Daniel Simpson and Alan Wallace s Dialogue on Buddhist meditation and the cognitive sciences

Similar documents
Past Lives - How To Prove Them

On the hard problem of consciousness: Why is physics not enough?

Chiara Mascarello, Università degli Studi di Padova

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia

Religion and Science: The Emerging Relationship Part II

Strange bedfellows or Siamese twins? The search for the sacred in practical theology and psychology of religion

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Behavior and Other Minds: A Response to Functionalists

TOWARD A SYNTHESIS OF SCIENCE AND SPIRITUALITY

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

A Quick Review of the Scientific Method Transcript

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

2011 FIRETHROAT PRESS LLC ALL RIGHTS RESERVED

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

K.V. LAURIKAINEN EXTENDING THE LIMITS OF SCIENCE

For an overview, see Dan Goleman s article in the New York Times, February 5, 2003.

FOREWORD: ADDRESSING THE HARD PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS

1990 Conference: Buddhism and Modern World

PROSPECTIVE TEACHERS UNDERSTANDING OF PROOF: WHAT IF THE TRUTH SET OF AN OPEN SENTENCE IS BROADER THAN THAT COVERED BY THE PROOF?

Descartes to Early Psychology. Phil 255

Ibuanyidanda (Complementary Reflection), African Philosophy and General Issues in Philosophy

EMPIRICISM & EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY

Structure and essence: The keys to integrating spirituality and science

Sounds of Love. Intuition and Reason

Experiences Don t Sum

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

BEYOND CONCEPTUAL DUALISM Ontology of Consciousness, Mental Causation, and Holism in John R. Searle s Philosophy of Mind

The evolution of the meaning of SCIENCE. SCIENCE came from the latin word SCIENTIA which means knowledge.

Written by Rupert Sheldrake, Ph.D. Sunday, 01 September :00 - Last Updated Wednesday, 18 March :31

MY IMPRESSIONS FROM READING Gerald L. Schroeder s

Andrew B. Newberg, Principles of Neurotheology (Ashgate science and religions series), Farnham, Surrey, England: Ashgate Publishing, 2010 (276 p.

Briggle, Adam; and Robert Frodeman. Thinking À La Carte. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 7, no. 6 (2018): 8-11.

CONSTRUCTIVE ENGAGEMENT DIALOGUE SEARLE AND BUDDHISM ON THE NON-SELF SORAJ HONGLADAROM

1. Introduction. REVIEW 127. John R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge, Mass., and London: MIT, a Bradford Book, 1992.

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour

Mathematics as we know it has been created and used by

Science and Worldviews

Instructor's Manual for Gregg Barak s Integrating Criminologies. Prepared by Paul Leighton (Boston: Allyn & Bacon, 1997) * CHAPTER 4

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Difference between Science and Religion? - A Superficial, yet Tragi-Comic Misunderstanding

Debate on the mind and scientific method (continued again) on

A note on Bishop s analysis of the causal argument for physicalism.

Possibility and Necessity

Life, Automata and the Mind-Body Problem

ONTOLOGICAL PROBLEMS OF PLURALIST RESEARCH METHODOLOGIES

Development of Thought. The word "philosophy" comes from the Ancient Greek philosophia, which

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

Meaning of the Paradox

The Buddhist Science of Mind

Darwinist Arguments Against Intelligent Design Illogical and Misleading

The Role of Science in God s world

GREAT PHILOSOPHERS: Thomas Reid ( ) Peter West 25/09/18

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Templeton Fellowships at the NDIAS

PHILOSOPHY (413) Chairperson: David Braden-Johnson, Ph.D.

Nature and Grace in the First Question of the Summa

Interview. with Ravi Ravindra. Can science help us know the nature of God through his creation?

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

Please remember to sign-in by scanning your badge Department of Psychiatry Grand Rounds

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Philosophy (PHIL) 1. PHIL 56. Research Integrity. 1 Unit

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

theoryofknowledge.net SAMPLE PACK

Lecture 1 Zazen Retreat 1995

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 11

Chalmers, "Consciousness and Its Place in Nature"

BIBLICAL INTEGRATION IN SCIENCE AND MATH. September 29m 2016

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

POLI 343 Introduction to Political Research

Department of Philosophy

Religious Studies. Name: Institution: Course: Date:

Let s explore a controversial topic DHMO. (aka Dihydrogen monoxide)

Introduction to Deductive and Inductive Thinking 2017

A Buddhist Perspective on Science, Evolution, and Naturalism: Implications for Buddhist- Christian Dialogue

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

Out-of-Body Journeys: Mystical Experience or Psychotic Episode?

