Hume Against Spinoza and Aristotle. Hume Studies Volume XVII, Number 2 (November, 1991) Frank J. Leavitt 208.

Similar documents
A Vindication. Hume Studies Volume XVII, Number 2 (November, 1991) Wim Klever 212.

The British Empiricism


WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

GREAT PHILOSOPHERS: Thomas Reid ( ) Peter West 25/09/18

Kant s Misrepresentations of Hume s Philosophy of Mathematics in the Prolegomena

Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement:

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

ON EFFICIENT CAUSALITY: METAPHYSICAL DISPUTATIONS 17,18, AND 19. By FRANCISCO SUAREZ. Translated By ALFRED J. FREDDOSO. New Haven:

Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

CONTENTS. CHAPTER 1. CHAPTER II. THE PROBLEM OF DESCARTES, -


Instructor Information Larry M. Jorgensen Office: Ladd Hall, room Office Hours: Mon-Thu, 1-2 p.m.

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

The Dialectic Of Enlightment: A Critique Of Recent Spinoza- Hume Scholarship

approach to God, as was proposed by René Descartes, deists, and some modern


WEEK 1: CARTESIAN SCEPTICISM AND THE COGITO

Philosophical Review.

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

Hume on Promises and Their Obligation. Hume Studies Volume XIV, Number 1 (April, 1988) Antony E. Pitson

Of Cause and Effect David Hume

Was Berkeley a Rational Empiricist? In this short essay I will argue for the conclusion that, although Berkeley ought to be

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

A Hobbist Tory: Johnson on Hume Paul Russell Hume Studies Volume XVI, Number 1 (April, 1990)

Inconsistency within a Reconciling Project Antony Flew Hume Studies Volume IV, Number 1 (April, 1978), 1-6.

You may not start to read the questions printed on the subsequent pages of this question paper until instructed that you may do so by the Invigilator

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes.

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2010


The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

Phil 3121: Modern Philosophy Fall 2016 T, Th 3:40 5:20 pm


Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at

A Multitude of Selves: Contrasting the Cartesian and Nietzschean views of selfhood

Treatise I,iii,14: Hume offers an account of all five causes: matter, form, efficient, exemplary, and final cause.

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Course Description and Objectives:

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses. David Hume

McKenzie Study Center, an Institute of Gutenberg College. Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree.

You may not start to read the questions printed on the subsequent pages of this question paper until instructed that you may do so by the Invigilator

HUME S IDEA OF NECESSARY CONNECTION A POSITIVE VIEW AGAINST THE TRADITIONAL MISUNDERSTANDING

This authoritative translation by John Cottingham of the Meditations is taken from the much acclaimed three-volume Cambridge. Descartes: Meditations

History of Education Society

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

Reid Against Skepticism

PHILOSOPHY 111: HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY EARLY MODERN

Descartes, Leibniz, Spinoza: Concept of Substance Chapter 3 Spinoza and Substance. (Woolhouse)

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

The Philosophy Of Spinoza By Benedict de Spinoza, Joseph Ratner

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

Chapter 4. The Categ~ry of Causation in Locke and Hume. 4.1 Introduction. In this chapter, we shall explain, examine and compare the category

Philosophy Courses-1

1/10. Descartes and Spinoza on the Laws of Nature

The Ethics. Part I and II. Benedictus de Spinoza ************* Introduction

IN his paper, 'Does Tense Logic Rest Upon a Mistake?' (to appear

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

1/8. Reid on Common Sense

Lecture 4: Transcendental idealism and transcendental arguments

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

Argumentative Analogy versus Figurative Analogy

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Owen on Humean Reason Don Garrett Hume Studies Volume XXVI, Number 2 (November, 2000)

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature ( ), Book I, Part III.

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2015

Spinoza s Modal-Ontological Argument for Monism

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Philosophy Courses-1

1/6. The Second Analogy (2)

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

PL 406 HISTORY OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY Fall 2009

History of Modern Philosophy

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Hume s Missing Shade of Blue as a Possible Key. to Certainty in Geometry

QUERIES: to be answered by AUTHOR

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

CRITICAL REVIEW OF AVICENNA S THEORY OF PROPHECY

Action in Special Contexts

to representationalism, then we would seem to miss the point on account of which the distinction between direct realism and representationalism was

Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Lend me your eyes; I can change what you see! ~~Mumford & Sons

