Aquinas, The Five Ways

Similar documents
Aquinas, The Divine Nature

Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence

Summer Preparation Work

Scholasticism In the 1100s, scholars and monks rediscovered the ancient Greek texts that had been lost for so long. Scholasticism was a revival of

Does God Exist? Understanding arguments for the existence of God. HZT4U1 February

Aristotle and Aquinas

Thomas Aquinas The Existence of God can be proved in five ways.

The cosmological argument (continued)

ARTICLE PRESENTATION, EXAMPLE 2: AQUINAS PHI 101: INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY DR. DAVE YOUNT

THEISM AND BELIEF. Etymological note: deus = God in Latin; theos = God in Greek.

Aristotle. Cause, Purpose and the Prime Mover

Monday, September 26, The Cosmological Argument

God and Creation, Job 38:1-15

The Five Ways THOMAS AQUINAS ( ) Thomas Aquinas: The five Ways

Does God Exist? By: Washington Massaquoi. January 2, Introduction

Five Ways to Prove the Existence of God. From Summa Theologica. St. Thomas Aquinas

What does it say about humanity s search for answers? What are the cause and effects mentioned in the Psalm?

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

Anselm of Canterbury, Proslogion, chapters 2-5 & replies

The Five Ways of St. Thomas in proving the existence of

The Cosmological Argument

Aquinas 5 Proofs for God exists

Philosophy of Religion. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Proof of the Necessary of Existence

The Cosmological Argument

Philosophy & Religion

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

The Unmoved Mover (Metaphysics )

McKenzie Study Center, an Institute of Gutenberg College. Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree.

New Chapter: Philosophy of Religion

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

PHIL 370: Medieval Philosophy [semester], Coastal Carolina University Class meeting times: [date, time, location]

Chapter Summaries: Three Types of Religious Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

PHILOSOPHY ESSAY ADVICE

Baha i Proofs for the Existence of God

A level Religious Studies at Titus Salt

Table of x III. Modern Modal Ontological Arguments Norman Malcolm s argument Charles Hartshorne s argument A fly in the ointment? 86

The Five Ways. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Question 2) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006) Question 2. Does God Exist?

QUESTION 47. The Diversity among Things in General

RCIA 2 nd Class September 16, 2015

Harry A. Wolfson, The Jewish Kalam, (The Jewish Quarterly Review, 1967),

Introduction to Philosophy Practice Final Exam Spring 2018

Descartes' Ontological Argument

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

1/9. Leibniz on Descartes Principles

Year 12 A Level Taster Lesson

Thomas Aquinas on the World s Duration. Summa Theologiae Ia Q46: The Beginning of the Duration of Created Things

Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017

because He has revealed Himself in His Word (Genesis 1:1) and in the world of His

Philosophical Issues in Physics PHIL/PHYS 30389

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

3 The Problem of Absolute Reality

AUSTIN GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THEOLOGY. BOOK REVIEW OF Great is the Lord: Theology for the Praise of God by Ron Highfield SYSTEMATIC CHRISTIAN DOCTRINE

The Cosmological Argument for the Existence of God

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

Aquinas, Hylomorphism and the Human Soul

GOD AND THE PRINCIPLE OF SUFFICIENT REASON

Augustine, On Free Choice of the Will,

Cartesian Aseity in the Third Meditation

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

Christian Apologetics The Classical Arguments

John Buridan on Essence and Existence

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Philosophy Quiz 01 Introduction

5 A Modal Version of the

The Ontological Argument

St. Anselm s versions of the ontological argument

[1968. In Encyclopedia of Christianity. Edwin A. Palmer, ed. Wilmington, Delaware: National Foundation for Christian Education.]

First Principles. Principles of Reality. Undeniability.

AS-LEVEL Religious Studies

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

DR. LEONARD PEIKOFF. Lecture 3 THE METAPHYSICS OF TWO WORLDS: ITS RESULTS IN THIS WORLD

What Must There be to Account for Being?

AKC Lecture 1 Plato, Penrose, Popper

Truthmakers for Negative Existentials

Do you have a self? Who (what) are you? PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2014

Transition: From A priori To Anselm

GCE Religious Studies Unit C (RSS03) Philosophy of Religion June 2009 Examination Candidate Exemplar Work: Candidate A

I Don't Believe in God I Believe in Science

Teleological: telos ( end, goal ) What is the telos of human action? What s wrong with living for pleasure? For power and public reputation?

Class 11 - February 23 Leibniz, Monadology and Discourse on Metaphysics

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

*If you are an individual candidate, taking this test away from a school or college, please write the name of your examination centre in this box.

We [now turn to the question] of the existence of God. By God I shall understand a

Thomas Aquinas The Treatise on the Divine Nature

Aquinas Cosmological argument in everyday language

Previous Final Examinations Philosophy 1

AS Philosophy and Ethics

Small Group Assignment 8: Science Replaces Scholasticism

Questions on Book III of the De anima 1

Book Review: From Plato to Jesus By C. Marvin Pate. Submitted by: Brian A. Schulz. A paper. submitted in partial fulfillment

St. Thomas Aquinas Excerpt from Summa Theologica

On Finitism and the Beginning of the Universe: A Reply to Stephen Puryear. Citation Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2016, v. 94 n. 3, p.