Matthew Huddleston Trevecca Nazarene University Nashville, TN MYTH AND MYSTERY. Developing New Avenues of Dialogue for Christianity and Science

Life and ConsCiousness in the universe Geshe Jangchup Choeden

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

DR. LEONARD PEIKOFF. Lecture 3 THE METAPHYSICS OF TWO WORLDS: ITS RESULTS IN THIS WORLD

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2009

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

A Brief Comparison between the Study of the Shroud and the Philosophical Inquiry on God

William James described pragmatism as a method of approaching

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Kant s Copernican Revolution

Can I Believe in the book of Genesis and Science? Texts: Genesis 2:1-9,15; Genesis 1:1-27 Occasion: Ask, series Themes: Science, creationism,

INTRODUCTION. Historical perspectives of Naturalism

Evolution: The Darwinian Revolutions BIOEE 2070 / HIST 2870 / STS 2871

Transcription:

Daniel Simpson and Alan Wallace s Dialogue on Buddhist meditation and the cognitive sciences Introduction: The following exchange between Daniel Simpson and Alan Wallace follows from Daniel Simpson s article Buddhist meditation and cognitive sciences 1 and Alan Wallace s oral response given during a recent lecture in Tuscany. 2 Daniel Simpson: I appreciate your engagement with the article, and I m grateful for your work on how materialism hijacks science. I particularly enjoyed reading The Taboo of Subjectivity and Mind in the Balance. Alan Wallace: In your essay, you wrote, To Wallace s frustration, science dismisses nonphysical influences in organic evolution or in human affairs, despite having no technology that can detect the presence or absence of any kind of consciousness, for scientists do not even know what exactly is to be measured. His critique is sound but he makes few suggestions (apart from endorsing meditation) When I read that, I assumed you hadn t read Mind in the Balance, for in that academic book I explain in quite some detail rigorous methods for exploring the nature, origins, and potentials of consciousness by integrating methods from contemplative and scientific disciplines. I also do so in many of my Dharma books, such as The Attention Revolution and Minding Closely. In your article you refer to panpsychism, which treats consciousness as an intrinsic, fundamental property of reality. I am familiar with Guilio Tononi and Christof Koch s Integrated Information Theory, which is the most sophisticated version of panpsychism I ve seen, but it suffers from serious drawbacks. Koch summarizes this theory as follows: Any complex system has the basic attributes of mind and has a minimal amount of consciousness in the sense that it feels like something to be that system. If the system falls apart, consciousness ceases to be; it doesn t feel like anything to be a broken system. And the more complex the system, the larger the repertoire of conscious states it can experience. As a Buddhist skeptic, my first response is that there is no empirical evidence to support the belief that any system that has even one bit of integrated information has a very minute conscious experience. Rather, this appears to me as an untestable hypothesis and is simply taken as an article of faith, or an unquestioned axiom, which I see no reason to accept. The most crucial flaw in his theory, as I see it, is that he fails to make the all-important distinction between quantitative and qualitative information, where the former is defined as the pattern of organization of matter and energy, and the latter as some pattern of organization and matter and energy given meaning by a living being (or its constituent parts). 3 By conflating quantitative information with qualitative, which is commonly done by materialists, Koch ignores the fact that the latter must be given meaning by a conscious being, and rather assumes that this conscious being emerges when an uncomplex or broken system transforms into a complex system of integrated information. In asserting that such an IIT is conscious, he fails to recognize the point validly made by John Searle: the information in the computer is in the eye of the beholder, it is not intrinsic to the computational system The electrical state transitions of a computer are symbol manipulations only relative to the attachment of a symbolic interpretation by some designer, programmer or user. 4 1 http://www.danielsimpson.info/archive/buddhist-meditatlon-science-lsd 2 http://media.sbinstitute.com/courses/spring2016/79-1-alan-wallace-s-response-to-the-article/ 3 See Bates, Marcia Fundamental Forms of Information Journal of the American Society for Information and Technology [Volume 57, Issue 8], pp. 1033 1045, June 2006. 4 John R. Searle, Consciousness and Language (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 34.]