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Aquinas on Spiritual Change. In "Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind Still Credible? (A draft)," Myles

5AANA003 MODERN PHILOSOPHY II: LOCKE AND BERKELEY


PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Commentary on Professor Tweyman's 'Hume on Evil' Pheroze S. Wadia Hume Studies Volume XIII, Number 1 (April, 1987)

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

Spinoza on the Essence, Mutability and Power of God

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Transcription:

Hume Against Spinoza and Aristotle Frank J. Leavitt Hume Studies Volume XVII, Number 2 (November, 1991) 203-208. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.humesociety.org/hs/about/terms.html. HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the HUME STUDIES archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Each copy of any part of a HUME STUDIES transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. For more information on HUME STUDIES contact humestudies info@humesociety.org http://www.humesociety.org/hs/

Hume Against Spinoza and Aristotlel Frank J. Leavitt! It is always good to try to make peace, to try to resolve differences between what some believe are conflicting points ofview. Nevertheless, sometimes the points of view which are believed to be opposed to each other really do oppose one another and so the most ingenious attempts at reconciliation turn out to have been ill-conceived. Wim Klever has brought considerable scholarship to bear in his attempt to show that Hume and Spinoza were not so far apart as we thought2 It was an especially pleasant surprise to see the comparison of their views on personal identity? for example. And he has made a convincing case for doubt that Hume's "sharp anti-spinozistic utterings" in Thatbe 1.4.5 were really sincere. In my opinion, however, Klever has gone too far in trying to bring together what should have been ler asunder. Some of his points ofthe purportedly common ground shared by Hume and Spinoza are based on what I believe to be a blatant misreading of Spinoza. Other points show a failure to appreciate a fundamental disagreement between Hume and Spinoza on central issues in the old Aristotelian tradition. Hume and Spinoza, like other philosophers of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, can be best understood when one is aware of the Aristotelian background against which they were writing and with which they expected their readers to be familiar. Hume shows familiarity with Aristotelianism in his discussion of the kitient philosophy" at Treatise 1.4.3 as well as in his various remarks about scholasticismb Spinoza'srelationship to Christian Aristotelianism has been discussed by Wolfsons and by myself,' among others. And his relationship to Maimonidea, who was his link to Jewish Aristotelianism, has been discussed by Harvey! I shall base my claim that Hume and Spinoza were much further apart than Klever makes them out to be upon an attempt to identify some scholastic and Aristotelian i8sues and doctrines with respect to which Hume and Spinoza took very different stands. The first thing which I want to draw attention tois Klever'sreading of the scholia to 2 Ethicu 40, which bears on medieval disputes over the nominalistic, conceptualistic and realistic approaches to Aristotle's treatment of the problem of the universals. Since Spinoza allows that universal notions "are not formed by all men in the same way,* Klever Volume XVII Number 2 203

FRANK J. LEAVITl" makes him out to be holding the same position which Hume expresses when he adopts Berkeley's opinion that "all general ideas are nothing but particular ones, annexed to a certain term" (T 17). And Klever claims "Hume and Spinoza are both thorough nominalists."'0 But Klever mimes the point that Hume denies that there are, in addition to particular ideas, universal ones, that is, common notions, while Spinoza clearly admits, in the second scholium to 11 Ethics 40, the difference which Hume denies. According to Spinoza we have (1) confused representations of particular things, and (2) remembered ideas which are 'similar to those through which we imagine things." These latter am ideas of the sort which Hume recognized. But in addition to these two, which Spinoza calls "opinion" and "imagination,. Spinoza claims that we have (3) "notions common to all men, and adequate ideas of the properties of things." These are notions of 'those things which are common to all, and which are equally in a part and in the whole [and which] cannot be conceived except adequately" (2 Ethics 38). These notions, which parallel Descartes'"c1ear and distinct ideas" are the general abstract ideas which Hume denies in Tmutise 1.1.7. There Hume denies that ideas can be general "in their nature" but allows that they can be general "in their representation." To the extent to which Hume'r position can be called "nominalism," the paseagee to which I have referred show that Spinoza, who basically accepted the Cartesian doctrine of clear and distinct ideas, was not a nominalist. Aristotle drew a sharp distinction between imagination and thought in De anima 2.3. Descartes preserved the distinction between imagination and intellection at the beginning of the fourth Meditation, among other places. The passage from the second scholium to 2 Ethics 40, which I have already cited adheres to this unction, which was already heralded in the explanation to 2 Ethics d!k 7 say conception rather than perception because the word perception seems to imply that the mind is paasive in respect of the objecg whereas conception seems to express an activity of the mind." Hume, however, rejects this ancient distinction when he announces his intention to "destroy this artifice," of"this notion of some spiritual andrefin'd perceptions"(t 72). By failing to recognize this point Klever obscures a fundamental Berkeleian-Humean departure from an ancient doctrine, from which Spinoza did not depart. The second point which I want to draw attention to is Klever's reading of Spinoza's discussion of the 'Third Kind of Knowledge." Klever quotes Hume's remark about Spropositions, that are prov'd by intuition or demonstration" (T 95) and hastens to assert, "Spinoza would call this the third kind of knowledge."11 Klever's assertion is, however, totally gratuitous. Spinoza's famous Third Kind of Knowledge "proceeds from an adequate idea of the absolute essence of certain 204 Hume Studies

