Francisco Suárez, S. J. De fine hominis disp. 1, sect. 3 1

Similar documents
QUESTION 8. The Objects of the Will

Universal Features: Doubts, Questions, Residual Problems DM VI 7

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DM XXIII, sect. 9 1

QUESTION 11. Enjoying as an Act of the Will

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DE FINE HOMINIS DISP. 1, SECT. 4 1

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DE FINE HOMINIS DISP. 1, SECT. 1 1

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DE FINE HOMINIS DISP. 2, SECT. 3 1

QUESTION 28. The Divine Relations

QUESTION 10. The Modality with Which the Will is Moved

QUESTION 34. The Goodness and Badness of Pleasures

QUESTION 36. The Causes of Sadness or Pain. Article 1. Is it a lost good that is a cause of pain rather than a conjoined evil?

QUESTION 90. The Initial Production of Man with respect to His Soul

QUESTION 20. The Goodness and Badness of the Exterior Act

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DE SCIENTIA DEI FUTURORUM CONTINGENTIUM 1.8 1

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DM XXIII, SECT. 3 1

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DE FINE HOMINIS DISP. 2, SECT. 2 1

QUESTION 55. The Essence of a Virtue

QUESTION 67. The Duration of the Virtues after this Life

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DE VOLUNTARIO ET INVOLUNTARIO DISP. 6, SECT. 1 1

QUESTION 87. How Our Intellect Has Cognition of Itself and of What Exists Within It

QUESTION 26. Love. Article 1. Does love exist in the concupiscible power?

PROLOGUE TO PART 1-2

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DE FINE HOMINIS DISP. 2, SECT. 4 1

QUESTION 63. The Cause of Virtue

The Science of Metaphysics DM I

QUESTION 55. The Medium of Angelic Cognition

QUESTION 59. An Angel s Will

BERNARD OF AUVERGNE ON JAMES OF VITERBO S DOCTRINE OF POSSIBLES: WITH A CRITICAL EDITION OF BERNARD S REPROBATIO OF JAMES S QUODLIBET 1, QUESTION 5 *

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DE FINE HOMINIS DISP. 5, SECT. 2 1

tion. Now [we will speak] briefly about those which St. Thomas [speaks] in [ST ] IaIIæ

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DISPUTATIO METAPHYSICA X, SECT. 1 1

QUESTION 44. The Procession of Creatures from God, and the First Cause of All Beings

QUESTION 56. An Angel s Cognition of Immaterial Things

QUESTION 45. Daring. Article 1. Is daring contrary to fear?

79 THE ROLE OF HABITUS IN ST. THOMAS'S MORAL THOUGHT John B. Kilioran King's College

Duane H. Berquist I26 THE TRUTH OF ARISTOTLE'S THEOLOGY

QUESTION 27. The Principal Act of Charity, i.e., the Act of Loving

QUESTION 53. The Corruption and Diminution of Habits. Article 1. Can a habit be corrupted?

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DE FINE HOMINIS DISP. 6, SECT. 3 1

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DM XXVII 1

Is Ockham off the hook?

Durandus of Saint-Pourçain In Petri Lombardi Sententias Theologicas Commentariorum

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DISPUTATIONES METAPHYSICÆ XII, SECT. 3 1

QUESTION 34. The Person of the Son: The Name Word

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DM XII.1 1

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DE VOLUNTARIO ET INVOLUNTARIO DISP. 8, SECT. 4 1

QUESTION 39. The Goodness and Badness of Sadness or Pain

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DE FINE HOMINIS DISP. 5, SECT. 1 1

SCOTUS argues in his mature Questions on the Metaphysics

De Casu Diaboli: An Examination of Faith and Reason Via a Discussion of the Devil s Sin

Francisco Suárez, S. J. Disputationes Metaphysicæ VIII 1

Resolutio secundum rem, the Dionysian triplex via and Thomistic Philosophical Theology

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DM VIII, SECT. 2 1

The Final End of the Human Being and the Virtue of Religion in the Theological Synthesis of Thomas Aquinas

QUESTION 83. The Subject of Original Sin

QUESTION 3. God s Simplicity

LOVE AS THE PRINCIPLE OF THE DYNAMISM OF BEINGS

QUESTION 65. The Connectedness of the Virtues

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DE FINE HOMINIS DISP. 3, SECT. 2 1

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DM XXVI, SECT. 1 1

QUESTION 54. An Angel s Cognition

QUESTION 76. The Union of the Soul with the Body

Truth as Relation in Aquinas

QUESTION 4. The Virtue Itself of Faith

A Note on Two Modal Propositions of Burleigh

QUESTION 57. The Distinctions Among the Intellectual Virtues

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DE FINE HOMINIS, DISP. 7, SECT. 2 1

WHAT IS THE USE OF USUS IN AQUINAS' PSYCHOLOGY OF ACTION? Stephen L. Brock

QUESTION 111. The Divisions of Grace

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n.