2 A third flaw is that Tononi/Koch present no cogent theory to explain how the minds of individual complex systems (e.g., the amygdala, hyppocampus, etc.) bind together to form a unified mind of a larger complex system (e.g., a brain). The binding problem has plagued all versions of panpsychism, and no one has solved it. A fourth flaw in this theory is the implausible implication that the Internet is a conscious being, but as you right admit, this is completely speculative. A fifth flaw is there is no explanation of where consciousness comes from when an uncomplex or broken information system becomes an integrated complex system, or what happens to that consciousness when it breaks. Clearly the beginning and end of an integrated complex system are only vaguely defined, and Tononi acknowledges that emergence of subjective feelings from physical stuff appears inconceivable. So if there is no consciousness in an uncomplex or broken information system in the first place, transforming an uncomplex into a complex system or fixing a broken system won t make it conscious. Tononi himself ridicules the idea that mere matter can generate mind. This is a mystery, he says, that is stranger than immaculate conception an impossibility that defies belief. 5 But this is the unavoidable implication when an uncomplex material system transforms into a complex, integrated system. All versions of panpsychism appear to me as the last gasp of materialists trying to explain, or explain away, the existence of consciousness. Again, I think Searle gets it right when he claims, It would be difficult to exaggerate the disastrous effects that the failure to come to terms with the subjectivity of consciousness has had on the philosophical and psychological work of the past half century. In ways that are not at all obvious on the surface, much of the bankruptcy of most work in the philosophy of mind and a great deal of the sterility of academic psychology over the past fifty years...have come from a persistent failure to recognize and come to terms with the fact that the ontology of the mental is an irreducibly first-person ontology. And yet in an apparent fit of amnesia, he makes the bizarre claim in the same work, Consciousness is, thus, a biological feature of certain organisms in exactly the same sense of biological in which photosynthesis, mitosis, digestion, and reproduction are biological features of organisms. 6 Over the past 2,500 years, Buddhist contemplatives have fully recognized and come to terms with the fact that the ontology of the mental is an irreducibly first-person ontology, and they have devised very sophisticated ways of training attention and introspective skills to probe deeply into the origins and nature of consciousness. On the basis of such experiential research, they have concluded that each human mind emerges from an individual, subtle continuum of consciousness that precedes the formation of the brain and continues after brain death. This deeper dimension of consciousness can be accessed through rigorous meditative training in highly focused attention and introspection. By so doing, one can gain access to past-life memories, the validity of which has been rigorously tested by contemplatives. There is further supportive scientific evidence in studies of near-death experiences (e.g. Sam Parnia) and reports of past-life recall in children (e.g. Ian Stevenson & Jim Tucker). For many centuries, Hindu, Taoist, Jewish, Muslim, Christian, and Shamanic contemplatives have made similar claims, not to mention Pythagoras, Socrates, Plato, and Plotinus. 5 6 Phi: A Voyage from the Brain to the Soul (2012) John R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 1994, pp. 93 & 95).

3 As far as I can tell, the scientific community has systematically refused to investigate or even acknowledge the existence of such claims with an open mind. But as Richard Feynman cogently advises, It is only through refined measurements and careful experimentation that we can have a wider vision. And then we see unexpected things: we see things that are far from what we would guess far from what we could have imagined.... If science is to progress, what we need is the ability to experiment, honesty in reporting results the results must be reported without somebody saying what they would like the results to have been... One of the ways of stopping science would be only to do experiments in the region where you know the law. But experimenters search most diligently, and with the greatest effort, in exactly those places where it seems most likely that we can prove our theories wrong. In other words we are trying to prove ourselves wrong as quickly as possible, because only in that way can we find progress. 7 To my mind, this claim by centuries of contemplatives and philosophers and recent scientific studies suggests the need for research involving sophisticated, sustained training in first-person, contemplative methods to complement third-person, scientific methods. Such research should examine the broadest possible range of states of consciousness, and be conducted by skeptical, rigorous, open-minded psychologists, neuroscientists, physicists, philosophers, and contemplatives. To enable such research, a network of research facilities should be created for training professional contemplatives in collaborative research with scientists and philosophers. Daniel Simpson: I think you re right that Richard Davidson is doing what he can to ride the edge of the paradigm, albeit accepting its constraints. Perhaps he could be encouraged to be a little more forthright, like Jay Garfield. 8 Alan Wallace: It s a step in the right direction, but what Garfield refuses to consider is that Buddhist philosophy, unlike Western philosophy, has empirical means to test its hypotheses, including the idea that it s possible to transcend the limitations of the conceptual mind. So, just as Western scholars of religion have appropriated Buddhism within their discipline, treating it simply as a belief system, now Western philosophers are trying to appropriate Buddhism within their discipline, treating it as one more speculative philosophical tradition one more case of blind men casing out the elephant. Daniel Simpson: Although I agree there s an in-built resistance to contemplative research, I m not sure it s the same as Cremonini s refusal to look through Galileo s telescope. For the analogy to stand, there would need to be a clearly defined experiment that scientists could do on expert meditators, which would give us more evidence for what they experience than what they say about it. Perhaps I m missing something, but I know of no such experiment. As far as I m aware, none has yet been proposed, apart from the sorts of studies that Garfield calls much ado about what we all should have known already ; for example, demonstrating that attention can be trained. Alan Wallace: I m very surprised to read this, for in Mind in the Balance, I clearly set forth two such experiments, the Jiva Project and the Alaya Project, for which I have attached the summaries. The very notion that the only way to proceed is to present a clearly defined experiment that scientists could do on expert meditators assumes that scientists alone have robust means of exploring the mind, while even the most expert meditators have only their (misleading) subjective impressions. Cremonini refused to look through a telescope on ideological grounds, for in his view (and in order for him to keep his job) the beliefs of Aristotle could not be challenged, regardless of any first-person observations that might be made through a telescope. Richie Davidson has adopted a similar view (also in order to keep his job and his standing within the materialistic scientific community), refusing to question the metaphysical assumption that all possible states of consciousness and mental activities are nothing more than activities of the brain. Giulio Libri, on the other hand, refused to look through a telescope for fear that whatever he might see would be nothing more than an optical illusion created by his brain. Psychologist Anne Treisman and philosopher Jay Garfield likewise refuse to take seriously any first-person claims made by even the most advanced meditators. The common point is that psychologists, neuroscientists, and 7 8 http://www.nytimes.com/2016/05/11/opinion/if-philosophy-wont-diversify-lets-call-it-what-it-reallyis.html Richard P. Feynman, The Character of Physical Law (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1967), 127, 148, 158.