HUME AGAINST SPINOZA AND ARISTOTLE attributes of God to the adequate knowledge of the essence of things (2 Ethics 40s2), and I am willing to wager that no reader of Hume Studies can recall that Hume ever recognized the existence of a kind of knowledge which is baaed upon an idea of the absolute essence of certain attributes ofgod. I have argued elsewhere that the divine origin of Spinoza s Third Kind of Knowledge makes it clear that Spinoza intends this kind of knowledge to be identical with prophecy, as prophecy is understood in the Iltactatus Theologico-Politicus.12 But a further discussion of this would take me far beyond the purposes of an essay devoted to Hume. Nowhere is the difference between Hume and Spinoza more apparent than in their approaches to the Aristotelian doctrine of causality, which Hume rejected and which Spinoza basically accepted. Klever quotes Spinoza s 2 Ethics 7 ( The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of things? as part of his attempt to back up his claim that both Hume and Spinoza were n~minalists. ~ But not only is Klever totally vague about his intentions as to the connection between 2 Ethics 7 and nominalism, he also fails to appreciate that Hume could not possibly have used the word connection in the way in which Spinoza uses it in 2 Ethics 7. For 2 Ethics 7 is, as Spinoza states in the proof, intended as a direct consequence of 1 Ethics a4: The knowledge of an effect depends on and involves the knowledge of a cause, which is an Aristotelian doctrine of causality the rejectwn of w hich was the occasion fir one of Hum s most brilliunt contributions to philosophy. Let me explain. Aristotle distinguishes between two senses of ne~essity. ~ One is in the sense of violence? The second is that which we appeal to in demonstrations. The first sense ofnecessity, the sense of yviolence: is the power of efficient causes, that is, the power of what causes change of what is changed. 16 The second sense of necessity, that which we appeal to in demonstrations, is also a kind of causal necessity for Aristotle. For Aristotle believed that the relationship between the premises and the conclusion of a demonstration16--or, more strictly speaking, the relationship between the middle term and the conclusion of a syllogistic scientific dem~nstration ~-is a causal relationship. Although Hume s denial of the first of the two kinds of Aristotelian causal necessity, his denial of efficacy, agency, power, fbrce, energy,... productive quulity (T 1571, has been frequently discussed, less attention has been paid to his denial of the second kind of Aristotelian causal necessity. If there is a difference between an empiricist and a rationalist, then it is this denial which makes the difference. One who denies the first kind of Aristotelian causal necessity is merely making a point of empirical observation: there is no such thing as an observed energy which passes between causes and effects. This Volume XVII Number 2 205