Faith is the Light of the Soul 1

Thomas Aquinas on God s Providence. Summa Theologiae 1a Q22: God s Providence

Francisco Peinado on Truthmakers for Negative Truths NEH Seminar, July 2015 Brian Embry

QUESTION 59. The Relation of the Moral Virtues to the Passions

THE METAPHYSICS BOOK IX, CHAPTER IV

Scotus Interpretation of the Difference between Voluntas ut Natura and Voluntas ut Voluntas

THE UNMITIGATED SCOTUS

QUESTION 66. The Equality of the Virtues

QUESTION 40. Hope and Despair

QUESTION 45. The Mode of the Emanation of Things from the First Principle

REFLECTIONS ON THE RELATION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY GERALD VAN ACKEREN, S.J.

QUESTION 22. God s Providence

QUESTION 116. Fate. Article 1. Is there such a thing as fate?

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DM XXX, SECT. 1 1

QUESTION 58. The Mode of an Angel s Cognition

Glossed books and commentary literature

Person and Ethics in Thomas Aquinas *

QUESTION 19. God s Will

Honors College, Baylor University, One Bear Place #97144, Waco, TX 76798, USA; Tel.:

ALTHOUGH THERE is general agreement among theologians that the

FORM, ESSENCE, SOUL: DISTINGUISHING PRINCIPLES OF THOMISTIC METAPHYSICS JOSHUA P. HOCHSCHILD

Reimagining Our Church for the Kingdom. The shape of things to come February 2018

WHAT CAN THE BLUES BROTHERS TEACH US ABOUT THE COMMON GOOD? A PRIMER ON THOMAS AQUINAS PHILOSOPHY OF NATURAL LAW. W. Penn Dawson *

A. Côté SIEPM, Palermo, September 2007

What Kind of Proofs are Aquinas s Demonstrations of God s Existence?

Being and Goodness: A Medieval Metaethical Thesis

c Peter King, 1987; all rights reserved. WILLIAM OF OCKHAM: ORDINATIO 1 d. 2 q. 6

TEN OBJECTIONS TO THE PRIMA VIA

Thomas Aquinas on the Metaphysical Nature of the Soul and its Union with the Body

John Duns Scotus. The possibility of the incarnation. Lectura III distinction 1 question 1 Latin text and English translation

Transcription:

Francisco Suárez, S. J. De fine hominis disp. 1, sect. 3 1 Last revision: October 27, 2015 Sydney Penner 2011 <6> 2 Whether an end exercises its causality under the aspect of cog- nized good. Utrum finis exerceat causalitatem suam sub ratione boni cogniti. Finis ratio, seu virtus per quam causat, est bonitas. Ostenditur auctoritate D. Thom. et aliorum. Explicuimus causalitatem finis et effectum ejus: sequitur We have explained the causality of an end and its effect. The ut dicamus de ratione causandi, seu de virtute, per quam next thing to talk about is the ratio of its causing or the force 5 causat. De qua duo sunt certa, circa quæ alia erunt du- 5R through which it causes. Two things are certain concerning this, bitanda et explicanda. but other related matters that are doubtful and should be explained. 1. Primo igitur certum est, finem in suo genere causare, 1. The first thing, then, that is certain is that the end causes The ratio of the quatenus quoddam bonum, et conveniens est. Hæc est in its genus insofar as it is a kind of good and agreeable thing. 3 end or the force through which sententia D. Thomæ 1, 2, quæst. 1, a. 1, in fine corporis, 10R This is St. Thomas s view in ST IaIIæ.1.1, co. (towards the end). it causes is 10 quam late tractat 3, cont. Gentes, cap. 2 et 3, ubi probat, He discusses it more thoroughly in SCG III, c. 2 and 3, where goodness. idem esse operari propter finem, et propter bonum: et he shows that to act for the sake of the end is the same as to It is shown by 1 p., q. 5, a. 4, similiter probat bonum habere rationem act for the sake of the good. In ST Ia.5.4 he likewise shows that the authority of St. Thomas and finis, ubi in solutione ad 2, in hunc modum explicat il- good has the ratio of an end, where in his solution ad 2 he in this others. lud Dionysii 4, c. de Divinis nominibus: Bonum est diffu- 15R way explains Dionysius s statement from On the Divine Names, 15 sivum sui. Eamdem doctrinam habet Alensis, 1 p., q. 17, c. 4: Goodness is self-diffusive. [Alexander] of Hales holds the memb. 3. et 34, memb. 1, et colligitur ex Aristotele, 1 same doctrine in Sent. I, q. 17, memb. 3 and q. 34, memb. 1, and Ethicor., cap. 7, dicente: Id esse unicuique bonum, cujus it is gathered from Aristotle, who says in EN I, c. 7: That is the gratia cætera operantur. Idem lib. I Ethic., in fine, et 2, good of each for whose sake everything else is done [1097a17 Item ratione. Phys., cap. 3, ubi dicit, finem et bonum idem esse. Ratio 20R 18]. Likewise at the end of book I and in Phys. II, c. 3, where he 20 vero constat ex dictis, quia causalitas finis in hoc consis- says: the end and the good are the same. 4 And the reason is And by reason. tit, quod trahit voluntatem ad se propter se amandum, clear from what was said, for the causality of the end consists in vel alia propter ipsum: sed nihil potest trahere volun- drawing the will to itself on account of being loved in itself or tatem nisi bonum, quatenus bonum est: ergo bonitas est to other things for its sake. But nothing can draw the will except a qua habet finis virtutem causandi finaliter; est ergo illi 25R something good insofar as it is good. Therefore, goodness is that 1 Latin text is from the Vivès edition; in some cases I have followed the 1628 edition. Marginal notes are as found in the 1628 edition. Most of those, though not all and not always in the right place, are included in the Vivès edition as italicised text. For recorded variants, A = 1628 edition, M = 1629 Mainz edition, and V = Vivès edition. 2 Numbers in angle brackets indicate page numbers in the Vivès edition for ease of reference, given that it is the most widely used edition. 3 This claim is treated at greater length in DM 23.5. 4 195a22 25?

Suárez, De Fine Hominis, disp. 1, sect. 3 2 Exponitur Caietanus circa rationem causandi finaliter. 25 ratio causandi. by which an end has the power of final-causing and is, therefore, the ratio of causing for it. 2. Hanc autem veritatem per se claram, obscuri- 2. This truth which is clear in itself is rendered rather ob- Cajetan on the orem reddit Cajetanus, 1 p., art. 4, q. 5, dicens, bonitatem scure by Cajetan when he says in [his commentary on] ST Ia.4.5 nature of final-causing is formalem esse ipsam rationem causæ finalis in actu ex- 30R that formal goodness is the very ratio of the final cause in the explained. ercito, non vero in actu signato, nisi tantum fundamen- exercised act but not in the signified act, unless merely funda- 30 taliter. Quorum verborum sensus in idem redit. Nam mentally. The sense of those words comes to the same thing. For per hoc nomen bonum non explicatur res sub habitu- through this word good one does not indicate a thing under a dine ad effectum, seu actum finaliter causandi, et hoc disposition to an effect or to an act of final-causing (and Cajetan vocavit Cajetanus finem in actu signato, quam rationem 35R calls this the end in the signified act). The ratio of good does not non <col. b> significat formaliter ratio boni, sed tantum formally signify this ratio. Rather, it only indicates the perfection 35 explicat perfectionem objecti, seu convenientiam quam of the object or the agreeability which it has to the will, as a rehabet cum voluntate, ex qua habet quod finalisare pos- sult of which it has that which allows it to final-cause. The name sit, quam habitudinem formaliter explicat nomen, seu or ratio of an end indicates this disposition. For this reason it ratio finis: et ideo dicitur fundari in bonitate. Et hoc 40R is said to be founded in goodness. And in this way Cajetan said modo dixit Cajetanus bonum significare rationem finis that good signifies the ratio of an end in the exercised act fun- 40 in actu exercito fundamentaliter, ac si in causa efficiente damentally, as if we were to say that in an efficient cause heat, diceremus calorem, verbi gratia, esse finem agentis fun- for example, is the agent s end fundamentally, yet as such it does damentaliter, tamen ut sic non significare formaliter ip- not formally signify the disposition itself of the efficient cause. sam habitudinem efficientis. Secundo certum est ut bonum causet finaliter nec- 45R Secondly, it is certain that in order for good to final-cause it 45 essarium esse ut cognitum sit; quia appetitus vitalis se- is necessary that it have been cognized, because the vital apquitur formam apprehensam, et ideo ferri non potest petite follows an apprehended form and therefore cannot be nisi in objectum cognitum ut constat ex philosophia, et brought to anything other than a cognized object. This is clear ex 1 p., quæst. 80 et sequentib., et ex quæst. 8 et 9, 1, 2, from the philosophers and from Sent. p. 1, q. 80 and followviderique possunt quæ scripsi in disp. 23, Metaphysicæ, 50R ing and from ST IaIIæ.8 9. And what I wrote can be seen in 50 sect. 7, et libr. 2, de Orat. mentali, cap. 13. Hinc vero DM 23.7 and De Orat. mentali lib. 2, c. 13. 5 But from here has oriebatur occasio disputandi quomodo se habebat esse arisen an occasion for disputing how cognitive being (esse cogcognitum ad rationem causandi finalem, an scilicet sit nitum) is related to the nature of final-causing, whether, namely, tantum conditio necessaria, vel etiam ratio causandi, et it is only a necessary condition or also a ratio of causing, and consequenter an bonum cognitum causet finaliter se- 55R consequently whether cognized good final-causes according to 55 cundum esse cognitum, vel secundum esse reale. Quam cognitive being or according to real being. This question is disquæstionem late tractat 1, 2, quæst. 1, art. 1, Medina, et cussed more thoroughly in Medina s and Cajetan s [commen- Cajetanus ibid., et antea in 1 part., quæst. 5, art. 4, et Fer- taries on] ST IaIIæ.1.1 and before that in Ia.5.4, and by Ferrara 5 This is presumably one of the places where Suárez s posthumous literary executor deleted material and inserted a reference to his fuller discussions elsewhere. 49 23 ] 13 V. 54 cognitum causet ] causet cognitum M V.