4 philosophers refuse to look through the telescope of contemplative inquiry into the nature and potentials of the mind, for this would require years of rigorous meditative training (comparable to earning a Ph.D. in any of their disciplines). It s not as easy as simply looking through a telescope that someone else has made for you. Daniel Simpson: You mention the exposure of Mind & Life scientists to Tibetans who speak about siddhis and previous lives and characterize their response as if I don t know it, you don t know it. I m not sure that s accurate. Is it not also possible to accept that contemplatives may know it while noting it can t be confirmed, except by taking people s word for it? And what they say is a different form of evidence to that which can be verified by other means. Alan Wallace; We re back to the issue of: are you willing to look through the telescope of highly developed samadhi to explore the potentials of the mind that are hidden as long as the mind is untrained? There are very few scientists who acknowledge that contemplatives may have made discoveries about the mind and its role in nature, even if scientists can t confirm those discoveries with physical measurements. This would be like Cremonini and Libri admitting that those who make ground-breaking discoveries by looking through telescopes may know it, but they can t be confirmed by people who refuse to look through telescopes. Daniel Simpson: The same applies to what contemplatives say about perception. I don t think it s a case of either Jay Garfield s right or they re all wrong. I appreciate you were speaking tongue in cheek, but is there not a middle way here? Even if scientists were to study the most accomplished of practitioners, how might it be proven that they can perceive without inferential processes and the other forms of filter Garfield mentions? Alan Wallace: The spectrum of contemplative insights ranges from ones that are deeply embedded in conceptual frameworks to those with thinner and thinner veils of conceptualization. This entire spectrum is explained in great detail in the professional contemplative literature of Buddhism. While scientists who refuse to look through the telescope of advanced stages of non-conceptual samadhi may study the brains and behavior of those who have mastered such contemplative states, and they may draw inferences from the contemplatives first-person reports, they will remain as much outsiders to this realm of the mind as medieval scholastics to advances in astronomy. The obvious point that Treisman and Garfield overlook is that all their own observations are totally embedded within conceptual frameworks that filter and often distort their perceptions. So what are the grounds for being more skeptical of contemplative discoveries than they are of scientific discoveries and philosophical insights? Imagine a group of neuroscientists who took an interest in advanced mathematics and decided the way to explore the validity of discoveries by the most accomplished mathematicians is to explore their brains and behavior and conduct interviews with them. Obviously, they will remain in the dark unless and until they are actually willing to undergo years of training in advanced mathematics. Daniel Simpson: To move the conversation forward, I think it would help to frame what needs to change in terms of research that might be done. It sounds like you re proposing this starts by encouraging scientists to engage more deeply in meditative practice. Yet whatever they observed would be dismissed by peers as anecdotal, and discussing it may even get them excommunicated. Alan Wallace: Unfortunately, you re quite right, and this was exactly the case of those medieval scholastics who dared to look through telescopes. As Max Planck famously commented, Science advances one funeral at a time. Closed-minded materialists who have based their entire careers on their metaphysical beliefs will never budge, but they will die off over time, leaving the field open for young, open-minded scientists to forge ahead where they dared not go. Daniel Simpson: Of course, this prospect shows the current paradigm is too rigid. But I don t really see what contemplative science consists of, beyond promoting meditation. That s no bad thing, but it wouldn t help communicate what people find, or prove its validity to anyone else. And despite the constraints on science, there s no one stopping us from pursuing it: we just need to practice. Alan Wallace: I believe I ve addressed those qualms above, and for further clarification I attach a set of slides on What constitutes compelling evidence and for whom? that make my point even clearer. Daniel Simpson: You claim that Buddhist philosophy, unlike Western philosophy, has empirical means to test its

