. <https://files.nyu.edu/pds4/public/>, accessed on August 2nd, 2011. Simons, M. 2001. On the conversational basis of some presuppositions. In Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory 11. Edited by R. Hasting, B. Jackson and Z. Zvolensky. Ithaca, New York: CLC Publications, Cornell University, pp. 431-448. Simons, M. 2003. Presupposition and Accommodation: Understanding the Stalnakerian Picture. Philosophical Studies 112: 251 278. Simons, M. Ms. Presupposition without Common Ground. <http://www.hss. cmu.edu/philosophy/faculty-simons.php>, accessed on August 6th, 2010. Stalnaker, R. 1973. Presuppositions. Journal of Philosophical Logic 2: 447-457. Stalnaker, R. 1974. Pragmatic Presuppositions. In Semantics and Philosophy. Edited by M.K. Munitz and P.K. Unger. New York: New York University Press. Also in R. Stalnaker. Context and Content. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999, pp. 47-62, to which I refer. Stalnaker, R. 1978. Assertion. In Syntax and Semantics 9. Edited by P. Cole. New York: Academic Press, pp. 315-332. Also in R. Stalnaker. Context and Content. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999, pp. 78-95, to which I refer. Stalnaker, R. 2002. Common Ground. Linguistics and Philosophy 25: 701-721. Stalnaker, R. 2010. Responses to Stanley and Schlenker. Philosophical Studies 151: 143-157. Yablo, S. 2006. Non-catastrophic presupposition failure. In Content and Modality: Themes from the Philosophy of Robert Stalnaker. Edited by J. Thomson and A. Byrne. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 164-190.