Suárez, De Fine Hominis, disp. 1, sect. 3 3 rarius 1, cont. Gent., cap. 44, et aliqui theologi in 2, dist. 1, in [his commentary on] SCG I, c. 44, and by other theologians præsertim Gabriel, part. 5, alii vero in 2, dist. 25, præser- 60R in Sent. II, dist. 1, especially Gabriel in part. 5, but others, espe- 60 tim Scotus et Capreolus. Sed quoniam hæc res in dis- cially Scotus and Capreolus, in II, dist. 25. But since I discuss this put. 23 Metaphysicæ, sect., 8, a me late traditur, et, ut ex- matter more thoroughly in DM 23.8, and, as I think, poses no istimo, nihil difficultatis habet, dicam breviter quæ sen- difficulty, I will say briefly what I think and what is necessary for tio, et quod ad Quæstiones Theologicas postea tractan- discussing the theological questions afterwards. das est necessarium. Cognitio objecti 65 3. Advertendum est ergo, interdum appetere vol- 65R 3. It should be noted, then, that sometimes the will desires The cognition finalizantis non untatem objectum cognitum solum in ordine ad cogni- a cognized object only in relation to cognition, as, for example, of the pertinet ad final-causing tionem, ut, verbi gratia, quando contemplando rosam when in contemplating a rose it does not desire to possess it but rationem object does not causandi non appetit illam habere, sed tantum considerare et only to consider and cognize it. 6 In that case to be cognized (esse belong to the finaliter, sed est cognoscere, et tunc esse cognitum non solum est con- cognitum) is not only a condition but also the reason for moving ratio of sola conditio. 70 ditio, sed est ratio, movendi voluntatem, quia non solum 70R the will, because not only is the cognition a prerequisite for the final-causing but is only a est quid prærequisitum ut voluntas moveatur, sed etiam will to be moved but it is also the terminus of the desire just condition. est terminus appetitionis, cujusmodi est quæcumque like any other thing that is judged to be agreeable. And in this alia res quæ judicatur esse conveniens, et hoc modo way when a human being is delighted in the cognition alone but quando homo delectatur tantum in cognitione non vero not in the cognized thing according to itself, to be cognized is 75 in re cognita secundum se, esse cognitum est id, a quo 75R that from which the act takes its ratio and goodness or badness, actus accipit suam rationem et bonitatem vel <7> mali- just as when a human being desires to see God, that being seen tiam: sicut est quando homo appetit videre Deum, il- belongs to the formal object that is the cause of final-causing. lud esse visum pertinet ad formale objectum, quod est But sometimes the will desires the cognized object so that It is shown causa finalisandi. Aliquando vero voluntas appetit ob- it has and obtains that thing itself, as when it desires health. In firstly. 80 jectum cognitum ut re ipsa illud habeat et consequatur, 80R that case, the ratio of final-causing is clearly the goodness that Ostenditur 1. ut quando appetit sanitatem, et tunc plane ratio final- the object has or is thought to have in reality. For the former isandi est bonitas, quam in reipsa objectum habet, vel is the will s end to which the impetus of the agent tends. But it habere apprehendit, quia illud est finis voluntatis, in does not tend except to the real being of the end itself, in order quod tendit impetus agentis, sed non tendit nisi in esse to have and obtain it. Therefore. Ostenditur 2. 85 reale ipsius finis, ut illud habeat et obtineat: ergo. Item, 85R Likewise, that has the proper ratio of an end by the achieve- It is shown illud habet propriam rationem finis, quo consecuto, qui- ment of which the will is at rest and by the lack of which it is secondly. escit voluntas, et quo deficiente frustratur ab intentione frustrated from its intention. The will, however, is not at rest sua, sed non quiescit in sola apprehensione, nisi re ipsa in the apprehension alone, unless that attains the end in reality, finem consequatur, et nisi hoc obtineat, frustrari dici- and it is said to be frustrated unless the latter is obtained. This is 90 tur: ergo signum est moveri a fine secundum suum esse 90R an indication, then, that the will is moved by the end according 6 Cf. De Actibus Qui Vocantur Passiones Tum Etiam de Habitibus 1.5.3. 59 vero ] om. V. 83 habere ] om. M V. 89 consequatur ] consequantur V.

