Similar documents

Commentary on Professor Tweyman's 'Hume on Evil' Pheroze S. Wadia Hume Studies Volume XIII, Number 1 (April, 1987)




Inconsistency within a Reconciling Project Antony Flew Hume Studies Volume IV, Number 1 (April, 1978), 1-6.

David O Connor. Hume on Religion H. O. Mounce Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 2 (November, 2002)

Argument from Design. Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. David Hume


A Hobbist Tory: Johnson on Hume Paul Russell Hume Studies Volume XVI, Number 1 (April, 1990)

A DILEMMA FOR JAMES S JUSTIFICATION OF FAITH SCOTT F. AIKIN

Questioning the Aprobability of van Inwagen s Defense

MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR. Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the


The unity of the normative

Philosophical Review.

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.


Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

Hume Studies Volume XXVIX, Number 2 (November, 2003)

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Philosophy 428M Topics in the History of Philosophy: Hume MW 2-3:15 Skinner Syllabus

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Anne Jaap Jacobson, ed. Feminist Interpretations of David Hume Michelle Mason Hume Studies Volume XXVII, Number 1 (April, 2001)

An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

The midterm will be held in class two weeks from today, on Thursday, October 9. It will be worth 20% of your grade.

Evidential arguments from evil

The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 83, No. 5. (May, 1986), pp

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

Hume on Promises and Their Obligation. Hume Studies Volume XIV, Number 1 (April, 1988) Antony E. Pitson

Is God Good By Definition?

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference?

By J. Alexander Rutherford. Part one sets the roles, relationships, and begins the discussion with a consideration

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY


CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

Kelly James Clark and Raymond VanArragon (eds.), Evidence and Religious Belief, Oxford UP, 2011, 240pp., $65.00 (hbk), ISBN

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

Phenomenal Consciousness and Intentionality<1>

[JGRChJ 9 (2013) R28-R32] BOOK REVIEW

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

David E. Alexander and Daniel Johnson, eds. Calvinism and the Problem of Evil.

The problem of God s cognoscibility in David Hume

Bayesianism, Analogy, and Hume s Dialogues concerning Natural Religion Sally Ferguson Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

Belief and Rationality

MEGILL S MULTIVERSE META-ARGUMENT. Klaas J. Kraay Ryerson University

Ethics and Religion. Cambridge University Press Ethics and Religion Harry J. Gensler Frontmatter More information

Scanlon on Double Effect

ONCE MORE INTO THE LABYRINTH: KAIL S REALIST EXPLANATION

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism

ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY

Certainty, Necessity, and Knowledge in Hume s Treatise

Hume Studies Volume XXIV, Number 1 (April, 1998)

There is a God. A Much-Maligned Convert

Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

The belief in the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent and benevolent God is inconsistent with the existence of human suffering. Discuss.

Paley s Inductive Inference to Design

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

A Rejection of Skeptical Theism

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Table of x III. Modern Modal Ontological Arguments Norman Malcolm s argument Charles Hartshorne s argument A fly in the ointment? 86

Gandalf s Solution to the Newcomb Problem. Ralph Wedgwood

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

A conversation about balance: key principles

An Early Account of David Hume. Hume Studies Volume 1, Issue 2 (November, 1975), J.C. Hilson

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

The Nature Of The Gods (Oxford World's Classics) PDF

Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and. Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xvi, 286.

What God Could Have Made

AP European History Document-Based Question #1 Due Tuesday, December 6, points Prompt In The Heavenly City of the Eighteenth-Century

Review of Thomas C. Brickhouse and Nicholas D. Smith, "Socratic Moral Psychology"

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

ISSA Proceedings 1998 Wilson On Circular Arguments

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

Philosophical Review.

