Modal Conditions on Knowledge: Sensitivity and safety

Similar documents
Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Nozick and Scepticism (Weekly supervision essay; written February 16 th 2005)

Sensitivity has Multiple Heterogeneity Problems: a Reply to Wallbridge. Guido Melchior. Philosophia Philosophical Quarterly of Israel ISSN


John Hawthorne s Knowledge and Lotteries

External World Skepticism

Fake Barns, Fake News. Paul Faulkner, University of Sheffield

Anti-Luck Epistemologies and Necessary Truths

Safety, Virtue, Scepticism: Remarks on Sosa

Sosa on Safety and Epistemic Frankfurt Cases

Sensitivity hasn t got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Varieties of Apriority

NO SAFE HAVEN FOR THE VIRTUOUS. In order to deal with the problem caused by environmental luck some proponents of robust virtue

LUMINOSITY AND THE SAFETY OF KNOWLEDGE

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise

Knowledge, so it seems to many, involves

REVIEW OF DUNCAN PRITCHARD S EPISTEMIC LUCK

Nozick s fourth condition

what makes reasons sufficient?

Relativity. Should we suspend our judgment regarding everything that appears to the senses?

Ascribing Knowledge in Context: Some Objections to the Contextualist s Solution to Skepticism

Basic Knowledge and the Problem of Easy Knowledge (Rough Draft-notes incomplete not for quotation) Stewart Cohen

Sensitivity Theory and the Individuation of Belief-Formation Methods

Saying too Little and Saying too Much. Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

Comments on Lasersohn

Saying too Little and Saying too Much Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

Safety, sensitivity and differential support

Outsmarting the McKinsey-Brown argument? 1

Modal Epistemology. A study of the conditions of knowledge. Jaakko Hirvelä Pro gradu tutkielma Teoreettinen filosofia

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

Three Modified Versions of Nozick s Theory of Knowledge

The Gettier problem JTB K

Analyticity and reference determiners

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

The Internalist Virtue Theory of Knowledge. Ralph Wedgwood

HOW I KNOW I M NOT A BRAIN IN A VAT * José L. Zalabardo University College London

Moore s Paradox and the Norm of Belief

Beware of Safety. Christian Piller University of York ENN Stockholm Oct 2017

Follow this and additional works at: Part of the Philosophy Commons

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

The Dreamer. Does Descartes know what he is doing when he shakes his head and stretches out his hand? Descartes, Meditations, 1641

Is Knowledge True Belief Plus Adequate Information?

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

The Gettier problem JTB K

New Lessons from Old Demons: The Case for Reliabilism

Constructing the World

Why Safety Doesn t Save Closure. Abstract

KNOWLEDGE ESSENTIALLY BASED UPON FALSE BELIEF

The Skeptic and the Dogmatist

Conceptual Analysis and Reductive Explanation

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS

SCEPTICISM, EPISTEMIC LUCK, AND EPISTEMIC ANGST

Nozick s defense of closure

KNOWLEDGE AS DE RE TRUE BELIEF?

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

EVERYBODY NEEDS TO KNOW?

knowledge is belief for sufficient (objective and subjective) reason

Philosophical reflection about what we call knowledge has a natural starting point in the

Metaphysical Dependence and Set Theory

Dogmatism and Moorean Reasoning. Markos Valaris University of New South Wales. 1. Introduction

Philosophical Issues, 23, Epistemic Agency, 2013 CAN VIRTUE EPISTEMOLOGY CAPITALIZE ON JTB S APPEAL? E.J. Coffman The University of Tennessee

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Edinburgh Research Explorer

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

A Puzzle about Knowing Conditionals i. (final draft) Daniel Rothschild University College London. and. Levi Spectre The Open University of Israel

Some Thoughts on the JK-Rule 1

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2016

Dretske on Knowledge Closure

Contemporary Epistemology

Lecture Notes on KNOWLEDGE. Brian Weatherson

A Defense of the Significance of the A Priori A Posteriori Distinction. Albert Casullo. University of Nebraska-Lincoln

RESPECTING THE EVIDENCE. Richard Feldman University of Rochester

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites

Evidentialist Anti-Skepticism

Epistemic luck and the generality problem

TRANSMISSION FAILURE EXPLAINED *

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

moral absolutism agents moral responsibility

THERE S NOTHING TO BEAT A BACKWARD CLOCK: A REJOINDER TO ADAMS, BARKER AND CLARKE

Can logical consequence be deflated?

A Priori Bootstrapping

Between the Actual and the Trivial World

Bradley on Chance, Admissibility & the Mind of God

A Two-Factor Theory of Perceptual Justification. Abstract: By examining the role perceptual experience plays in the justification of our

This discussion surveys recent developments

Ignorance is Lack of True Belief: A Rejoinder to Le Morvan

SAFETY-BASED EPISTEMOLOGY: WHITHER NOW?

