Follow Will of the People. Your leftist h. b. ave often d1sgusted b h

Similar documents
Reconstructing Arguments 1. Reconstructing Arguments 3. Reconstructing Arguments 2. HW #4 is due on Thursday Longer than usual (and on ch.

Basic Concepts and Skills!

ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. 1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

Pastor-teacher Don Hargrove Faith Bible Church September 8, 2011

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

Argument Basics. When an argument shows that its conclusion is worth accepting we say that the argument is good.

T. Parent. I shall explain these steps in turn. Let s consider the following passage to illustrate the process:

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Part II: How to Evaluate Deductive Arguments

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

Suppressed premises in real life. Philosophy and Logic Section 4.3 & Some Exercises

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

PHILOSOPHY ESSAY ADVICE

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

2013 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved. 1

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

PRACTICE EXAM The state of Israel was in a state of mourning today because of the assassination of Yztzak Rabin.

A Brief Introduction to Key Terms

Handout for: Ibn Sīnā: analysis with modal syllogisms

How to Write a Philosophy Paper

Deduction. Of all the modes of reasoning, deductive arguments have the strongest relationship between the premises

Introduction to Logic

Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000)

A Primer on Logic Part 1: Preliminaries and Vocabulary. Jason Zarri. 1. An Easy $10.00? a 3 c 2. (i) (ii) (iii) (iv)

In more precise language, we have both conditional statements and bi-conditional statements.

II Plenary discussion of Expertise and the Global Warming debate.

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Are There Moral Facts

2 MC-P ARGUMENT OUTLINING

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Transition to Quantified Predicate Logic

Portfolio Project. Phil 251A Logic Fall Due: Friday, December 7

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

The SAT Essay: An Argument-Centered Strategy

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Venn Diagrams and Categorical Syllogisms. Unit 5

Testing Fairmindedness

It is thus a logical and basic premise that all assemblies in God s name, also church council meetings, proceed in an orderly way.

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW LOGICAL CONSTANTS WEEK 5: MODEL-THEORETIC CONSEQUENCE JONNY MCINTOSH

Relevance. Premises are relevant to the conclusion when the truth of the premises provide some evidence that the conclusion is true

Complications for Categorical Syllogisms. PHIL 121: Methods of Reasoning February 27, 2013 Instructor:Karin Howe Binghamton University

13.6 Euler Diagrams and Syllogistic Arguments

Introduction to Logic

Argument. What is it? How do I make a good one?

Instructor s Manual 1

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Syllogism. Exam Importance Exam Importance. CAT Very Important IBPS/Bank PO Very Important. XAT Very Important BANK Clerk Very Important

What God Could Have Made

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

Am I free? Freedom vs. Fate

Session 8 DEDUCTION VS. INDUCTION ( PART 1)

Ethics and Science. Obstacles to search for truth. Ethics: Basic Concepts 1

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

3. Detail Example from Text this is directly is where you provide evidence for your opinion in the topic sentence.

EXERCISES: (from

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

14.6 Speaking Ethically and Avoiding Fallacies L E A R N I N G O B JE C T I V E S

Logical Fallacies. Define the following logical fallacies and provide an example for each.

SCAMMED! Assignment: Identify main claim (conclusion) in three different scams and outline argument.

Definite Descriptions: From Symbolic Logic to Metaphysics. The previous president of the United States is left handed.

Persuasive Argument Relies heavily on appeals to emotion, to the subconscious, even to bias and prejudice. Characterized by figurative language,

A Mini Guide to Critical Thinking. Joe Lau

In a previous lecture, we used Aristotle s syllogisms to emphasize the

Statements, Arguments, Validity. Philosophy and Logic Unit 1, Sections 1.1, 1.2

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims).

INDUCTION. All inductive reasoning is based on an assumption called the UNIFORMITY OF NATURE.

Philosophy of Law Summer Session II, 2016

the negative reason existential fallacy

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Paley s Inductive Inference to Design

2014 Examination Report 2014 Extended Investigation GA 2: Critical Thinking Test GENERAL COMMENTS

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Criticizing Arguments

Critical Thinking. The Four Big Steps. First example. I. Recognizing Arguments. The Nature of Basics

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

Overview of Today s Lecture

STILL NO REDUNDANT PROPERTIES: REPLY TO WIELENBERG

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Refutation Paragraphs

Lecture 1: Validity & Soundness

TAF_RZERC Executive Session_29Oct17

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

9694 THINKING SKILLS

Material objects: composition & constitution

Argument Writing. Whooohoo!! Argument instruction is necessary * Argument comprehension is required in school assignments, standardized testing, job

Lecture 6 Kantianism. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Interpreting Arguments

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

e x c e l l e n c e : an introduction to philosophy

Improving Students' "Dialectic Tracking" Skills (Diagramming Complex Arguments) Cathal Woods for 2010 AAPT Meeting.