Suárez, De Fine Hominis, disp. 1, sect. 3 4 Existentia realis non ingreditur etiam rationem causandi finaliter. Notatio pro præcedente doctrina. reale. Non est autem intelligendum requiri ad causali- to its real being. tatem finis quod res illa, quæ est finis a parte rei præex- Nor should one understand as required for the causality of Real existence istat, quia cum solum moveat metaphorice per cogni- the end that the thing that is the end pre-exist in reality, since it is not even a constituent of tionem, satis est quod animo apprehendatur, et quasi is sufficient that it be apprehended by the mind and be reprethe ratio of 95 in imagine repræsentetur; sensus ergo est rem illam 95R sented in an image, as it were. The sense, therefore, is that that final-causing. secundum esse reale, quod objicitur, et in ea appre- thing moves the will and has the causality of an end according henditur, movere voluntatem, et habere causalitatem to the real being that is presented and is apprehended in it. It finis, quia secundum illud esse judicatur conveniens: moves, moreover, as we said, insofar as it is judged agreeable. movet autem, ut diximus, quatenus conveniens judi- For this reason, the cognition of this agreeability and goodness 100 catur; cognitio igitur hujus convenientiæ et bonitatis, 100R is not properly the ratio of moving, because in this case the will non est propria ratio movendi, quia tunc voluntas non does not desire to cognize. But the cognition is said to be necappetit cognoscere, sed dicitur esse cognitio necessaria essary in the mode of coming close, not, indeed, according to per modum approximationis, non quidem secundum place, but only according to the subordination of the soul s powlocum, sed tantum subordinationem potentiarum an- ers, and because without that the end does not have that mode 105 imæ; et quia sine illa non habet finis illum modum quo 105R which it needs for its causality. And this view is clearer when indiget ad suam causalitatem. Et hoc modo explicata explained in this way, as is clear from Scotus, Gabriel, Cajetan, hæc sententia clarior est, ut patet ex Scoto, Gabriele, Ca- and Ferrara in the places cited above, and it has no difficulty of jetano et Ferrario, locis supra citatis, et nullam habet dif- any importance. ficultatem alicujus momenti. 110 4. Ut tamen facile dissolvantur multa argumenta, 4. Nevertheless, so that the many arguments which Med- A note quæ hic multiplicat Medina; oportet ultimo advertere, 110R ina multiplies in this place are easily resolved, it is necessary fiquod sicut in causa efficiente approximatio non est ratio nally to notice that just as in the case of an efficient cause coming concerning the preceding doctrine. agendi, sed conditio, potest tamen ratione illius variari close together is not the ratio of acting but a condition for it and actio, si diversum agens applicetur, ita et in hac appre- yet the action can be varied by reason of it, if a different agent 115 hensione, seu cognitione intellectus, contingere potest, is applied, so also it can happen with this apprehension or cogut ratione illius varietur actio voluntatis, si in objecte 115R nition by the intellect that by reason of it the action of the will aliud esse, seu aliam rationem apprehendat boni, vel is varied, if some other being or another aspect of good or bad mali: quo sensu dici solet finem specificare actum vo- is apprehended in the object. The end is usually said to specluntatis, non ut in re est, sed ut apprehenditur: nam licet ify the act of the will in this sense, not as it is in reality but as it 120 eleemosyna, verbi gratia, in re sit bona, si quis illam ex- is apprehended. For although giving alms, for example, is good istimat malam, actio voluntatis non est bona, sed mala. 120R in reality, if someone thinks it bad, the action of the will is not Propter quam rationem videtur dixisse divus Thomas, good but bad. For this reason St. Thomas seems to have said in 1, 2, quæst. 31, artic. 3, ad 1, cum objectum voluntatis ST IaIIæ.31.3 ad 1 that when the object of the will is apprehended sit bonum apprehensum, diversitatem apprehensionis as good, difference of apprehension belongs to difference of the 125 pertinere ad diversitatem objecti, atque idem sentit Ca- object. And Cajetan thinks the same in q. 30, art. 3. But these are jetanus, q. 30, art. 3. Sed hæc non sunt contraria, quia 125R not contraries, because apprehension of the good now varies tunc apprehensio boni tantum variat objectum in quan- the object only insofar as different being of the object is appretum in illo apprehendit et applicat diversum esse ob- hended and appplied in it and consequently different goodness