Review of Erik J. Wielenberg: Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism

FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Plantinga, Van Till, and McMullin. 1. What is the conflict Plantinga proposes to address in this essay? ( )

F. Rachel Magdalene Universität Leipzig Leipzig, Germany

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Transcription:

Thomas Holden. Spectres of False Divinity: Hume s Moral Atheism. David O Connor Hume Studies Volume 36, Number 2 (2010), 236-239. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.humesociety.org/hs/about/terms.html. HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the HUME STUDIES archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Each copy of any part of a HUME STUDIES transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. For more information on HUME STUDIES contact humestudies-info@humesociety.org http://www.humesociety.org/hs/

Hume Studies Volume 36, Number 2, 2010, pp. 236 239 Thomas Holden. Spectres of False Divinity: Hume s Moral Atheism. New York: Oxford University Press, 2010. Pp. xvi + 246. ISBN 978-0-19-957994-5, Cloth, $50.00. The main thesis developed and defended in this superb book is that Hume implicitly denies the existence... of a morally assessable god (8), not just the existence of an overall morally praiseworthy god (8). Holden characterizes these as strong and weak moral atheism, respectively (7 9). While the idea of Hume as a moral atheist is not new, Holden s case for that proposition makes two new and important contributions to the discussion of the issue. The first is his detailed piecing-together of points made by Hume in various writings into two arguments for strong moral atheism and his attribution of the arguments to Hume. He calls them the argument from sentimentalism and the argument from motivation, respectively. Both arguments are based in Hume s moral psychology, but there is no text in which he either endorses them or even sets them forth as such. In light of this lack of direct textual support, Holden s painstaking reconstruction of the two arguments and his convincing case for seeing both of them as Hume s arguments, thus for seeing Hume as a strong moral atheist, are important contributions to Hume studies. The book s second new (albeit with a qualification mentioned below) and important contribution to discussions of moral atheism in Hume is Holden s point that these are Hume s only arguments for moral atheism, strong or weak. This puts him at odds with commentators who maintain that either the author of sin argument in Section 8 of the first Enquiry or the evidential argument from evil (a.k.a. the argument to divine indifference) in Part XI of the Dialogues supports attributing moral atheism to Hume. Holden begins his case with a detailed description of moral atheism and a convincing rebuttal of an anticipated objection based on the aforementioned lack of direct textual support (chapter 1). But a potentially more damaging objection awaits. It is that moral atheism, being a theory about the essential nature of the deity, is effectively a form of natural theology and, as such, incompatible with Hume s skepticism. The key to Holden s response to this objection is his distinction between two ways of inferring things about the deity, in effect, two kinds of natural theology, core and liminal natural theology, respectively. The former is traditional natural theology and includes Cleanthes s version in the Dialogues. The latter, by contrast, contains no theorizing or inference-making about the nature of the first cause as such. This is because it is restricted to inferring characteristics that would be attributable to any unknown entity whatsoever (29). Parenthetically, we find liminal natural theology in Cleanthes too, when, in Part IV of the Dialogues, he argues that the deity could not be both a mind and immutable, since Hume Studies

Book Reviews 237 nothing could. Such a conclusion, then, although applicable to the first cause, is not about it specifically. Holden s point is that core natural theology, by claiming to achieve insight into the distinctive or species-specific intrinsic character (116) of the first cause, is indeed at odds with Hume s skeptical principles but that liminal natural theology is not (chapter 2). Pre-emptive big-picture objections (14) met, Holden sets about developing the positive core of his case, the detailed working-out of both the argument from sentimentalism (chapters 3 and 4) and the argument from motivation (chapter 5) and their attribution to Hume. This done, he turns to examining two well-known arguments for weak moral atheism that have often been attributed to [Hume] (210) the evidential argument from evil and the author of sin argument and rejects them. Discussing the three forms of the argument from evil that we find in Hume, the logical, inference, and evidential forms, Holden maintains that Hume does not endorse the evidential form of the argument, so his discussion of it does not reflect an endorsement of moral atheism (chapter 6). Insofar as the author of sin argument is concerned, Holden maintains both that it is not endorsed by Hume and that it does not support moral atheism anyway (chapter 7). Holden concludes his investigation by briefly drawing together the various facets of his case for moral atheism in Hume (Conclusion). Rounding out the book, there is a useful bibliography and an index. As noted, the core of Holden s case is the conjunction of the argument from sentimentalism and the argument from motivation. Very briefly, the key to the former and to its attribution to Hume is the conjunction of two points: first, his claim, in a letter of June 30, 1743 to William Mure, that the deity is not the natural object of any Passion or Affection (52 53); and, second, as Holden states Hume s point, that moral concepts are determined by the characteristic sentiments of approval and disapproval that humans naturally feel toward different sorts of character trait (49). The key to the argument from motivation and to its attribution to Hume is his idea, again in Holden s words, that morality... is an anthropological phenomenon root and branch, and quite unintelligible outside of... [the] human context (120). An embryonic form of the latter argument was set out as Hume s argument by Bernard Williams in Hume on Religion (David Hume: A Symposium, ed. D. F. Pears [London: Macmillan, 1963], 77 88), as Holden notes, but the developed version in this book is the benchmark for future discussions. Holden s reconstruction of the two arguments is a first-rate piece of scholarship and his case for their being Hume s arguments is convincing. The book has two interesting sub-plots: Holden s previously noted opposition to the reasons that other scholars have given for reading Hume as a moral atheist and his argument that Hume thinks the logical form of the argument from evil is successful (150 57). For reasons of space, let us look only at one part of one sub-plot, Holden s dismissal of the evidential argument from evil as a basis for attributing Volume 36, Number 2, 2010