FRANK J. LEAVITT is only to claim that there is one less thing-this energy-in the inventory of the empirical world. And this is hardly a claim about which there is much reason for philosophers to get excited. But Hume's rejection of the second kind of Aristotelian causal necessity is unquestionably grounds for excitement. For here Hume rejects a logical doctrine: the Aristotelian belief that there is a connection 'of the kind which we appeal to in demonstrations" (as Aristotle put it) between causes and effecta. Hume, himself, obscures the fact that he is rejecting two distinct kinds of Aristotelian causal necessity. For he claims that 'all causes are of the same kind" and that "there is but one kind of necessity" (T 171). But a close comparison of Hume to the Aristotelian texts previously mentioned shows that Hume is carrying on two separate arguments, of which only one-the sustained argument that we have no impression of power except as a "determination of the thought" (T 166th- to do directly with Aristotle's first kind of necessity, what Aristotle calls "violence" and what Hume calls 'efficocu, agency," etc. Hume's rejection of the second Aristotelian kind of necessity becomes clear when we contrast Hume's language with Aristotle's own. We have, according to Aristotle, unqualified scientific knowledge, as oppoeed to accidental sophistic knowledge, of a thing or fact when we know the cause on which that thing or fact depends." To know a thing's 'essential nature,' Aristotle says, is "the same as to know the cause of a thing's existence."'@ The causal relationship here is a logical relationship of the kind "to which we appeal in demonstrations" such that the very knowledge of the effect depends upon the knowledge of the cause. But it is precisely this relationship the existence of which Hume denies when he says 'there is nothing in any object, cvneider'd in itself, which can afford ua a reaaon fir drawing a conclusion beyond it" (T 139, Hume's emphasis) and that 'there are no objects, which by the mere survey, without consulting experience, we can determine to be the causes of any other" (T 173). It is, however, this second kind of causal necessity which Spinoza affirms at 1 Ethics a4: "he knowledge of an effect depends on and involves the knowledge of a cause? As I have already said, Klever takes 2 Ethics 7 ('The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of things") to be a proposition which Hume could accept.m But Spinoza proves 2 Ethics 7 directly from 1 Ethia a4. So it is clear that for Spinoza the order of ideas parallels the order of things because of the necessary (in Aristotle's second sense) connection between the idea of a thing and the idea of its cause. But for Hume the correspondence between the order of ideas and the order of things cannot be ascribed to any stronger principle than the Association of Ideas, which is certainly not an 206 Hume Studies

HUME AGAINST SPINOZA AND ARISTOTLE 1 Aristotelian necessary connection of the sort which Spinoza adopted, but merely a gentle force, which commonly prevails (T 10). Spinoza and Leibniz were the last greats in the grand old Aristotelian school which distinguished between intellection and imagination and which saw causality as an internal, logical, relation. I I Hume followed Berkeley in rejecting intellection as a separate faculty. And Hume did the most to bring about the acceptance of the modem view of causality as an external relationship reducible to constant conjunction. Kleveis attempt at reconciling Hume to Spinoza obscures fundamental issues in Hume s departure from Aristotelianiam. Ben-Gurwn University of the Negev 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. Thanks to Haim Marantz for helpful suggestions. Wim Klever, %ume Contra Spinoza? lhme Studies 16, no. 2 (November 1990): 89-105. Ibid., 91f. bid., 104. See David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, 2d ed., rev., ed. P. H. Nidditch (1978; reprint, Oxford, 1987), 312 (hereafter cited as TI. In addition to this reference to scholasticism, which Selby-Bigge recognizes in his Index, there are references to the schools or scholasticism on at least the following pages: 40,44,175. Hany Austryn Wolfson, The Philosophy of Spinour (1934; reprint, New York, 1969). See, e.g., p. 9. Rank J. Leavitt, The Christian Philosophy of Benedictus de Spinoza (in Hebrew), DAAT, a Journal of Jewish Philosophy and Kabbakrh 26 (Winter 1991): 97-108. Warren Zev Harvey, Portrait of Spinoza as a Maimonidean, Journal of the History ofphilapophy 19 (1981): 151-72. Translations are taken from Benedict de Spinoza, The Chief Works ofbenedict despinoza, trans. R. H. M. Elwee, 2 vols. (1883; reprint, New York, 1955). The following abbreviations are used when reference is made to the Ethics: a: rudoma; d: definitio; a: scholium. 10. Klever (above, n. 2),94. 11. Ibid., 97. 12. See n. 7, above. Eap. pp. 10%. 13. Klever (above, n. 2),95. 14. Aristotle, Metaphysics, tr. W. D. Rosein, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. RichardMcKeon (New York, 1941), K.8.1064b.34f. All of my references to Aristotle will be to the various translations in this Random House edition of the Oxford translation. Volume XVII Number 2 207

FRANK J. LEAVITT 15. Physice 2.3.1941331. See Aristotle'e diecussion there of the four kinds of causality: (1) material, (2) formal, (3) efficient, and (4) formal. 16. PoeteriorAnuZytics 1.2.711322,711329, tr. G. R. G. Mure. 17. Ibid., 2.2.9OaSf. 18. Ibid., 1.2.71b8ff. 19. Ibid., 2.8.93a4f. 20. Klever (above, n. 2), 95. 208 Hume Studies