Suárez, De Fine Hominis, disp. 1, sect. 3 5 jecti, atque adeo distinctam bonitatem, vel convenien- or agreeability, which, as I said, is the ratio of moving the will. 130 tiam, quæ, ut dixi, est ratio movendi voluntatem. Quo- Wherefore, when it is said that the object moves as apcirca quando dicitur objectum movere ut apprehen- 130R prehended, one should avoid equivocation in that reduplicating sum, cavenda est æquivocatio in illa particula redupli- phrase. For if it only reduplicates the denomination arising from cante: nam si reduplicet solam denominationem prove- the apprehension such that the apprehension itself is the form nientem ab apprehensione ita ut ipsa apprehensio sit through which the end moves, the statement is false, as I said. 135 forma, per quam finis movet, falsum est, ut dixi, si autem But if the objective being itself (which is apprehended) is redureduplicet ipsum esse objectivum, quod apprehendit, 135R plicated, the expression is true. In the same way the diversity sic vera est locutio, atque eodem modo diversitas cogni- of cognition, which holds only on the part of the power, either tionis, quæ se tenet tantum ex parte potentiæ, aut cog- in cognition or in the proper qualities of the act of understandnitionis, seu in propriis qualitatibus ipsius actus intelli- ing itself (some examples are that it is clear, or obscure, and so 140 gendi, ut sunt, verbi gratia, quod sit clara, vel obscura, et on), this diversity, I say, does not vary the ratio of the end and similis, hæc, inquam, diversitas non variat rationem fi- 140R consequently neither the motion of the will. nis, et consequenter nec motionem voluntatis: at vero But, on the other hand, the diversity of cognition which rediversitas cognitionis, quæ redundat in objecto, scilicet dounds to the object (namely, because something else is cogquia aliud est quod cognoscitur, vel alia proprietas in eo nized or other properties are apprehended in it) varies the end 145 apprehenditur, hæc variat finem et motionem, quia pro- and the motion, because it proposes and approaches the subponit, et appropinquat subjectum secundum aliud esse 145R ject according to other objective being. Hence it diversifies it, objectivum: unde quasi diversificat illud, et sic reddit di- as it were, and so delivers different cognition not on the part versam cognitionem non ex parte esse cogniti absoluti, of cognitive being absolutely, but on the part of the object that sed ex parte objecti quod cognoscitur. Et hæc de causal- is cognized. And that [suffices] concerning the causality, effect, 150 itate, effectu et principio, seu forma, quæ est principium and principle or form, which is the principle of an end. finis. 138 se ] om. V.