The traditional tripartite account of knowledge as justified true belief

Skepticism and Internalism

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

Knowledge, Safety, and Questions

It is received wisdom that the skeptic has a devastating line of

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Resolving the Gettier Problem in the Smith Case: The Donnellan Linguistic Approach

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

PHIL-210: Knowledge and Certainty

Transcription:

Modal Conditions on Knowledge: Sensitivity and safety 10.28.14

Outline A sensitivity condition on knowledge? A sensitivity condition on knowledge?

Outline A sensitivity condition on knowledge? A sensitivity condition on knowledge?

Introduction to sensitivity Sensitivity, to a first approximation, is this counterfactual relation: (Sensitivity) S s belief that p is sensitive if and only if, if p were false, S would not believe that p. A sensitivity condition on knowledge was first defended by Robert Nozick (1981).

IIntroduction to sensitivity What does sensitivity amount to, really? (Lewis s counterfactuals) if p were false, S would not believe that p iff in the nearest possible worlds in which not-p, the subject does not believe that p. So a belief is sensitive just in case in the nearest possible worlds in which not-p, the subject does not believe that p.

Outline A sensitivity condition on knowledge? A sensitivity condition on knowledge?

Goldman s first analysis Goldman s first attempt to capture his basic idea goes as follows. S perceptually knows that P iff: P is true.

Goldman s first analysis Goldman s first attempt to capture his basic idea goes as follows. S perceptually knows that P iff: P is true. S has a perceptual belief that P.

Goldman s first analysis Goldman s first attempt to capture his basic idea goes as follows. S perceptually knows that P iff: P is true. S has a perceptual belief that P. There is no alternative Q which is both relevant and which is such that, if Q obtained, S would still have a perceptual belief that P.

Goldman s first analysis For example, suppose S looks out the window of his car and sees a barn.

Goldman s first analysis For example, suppose S looks out the window of his car and sees a barn. S forms the true belief that there s a barn.

Goldman s first analysis For example, suppose S looks out the window of his car and sees a barn. S forms the true belief that there s a barn. One alternative would be the hypothesis that it s just an empty field.

Goldman s first analysis For example, suppose S looks out the window of his car and sees a barn. S forms the true belief that there s a barn. One alternative would be the hypothesis that it s just an empty field. However, if that alternative obtained, then S would have different experiences and so he would no longer believe that there s a barn.

Goldman s first analysis For example, suppose S looks out the window of his car and sees a barn. S forms the true belief that there s a barn. One alternative would be the hypothesis that it s just an empty field. However, if that alternative obtained, then S would have different experiences and so he would no longer believe that there s a barn. Hence, S is able to discriminate this alternative from what believes to be true.

Sensitivity and Gettier cases One motivation for including a sensitivity condition in an analysis of knowledge is that there seems to be an intuitive sense in which knowledge requires not merely being correct, but tracking the truth in other possible circumstances.

Sensitivity and Gettier cases One motivation for including a sensitivity condition in an analysis of knowledge is that there seems to be an intuitive sense in which knowledge requires not merely being correct, but tracking the truth in other possible circumstances. This seems to be a plausible diagnosis of what goes wrong in at least some Gettier cases.

Sensitivity and Gettier cases One motivation for including a sensitivity condition in an analysis of knowledge is that there seems to be an intuitive sense in which knowledge requires not merely being correct, but tracking the truth in other possible circumstances. This seems to be a plausible diagnosis of what goes wrong in at least some Gettier cases. For example, Smith s belief that Jones owns a Ford or Brown is in Barcelona seems to be insensitive.

Sensitivity and Gettier cases For if that disjunction were false, if Jones didn t own a Ford and Brown wasn t in Barcelona, Smith would have held the same belief on the same grounds, viz., the misleading evidence vis-a-vis Jones s car.

Sensitivity and Gettier cases For if that disjunction were false, if Jones didn t own a Ford and Brown wasn t in Barcelona, Smith would have held the same belief on the same grounds, viz., the misleading evidence vis-a-vis Jones s car. But does sensitivity help in all of Gettier cases?

Sensitivity and Gettier cases For if that disjunction were false, if Jones didn t own a Ford and Brown wasn t in Barcelona, Smith would have held the same belief on the same grounds, viz., the misleading evidence vis-a-vis Jones s car. But does sensitivity help in all of Gettier cases? Let us consider a few cases.

Barn facades A sensitivity condition on knowledge? Suppose there is a county in the Midwest with the following peculiar feature. The landscape next to the road leading through that county is peppered with barn-facades: structures that from the road look exactly like barns. Observation from any other viewpoint would immediately reveal these structures to be fakes: devices erected for the purpose of fooling unsuspecting motorists into believing in the presence of barns. Suppose Henry is driving along the road that leads through Barn County.