Transcription:

Philosophy 101 (3/24/11) I ve posted solutions to HW #3 (study these!) HW #4 is due today Quiz #4 is next Thursday This will be re-do of the last quiz (on chs. 3&4) I ll give you the higher of your two scores HW #5 is posted (see schedule page on website) Due on Thurs. 4/7 (7 problems from Chapter 5) (Charitably) Reconstructing Arguments Recognizing arguments vs non-arguments Detecting argument structure(s) in a passage Seeking the strongest arguments expressed Reconstructing Arguments 5.1 This passage (which appeared, at first, to be purely rhetorical) actually contains a surprising amount of argumentation. The main conclusion advanced in the passage is: (C) The editorial (which claimed that (C1) the Supreme Court decision on flag burning was correct, and which claimed that (C2) Bush was wrong to come out against the decision) is incorrect. There are two (independent) lines of argument for (C) here. One line goes against (C1) and the other against (C2), i.e., the first argues that not-(c1) and the second argues that not-(c2). Let s have a look at each of these lines of argument. Reconstructing Arguments 5 The example I gave before of a rhetorical passage was an incomplete excerpt from an actual letter to the editor. Let s look at the whole letter are there arguments in here? Follow Will of the People Your leftist h. b. ave often d1sgusted b h urnmg decision was bh me, ut t e one on the your readers a Even your own survey With this ridiculous editorial gamst the deosion, you come up Can't you see that flag.burn in is ob.. naked down Main Street at noon?.j,; scene--just as obscene as walking expression also? You probably you defend this as freedom of Somewhere we have to draw the,.. proposed doing just that H me President Bush has the will of all patriotic him for responding to th1s decision? Our office holders have an obi". and that is exactly what he is doing.!gatjon to follow the will of the people 5 an ' am sure, to his own outrage at Reconstructing Arguments 5.2 The main conclusion of the first line of argument is: not-(c1) The court s decision that flag burning is protected speech (under the 1st amendment) was incorrect. The stated premise for this conclusion is: (1) Flag burning is obscene (indeed, flag burning is as obscene as walking down Main Street naked at noon-time). This means we ll need to add two implicit premises: (2) If flag burning is obscene, then it is not protected speech under the first amendment. (3) If (1) and (2) are both true, then not-(c1). Thus, we have reconstructed a (valid!) argument for not-(c1), from one stated premise (1), and two implicit premises (2)/(3)...

Reconstructing Arguments 5.3 The main conclusion of the second line of argument is: not-(c2) Bush was right to come out against the decision. The stated premises for this conclusion are: (4) In coming out against the supreme court s decision, Bush was following the will of the people. (5) All office holders are always right to follow the will of the people. (7) A poll of the paper s readers was overwhelmingly against the supreme court s decision. This means we ll need to add an implicit premise: (8) If (7) is true, then the will of the people was against the supreme court decision. We have here a (valid!) argument for not-(c2). Reconstructing Arguments 6 Identifying Conclusions of Arguments If you think you ve got an argument expressed in a passage, you ll first need to identify its conclusion. Some guidelines: Ask yourself: what s the main point of the passage? Conclusions need not be controversial claims they can be about any sort of topic. Longer passages may contain multiple arguments. It can be useful to outline the structure of a passage, if you think there are multiple conclusions being argued for in the passage. Look for conclusion indicators ( therefore, hence, thus ). Try to insert a conclusion indicator, and see if the passage still reads smoothly (as an argument for that claim). Sometimes conclusions are not explicitly stated, or they are stated in an unclear or imprecise (or even misleading!) way. Reconstructing Arguments 5.4 It is helpful to look at a diagram of the structure of the arguments expressed in this passage. (1)+(2)+(3) not-(c1) (C) (7)+(8) (4)+(5) not-(c2) Reconstructing Arguments 7 Identifying Premises of Arguments Ask yourself: what are the author s reasons for believing the conclusion (or what reasons are they offering)? If there are multiple arguments in the passage, be careful to group premises with their associated conclusions. Look for premise indicators. [Or, try to insert premise indicators, and see if the passage still reads smoothly.] Some premises are implicit, and must be articulated by us. Premises can be stated in obscure or unclear ways. Our reconstructions should make such premises clear and precise. Sometimes statements in a passage are unnecessary premises. Some stated premises may be irrelevant to the conclusion (we may omit these if it makes the argument stronger).