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents

Transcription:

Aquinas, The Five Ways 1. Preliminaries: Before offering his famous five proofs for God, Aquinas first asks: Is the existence of God self-evident? That is, if we just sat around thinking about it without observing anything about the world could we know with certainty that God exists? Some things are self-evident. For instance, <All triangles have 3 sides>. If you knew the meanings of all of the terms, you d just automatically see that this statement is certainly true even if you had never observed anything in the world. That is because 3-sided is included in the very DEFINITION of triangle. [Note: Strictly speaking, Aquinas DOES think that existence is included in the very definition of God. As we ll see, he defends Avicenna s view that God s essence IS existence. In that case, God s existence IS self-evident. However, he thinks that this won t be very obvious to anyone unless we ve already proven God s existence in some other way first.] Aquinas doesn t think knowledge of God is like this. He thinks that proofs for God s existence require a starting point in creation. We OBSERVE something in the world, and then reason from there to God. Namely, we reason from the EFFECTS (creatures) to their CAUSE (God). We can t gain a PERFECT knowledge of God by this method (since in this case the cause is infinitely superior to its effects). But we can at the very least come to know THAT a cause exists, even if we can t know fully WHAT that cause is like. Anselm & Augustine: Aquinas dismisses Anselm s ontological argument, saying only that one cannot prove that something exists in reality based merely on the fact that it exists in one s mind. He dismisses Augustine s truth-based argument even more quickly. He agrees that the existence of truth is self-evident. [To deny the existence of truth is selfdefeating, since what you d really be saying is that It is true that there is no truth.] However, he doesn t think it s self-evident that there is some ultimate Truth, such that this Truth = God. 2. The 1 st and 2 nd Way: These are taken from Aristotle. The starting point of Aquinas s first way is that we observe motion, or change. Things change all the time. They take on new properties, like shapes, colors, motions, and so on. But, nothing changes itself. Every change is caused by something external. For instance, consider a billiard ball sitting motionless. It cannot just impart motion to itself. Rather, it starts moving only when motion is imparted to it by something ELSE. 1

Aquinas then reasons that there must be a FIRST mover. Here s why. Consider this toy (called a Newton s cradle ): The first ball imparts motion to the next, and it translates on down the chain to the last ball. But, now imagine that we remove the first ball or rather, the first motion. What happens? Nothing, right? So, it seems to follow that, if there is no first mover in a chain of motions, or changes, then there will be no motions or changes at all. You might say, What if the series just goes back and back forever, without beginning? Well, just ask: Does a beginningless series of movers have a FIRST mover? Obviously not. So, then, our claim above is not met. The chain never gets started, and there will still be no motions or changes at all. So, there MUST be a beginning. [This does NOT mean that Aquinas thinks that an infinite series of motions is impossible. Rather, there would still need to be something to put that WHOLE series INTO motion.] Think of it another way: Imagine a bunch of interconnected gears. If one moves, the rest will move. But, unless someone inserts a crank into one of them and starts turning it, none of them will move. In short, without an external MOVER, the gears will remain motionless. Adding an INFINITE number of gears does not change this fact. For, an infinite number of interconnected gears still requires an EXTERNAL source of motion (e.g., someone to turn the crank). 2

The conclusion is that there must be a first mover, which was not itself moved by anything prior. And we call that God. Here it is in argument form: 1. Things move, or change. 2. But, nothing can move or change itself. It requires an external cause. 3. If there were no first mover in the chain of motions (i.e., changes), then there would be no motions at all. 4. Therefore, there must be a First Mover, which itself is unmoved by an external cause. And this is God. (Aristotle called it the Prime Mover, Unmoved ) The 2 nd Way: The second way is exactly like the first, except that it begins with the observation that things come into existence. But, again, nothing can be the cause of its own existence. For then a thing would have to exist prior to its own existence, which is absurd. And if there is no first cause in the chain of causes, then nothing would ever come into existence at all. Therefore, there must be a First Cause. And this is God. In short, just replace move with begins to exist in the argument above. [Which is stronger? Compare premise 2 of each argument. What do you think?] 3. The 3 rd Way: This one is reminiscent of Avicenna s argument, which went like this: 1. Everything that exists is either contingent (i.e., requiring an external cause for its existence) or necessary (i.e., not requiring an external cause for its existence, since its essence by itself entails its existence). 2. Something contingent exists (e.g. tables, trees, you). 3. The set of all contingent beings is itself contingent (since, if all of a thing s parts are contingent, then the whole is contingent); i.e., it must have an external cause. 4. Therefore, a necessary being exists (since a cause that is NOT a member of the set of all contingent beings can only be a necessary being). And this is God. Again, the basic idea is that, if there is no NECESSARY being to (so to speak) anchor the existence of all of the contingent beings, then the existence of contingent beings remains unexplained. So, not ALL beings can be contingent. Misinterpretation? However, Aquinas is often interpreted differently here. Many think that his reason for thinking that not every being can be contingent is this: If there were all and only contingent beings, there could be no beginning. But, if the universe were beginningless, then an infinite amount of time would have 3