Barn facades A sensitivity condition on knowledge? Barn facades, continued Naturally, Henry will on numerous occasions form false beliefs in the presence of barns. Since Henry has no reason to suspect that he is the victim of organized deception, these beliefs are justified. Now suppose further that, on one of those occasions when he believes there is a barn over there, he happens to be looking at the one and only real barn in the county.

Sensitivity and Gettier cases In the Barn Facades, the sensitivity condition of knowledge rules out Henry s belief from being a case of knowledge.

Sensitivity and Gettier cases In the Barn Facades, the sensitivity condition of knowledge rules out Henry s belief from being a case of knowledge. However, consider Kripke s variation of the case.

Saul Kripke Cast of Characters A sensitivity condition on knowledge? Logician and philosopher. Huge, immense contributions to analytic philosophy. Never got a PhD. After graduating from high school in 1958, graduated from Harvard in mathematics. Upon graduation (1962) he received a Fulbright Fellowship, and in 1963 was appointed to the Society of Fellows. Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at CUNY graduate center.

Kripke (2011), Barn facades Suppose that barn facades are always green, but genuine barns are always red.

Kripke (2011), Barn facades Suppose that barn facades are always green, but genuine barns are always red. In this case, Henry s belief that he sees a red barn will be sensitive: if the animal is looking at were not red, he would not believe it was.

Kripke (2011), Barn facades Suppose that barn facades are always green, but genuine barns are always red. In this case, Henry s belief that he sees a red barn will be sensitive: if the animal is looking at were not red, he would not believe it was. On the other hand, his belief that he sees a barn will be non-sensitive, for the previous reasons.

Kripke (2011), Barn facades Suppose that barn facades are always green, but genuine barns are always red. In this case, Henry s belief that he sees a red barn will be sensitive: if the animal is looking at were not red, he would not believe it was. On the other hand, his belief that he sees a barn will be non-sensitive, for the previous reasons. So the prediction is that Henry knows that he is seeing a red barn but does not know that he is seeing a barn.

Kripke (2011), Barn facades Suppose that barn facades are always green, but genuine barns are always red. In this case, Henry s belief that he sees a red barn will be sensitive: if the animal is looking at were not red, he would not believe it was. On the other hand, his belief that he sees a barn will be non-sensitive, for the previous reasons. So the prediction is that Henry knows that he is seeing a red barn but does not know that he is seeing a barn. That seems like a bad prediction.

Against Sensitivity Most epistemologists today reject sensitivity requirements on knowledge.

Against Sensitivity Most epistemologists today reject sensitivity requirements on knowledge. The chief motivation against a sensitivity condition is that, given plausible assumptions, it leads to unacceptable implications called abominable conjunctions.

Against Sensitivity Most epistemologists today reject sensitivity requirements on knowledge. The chief motivation against a sensitivity condition is that, given plausible assumptions, it leads to unacceptable implications called abominable conjunctions. To see this, suppose first that skepticism about ordinary knowledge is false, ordinary subjects know at least many of the things we ordinarily take them to know. For example, George, who can see and use his hands perfectly well, knows that he has hands.

Against Sensitivity Now imagine a skeptical scenario in which George does not have hands.

Against Sensitivity Now imagine a skeptical scenario in which George does not have hands. Suppose that George is the victim of a Cartesian demon, deceiving him into believing that he has hands.

Against Sensitivity Now imagine a skeptical scenario in which George does not have hands. Suppose that George is the victim of a Cartesian demon, deceiving him into believing that he has hands. If George were in such a scenario, of course, he would falsely believe himself not to be in such a scenario.

Against Sensitivity So given the sensitivity condition, George cannot know that he is not in such a scenario.

Against Sensitivity So given the sensitivity condition, George cannot know that he is not in such a scenario. These two verdicts, the knowledge-attributing one about ordinary knowledge, and the knowledge-denying one about the skeptical scenario, are arguably each intuitive, it is intuitively problematic to hold them together.

Against Sensitivity Their conjunction is, in DeRose s term, abominable: George knows that he has hands, but he doesn t know that he s not the handless victim of a Cartesian demon.

Against Sensitivity Their conjunction is, in DeRose s term, abominable: George knows that he has hands, but he doesn t know that he s not the handless victim of a Cartesian demon. A sensitivity condition on knowledge, combined with the nonskeptical claim that there is ordinary knowledge, seems to imply such abominable conjunctions.

Outline A sensitivity condition on knowledge? A sensitivity condition on knowledge?

Introduction to safety Although few epistemologists today endorse a sensitivity condition on knowledge, the idea that knowledge requires a subject to stand in a particular modal relation to the proposition known remains a popular one.

Introduction to safety Although few epistemologists today endorse a sensitivity condition on knowledge, the idea that knowledge requires a subject to stand in a particular modal relation to the proposition known remains a popular one. In his 1999 paper, How to Defeat Opposition to Moore, Ernest Sosa proposed that a safety condition ought to take the role that sensitivity was intended to play.