Reconstructing Arguments 8 General vs Specific Premises Premises can be either general or specific. Specific premises are claims about individual objects. e.g., Socrates is a man. General premises involve quantifying over groups of objects. There are various types of quantifiers : Some, many, most, all, none, almost all, every, any. Often, specific and general premises are combined in arguments. We ve seen examples from predicate logic. We will reconstruct general premises in standard form: All As are Bs. Most As are Bs. Some As are Bs. Reconstructing Arguments 10 Adding Implicit Premises We have three basic principles to help guide us in the addition of implicit premises (when it is clear that this is needed). Faithfulness: (PF) Add implicit premises that are consistent with the intention of the author of the argument. Charity: (PCI) Add implicit premises that are reasonable to accept rather than implicit premises that are obviously false. Generalization: (PG) When adding a generalization as an implicit premise, add a true wide generalization rather than a true narrow one, and add a true narrow generalization rather than a false wide one. Reconstructing Arguments 9 General vs Specific Premises Here are some examples (to convert into standard form): If something is a bird, then it can fly. The only people who got an A did it by bribing the prof. A person is a student only if that person is registered. Lying is always risky. In most cases, honesty is the best policy. Form: Most As are Bs. Reconstructing Arguments 11 Bar X. Am is a recent law-school graduate who has just been interviewed for a position in a law firm. The interviewer says, "Bar will be a successful lawyer. She's smart and articulate, and she likes to argue." As a first pass, we might try the following reconstruction: ------------------------ 4. Bar will be a successful lawyer. But, this reconstruction is missing a generalization. What generalization should we add here?

Reconstructing Arguments 12 The first thing to try would be something like this: 4. All people who are smart, articulate, and like to argue will be successful lawyers. ------------------------ 5. Bar will be a successful lawyer. At least the argument is valid now (assuming Bar is a person). But, the generalization we added is too wide to be plausible. Why is it clear that this generalization is false? Reconstructing Arguments 15 Why not go even narrower? 5. Bar is a woman. 6. All lawyers who are women and are smart, articulate, and like to argue will be successful lawyers. 7. Bar will be a successful lawyer. (PG) favors true wide over true narrow, unless there is a specific reason to think the author intended the narrower generalization. Reconstructing Arguments 13 This suggests the following amended reconstruction: 5. All lawyers who are smart, articulate, and like to argue will be successful lawyers. 6. Bar will be a successful lawyer. This narrower generalization is more reasonable/likely. (PG) recommends true narrow over false wide. Reconstructing Arguments 14 The principle of charity urges us to find the strongest argument in the vicinity. Consider the following non-deductive alternative: 5. Most lawyers who are smart, articulate, and like to argue will be successful lawyers. 6. Bar will be a successful lawyer. This may be a stronger argument than the deductive rendition. This most generalization is more plausible, to be sure

Reconstructing Arguments 15 Adding Implicit Generalizations (Example #2) Two common mistakes here: (a) leaving out a requisite general premise (b) leaving the quantifier off a general premise Example: Michael must be tall. After all, he s a professional basketball player. Mistake (a) would lead to this incomplete reconstruction: 1. Michael is a professional basketball player. -------------------------------------------------------- 2. Michael is tall. Reconstructing Arguments 17 Two Example Argumentative Passages: Reconstructing Arguments 16 Adding Implicit Generalizations (Example #2) Mistake (b) would lead to this incomplete reconstruction: 1. Michael is a professional basketball player. 2. Professional basketball players are tall. -------------------------------------------------------- 3. Michael is tall. This is still incomplete, since (2) is missing a quantifier. Which quantifier should we add here? All? Most? or some other quantifier? Remember, we want the strongest, plausibly true claim God does not exist. For there is a tremendous amount of pain and suffering in the world. And if God existed, then there would not be this much suffering in the world. For God is supposed to be all-powerful. In addition, he is supposed to be all-knowing, and he is supposed to be all-good. And if he has these qualities, he wouldn t allow so much gratuitous suffering. Bush should not have won the election, since Gore should have won. For Gore won the national popular vote by some 300,000 votes. And he also would have won the popular vote in Florida if the Supreme Court had allowed the re-counts to continue, and surely this is something they ought to have done.