passed already. But, over the course of an infinite amount of time, EVERY possibility is realized. But, if everything is contingent (i.e., possibly fails to exist), then one possibility is that ALL of the contingent beings fail to exist at the same time in which case there would be nothing. In short, if everything is contingent, then every single possibility would have been realized by now in which case, everything would have winked out of existence by now, and then there would presently be nothing. This is obviously false, so not ALL beings are contingent beings. [Is this REALLY the correct interpretation of Aquinas? What do you think?] Motivation: Here, Aquinas seems to assume (but not explicitly state) the following principle: Given an infinite amount of time, all possibilities will be realized. Why would anyone think this? Well, consider The Infinite Monkey Theorem: A chimpanzee sitting at a typewriter for eternity randomly banging out letters would eventually type Shakespeare s Hamlet in its entirety. Problem: But, another possibility is that the collection of all possible beings DON T go out of existence (e.g., if each replaces itself before going out of existence). But, that possibility is incompatible with the possibility that all possible beings DO go out of existence. So, the principle stated above is clearly false. (In short, clearly not EVERY possibility will be realized, given an infinite amount of time, since two of the possibilities are logically incompatible.) [Avicenna sort of pitches his cosmological argument as if it is self-evident. Technically, we DO have to observe something about the world namely, something exists. However, as we ll see later, Avicenna thinks that your own existence is self-evident. One cannot coherently deny it. And from there, it should be self-evident that anything that exists must either be necessary or contingent. Etc. For this reason, some have claimed that Avicenna s argument is closer to being an ontological argument than a cosmological argument.] 4. The 4 th Way: This one is inspired by both Aristotle and Plato. Here, Aquinas begins with the observation that various attributes come in degrees. Things can be more or less true, more or less good, and so on. But, if things are more or less like X, then there must be a STANDARD against which being-like-x is measured. For instance, if we all made drawings of Thomas Jefferson, some would look more like him and others less like him. But, we can say this only because there is a STANDARD against which we are measuring our drawings. Namely, the actual Thomas Jefferson. Similarly, if we say that things are more good or less good, then there must be a STANDARD of goodness that we are measuring things against; a MOST good thing that is absolutely perfect. And a MOST true thing, and so on. And this is God. 4

[Problems: First, why does the entity at the top of each scale need to be the SAME entity? For instance, perhaps there is a most wise thing and a most good thing and a most beautiful thing and so on but why must all of these all be included in ONE being? Second, there seem to be all sorts of scales. Is there a hottest thing? A greenest thing? A most disgusting thing? Etc. Is God at the top of these scales too? Reply: At the very least, Aquinas DOES seem to think there is a hottest thing and it s not God, but FIRE. So, is the idea that the standards against which concrete, material properties (e.g., hotness, greenness) are measured are found in Earthly things, but the standards against which abstract perfections are measured (e.g., goodness, wisdom) could only be something God-like?] [Problem of Evil: Interestingly, Aquinas gives a brief refutation of the Problem of Evil (i.e., that the existence of evil disproves the existence of a good God). His reply is simply that a good God could coherently allow some evil if doing so brings about an even greater good.] 5. The 5 th Way: This is a teleological argument (e.g., Averroes). [Note: The first 3 ways are, roughly, about efficient causes. Meanwhile, the 4 th way is, roughly, about formal causes. Here, the 5 th way is about final causes.] Here, Aquinas reasons from the observation that everything seems to have a telos; that is, a purpose, or end. But, things act or are arranged, or are ordered toward some end if there is an Arranger or an Orderer which gives things purposes, or ends. Therefore, there exists some intelligent grand Designer of everything in the universe. Notice that Aquinas s teleological argument does not focus on the fact that the universe seems suited to human life, as Averroes s does, but rather on the fact that things THEMSELVES are orderly. Each thing in the universe seems to have an end. In contemporary language, we might say that everything in the universe obeys physical laws, such that all things act in regular, orderly ways. Matter ALWAYS attracts other matter. Light ALWAYS travels in straight lines*, and at the same speed (*caveat: space itself is usually curved). Put 79 protons, 79 electrons, and 118 neutrons together into atoms and you will ALWAYS get gold. Etc. The world is ridiculously orderly! [For a crash course on Aquinas s first four ways, go here. But, that video seriously misrepresents and mis-interprets Aquinas in a number of ways. So, for an excellent reply to the first video, go here. (And for a lengthy discussion of ONLY the 3 rd way which is basically Avicenna s argument for the Necessary of Existence go here.)] 5