Introduction to safety Although few epistemologists today endorse a sensitivity condition on knowledge, the idea that knowledge requires a subject to stand in a particular modal relation to the proposition known remains a popular one. In his 1999 paper, How to Defeat Opposition to Moore, Ernest Sosa proposed that a safety condition ought to take the role that sensitivity was intended to play. Sosa characterized safety as the counterfactual contrapositive of sensitivity:

Introduction to safety Sosa characterized safety as the counterfactual contrapositive of sensitivity:

Introduction to safety Sosa characterized safety as the counterfactual contrapositive of sensitivity: (Sensitivity) S s belief that p is sensitive if and only if, if p were false, S would not believe that p.

Introduction to safety Sosa characterized safety as the counterfactual contrapositive of sensitivity: (Sensitivity) S s belief that p is sensitive if and only if, if p were false, S would not believe that p. () S s belief that p is safe if and only if, if S were to believe that p, p would not be false.

Introduction to safety Sensitivity and safety are not equivalent!

Introduction to safety Sensitivity and safety are not equivalent! An example of a safe belief that is not sensitive, according to Sosa, is the belief that a distant skeptical scenario does not obtain.

Introduction to safety If we stipulate that George, discussed above, has never been at risk of being the victim of a Cartesian demon, because, say, Cartesian demons do not exist in George s world. then George s belief that he is not such a victim is a safe one, even though we saw in the previous section that it could not be sensitive.

Introduction to safety If we stipulate that George, discussed above, has never been at risk of being the victim of a Cartesian demon, because, say, Cartesian demons do not exist in George s world. then George s belief that he is not such a victim is a safe one, even though we saw in the previous section that it could not be sensitive. Notice that although we stipulated that George is not at risk of deceit by Cartesian demons, we did not stipulate that George himself had any particular access to this fact.

Contraposing counterfactuals (p q) (not q notp);

Contraposing counterfactuals (p q) (not q notp); (p notq) (q notp);

Another example If water now flowed from your kitchen faucet, it would not then be the case that water so flowed while your main valve was closed. (TRUE) p q

Another example If water now flowed from your kitchen faucet, it would not then be the case that water so flowed while your main valve was closed. (TRUE) p q If it were the case that water flowed from your kitchen faucet while the main valve was closed, then water would not flow from the kitchen faucet. (FALSE) not q notp

Introduction to safety Rather than resting on a contentious treatment of counterfactuals, then, it may be most perspicuous to understand the safety condition more directly in these modal terms, as Sosa himself often does:

Introduction to safety Rather than resting on a contentious treatment of counterfactuals, then, it may be most perspicuous to understand the safety condition more directly in these modal terms, as Sosa himself often does: (, II) S s belief that p is safe if and only if, In all nearby worlds where S believes that p, p is not false.

and Gettier Satefy seems to help with Gettier cases: Henry does not know that somebody in his office owns a Ford because Henry would have believed that even if nobody in his office owned a Ford.

and Gettier Satefy seems to help with Gettier cases: Henry does not know that somebody in his office owns a Ford because Henry would have believed that even if nobody in his office owned a Ford. What about the barn facade cases? Does safety help with those too? if so, how?

Outline A sensitivity condition on knowledge? A sensitivity condition on knowledge?

and mathematical knowledge Mathematical propositions that are true are necessarily true cannot be false.

and mathematical knowledge Mathematical propositions that are true are necessarily true cannot be false. So every mathematical belief is trivially safe.

and mathematical knowledge Mathematical propositions that are true are necessarily true cannot be false. So every mathematical belief is trivially safe. But one can come to have a mathematical belief that is true only by luck.

and mathematical knowledge Mathematical propositions that are true are necessarily true cannot be false. So every mathematical belief is trivially safe. But one can come to have a mathematical belief that is true only by luck. So safety does not work as an anti-luck condition on mathematical beliefs.

and demons Suppose an evil angel is making sure that I do not get to have any false belief.

and demons Suppose an evil angel is making sure that I do not get to have any false belief. So he is making sure that I do not come to believe something that turns out false.

and demons Suppose an evil angel is making sure that I do not get to have any false belief. So he is making sure that I do not come to believe something that turns out false. In this case, every belief that I came to have is safe.

and demons Suppose an evil angel is making sure that I do not get to have any false belief. So he is making sure that I do not come to believe something that turns out false. In this case, every belief that I came to have is safe. But I do not know in that case, intuitively.

and demons Suppose an evil angel is making sure that I do not get to have any false belief. So he is making sure that I do not come to believe something that turns out false. In this case, every belief that I came to have is safe. But I do not know in that case, intuitively. So safety cannot be sufficient for knowledge.