5 hypotheses, including the idea that it s possible to transcend the limitations of the conceptual mind. Unless scientists are able to verify this objectively, it s not going to change the current paradigm. No experiment exists which could do so. Even if scientists are willing, as you propose, to change their own minds through meditative practice, what they experience would not conclusively prove that they re perceiving non-conceptually, for the reasons discussed by Garfield s article. 9 To argue otherwise would assert that first-hand evidence trumps all other data. And if that s the case, why bother engaging with scientists? It would be sufficient to share Buddhist teachings. Alan Wallace: I doubt that many people will care whether or not it s possible to transcend the conceptual mind, and even fewer will care whether scientists have verified this. Scientists commonly overestimate how much their views matter to the general public. I m convinced that the fact that science illiteracy in the U.S. is so high with more than 40% of the public believing in a literal reading of the Genesis account of creation is due in large part to the scientific community s insistence on force-feeding the beliefs of materialism as they dish out reports of their latest discoveries. Materialism is so morally and intellectually repugnant to so many people, that if rejecting that belief system means they need to chuck out science as a whole, then so be it. I m sure it s no mere coincidence that Christian fundamentalism arose during the late nineteenth century, exactly when scientific materialism first began to dominate all of scientific research, education, and media coverage of scientific advances. I m amazed that so few scientists are aware that their own reductionist views so hinder the acceptance of scientific discoveries by the general public. The value of contemplative inquiry doesn t hinge on the one issue of whether or not contemplative insights transcend concepts. First, we should bear in mind that all scientific observations and conclusions are made within the confines of the conceptual mind, and no one seems bothered by that. And William James, who was such a champion of the first-person perspective when it comes to exploring the mind, freely acknowledged, introspection is difficult and fallible; and... the difficulty is simply that of all observation of whatever kind... The only safeguard is in the final consensus of our farther knowledge about the thing in question, later views correcting earlier ones, until at last the harmony of a consistent system is reached. 10 The third-person, cognitive/behavioral methods of psychology and the physiological methods of neuroscience may shed light on aspects of the mind that are not accessible to the first-person methods of contemplative science, and vice versa. All I m suggesting is that all three approaches be employed and integrated, as William James advocated more than a century ago. I m firmly convinced that Buddhist and other contemplatives have made fundamental discoveries about the nature, origins, and potentials of the mind that are hidden to researchers who confine their observations to the brains and behavior of ordinary individuals. If Buddhist contemplatives have discovered truths, for example, about the existence of a subtle continuum of consciousness that carries on from one life to the next, then these truths should be made public and shared with everyone. So I m now working with scientists to collaborate in long-term research with highly trained contemplatives, in which the scientists and contemplatives will treat each other as fellow professionals, rather than scientists denigrating contemplatives by treating them as mere subjects for their research. Daniel Simpson: Although materialism places little value on subjective evidence, it doesn t stop anyone learning to meditate, or choosing to value their own experience. Alan Wallace: Yes, but relegating contemplative insights to mere subjective evidence leaves the public with the false notion that science alone sheds light on the nature of reality as a whole, including the mind. It s time to break the monopoly of scientists being seen as the sole arbiters of truth. Scientific discoveries are based on measuring and analyzing objective, physical, quantifiable phenomena, which excludes all nonphysical phenomena from having any significant role in nature. That is nothing more than an epistemological bias that gives us a two-dimensional vision of reality as a whole. To progress to a three-dimensional vision of reality, we must include rigorous observations and analyses of non-physical natural phenomena, at which contemplatives excel, to complement the rigorous observations and analyses of physical phenomena, at which scientists excel. 9 https://www.academia.edu/2833529/ask_not_what_buddhism_can_do_for_cognitive_science_ask_what_cogniti ve_science_can_do_for_buddhism 10 William James, The Principles of Psychology (New York: Dover Publications, 1950), pp. 191-2