238 Book Reviews moral atheism to Hume. Holden notes that the argument appears to run afoul of Hume s skepticism (170, 173) and cannot be saved as a form of liminal natural theology (170 71), that it is vulnerable to some of the very objections that Philo himself brings against the design argument (171), thereby calling Philo s consistency into question, and that, for good measure, it is an embarrassingly weak argument (175). Holden s conclusion is that, at a minimum, any attribution of the argument to Hume will need to come up with a plausible distancing mechanism (175) to cope with the first three of those points. He himself endorses Klaas Kraay s reading of the argument ( Philo s Argument for Divine Amorality Reconsidered, Hume Studies 29 [2003]: 283 304) as a parody of core natural theology in general and of Cleanthes s version in particular (175). (Earlier, noting Holden s point that the arguments from sentimentalism and motivation, respectively, are Hume s only arguments for moral atheism, I called the point new, but with a qualification. The qualification is Holden s endorsement of Kraay s parody interpretation.) Very briefly, here are three points for discussion. First, the pivotal idea in the argument from sentimentalism is that the deity is not a natural object of the passions, understood in the strong sense that normal humans are constitutionally incapable of moral sentiments toward the first cause (109). As a possible tactic in defense of this point, Holden suggests that the first cause is not picturable or imaginable (111). Under various God-of-the-philosophers descriptions, for instance, the original cause, this seems plausible enough. But it seems less plausible under descriptions of the deity that would matter a lot more to some Christian believers than the original cause, for instance, the redeemer who died on Good Friday, used in conjunction with other such descriptions, images, stories, rituals, or prayers that promote feelings of proximity and familiarity. Secondly, on the parody interpretation of the evidential argument from evil, Holden describes Hume s purpose as showing that if the core natural theologian embarks on a venture such as Cleanthes s, then we can generate theological systems... willy-nilly (178). However, on that interpretation, wouldn t we expect more extravagant and novel hypotheses than, or in addition to, the four actually offered? If so, then perhaps Hume s aim here is to show that engaging in core natural theology invites the scandalously unorthodox (178) indifference hypothesis in particular. Prima facie, this suggestion supplies a plausible distancing mechanism of the sort required by the author. Thirdly, if weakness in the evidential argument from evil is evidence that Hume does not endorse it, perhaps a similar point applies to his version of the logical argument, where success carries the very heavy burden of proving logical impossibility. This book is a major achievement. New and seminal ideas are developed in it and set forth with great clarity and economy. In addition to its value to scholars Hume Studies

Book Reviews 239 of Hume, the book would be quite suitable for upper-level undergraduate courses in either Hume s moral philosophy or his philosophy of religion. david o connor Department of Philosophy 310 Fahy Hall Seton Hall University South Orange, NJ 07079, U.S.A. oconnoda@shu.edu Volume 36, Number 2, 2010