Russell on Metaphysical Vagueness

Similar documents
NB: Presentations will be assigned on the second week. Suggested essay topics will be distributed in May.

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

IN his paper, 'Does Tense Logic Rest Upon a Mistake?' (to appear

Tuomas E. Tahko (University of Helsinki)

Mereological Ontological Arguments and Pantheism 1. which draw on the resources of mereology, i.e. the theory of the part-whole relation.

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

NATURALISM AND THE PARADOX OF REVISABILITY

Skepticism and Internalism

A Note on a Remark of Evans *

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

(Some More) Vagueness

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

TRUTH IN MATHEMATICS. H.G. Dales and G. Oliveri (eds.) (Clarendon: Oxford. 1998, pp. xv, 376, ISBN X) Reviewed by Mark Colyvan

CONTRASTIVE EMPIRICISM AND INDISPENSABILITY

Relativism and Indeterminacy of Meaning (Quine) Indeterminacy of Translation

Vagueness. Bertrand Russell

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

Mathematics: Truth and Fiction?

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

What Is Existence? 1. 1 Introduction. João Branquinho University of Lisbon and LanCog Group

Chapter Six. Putnam's Anti-Realism

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

Experiences Don t Sum

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Vagueness and supervaluations

BOOK REVIEWS. The Philosophical Review, Vol. 111, No. 4 (October 2002)

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Varieties of Vagueness *

Conceptual Analysis meets Two Dogmas of Empiricism David Chalmers (RSSS, ANU) Handout for Australasian Association of Philosophy, July 4, 2006

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

Supervaluationism and Fara s argument concerning higher-order vagueness

Against Vague and Unnatural Existence: Reply to Liebesman

Arguments Against Metaphysical Indeterminacy and Vagueness 1 Elizabeth Barnes. Draft, June 2010

Epistemicism, Parasites and Vague Names * vagueness is based on an untenable metaphysics of content are unsuccessful. Burgess s arguments are

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference?

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

Naturalism and is Opponents

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

The knowledge argument purports to show that there are non-physical facts facts that cannot be expressed in

Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

Review of Stewart Shapiro, Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure and Ontology. Øystein Linnebo *

CLASS PARTICIPATION IS A REQUIREMENT

Response to Eklund 1 Elizabeth Barnes and JRG Williams

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Horwich and the Liar

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Philosophy 1760 Philosophy of Language

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Moore s paradoxes, Evans s principle and self-knowledge

Statement of Research

Philosophy 370: Problems in Analytic Philosophy

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages

1 Why should you care about metametaphysics?

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

CURRICULUM VITAE. Matthew W. McKeon

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

PHIL 4800/5800/5801 Fall Core Theoretical Philosophy I and II

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Defending A Dogma: Between Grice, Strawson and Quine

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

5 A Modal Version of the

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Kazuhisa Todayama (Graduate School of Information Science, Nagoya University, Japan)

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Summary of Sensorama: A Phenomenalist Analysis of Spacetime and Its Contents

Fictionalism, Theft, and the Story of Mathematics. 1. Introduction. Philosophia Mathematica (III) 17 (2009),

Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators. Christopher Peacocke. Columbia University

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Transcription:

Russell on Metaphysical Vagueness Mark Colyvan Abstract Recently a fascinating debate has been rekindled over whether vagueness is metaphysical or linguistic. That is, is vagueness an objective feature of reality or is it merely an artifact of our language? Bertrand Russell s contribution to this debate is considered by many to be decisive. Russell suggested that it is a mistake to conclude that the world is vague simply because the language we use to describe it is vague. He argued that to draw such an inference is to commit the fallacy of verbalism. I argue that this is only a fallacy if we have no reason to believe that the world is as our language says. Since vagueness is apparently not eliminable from our language a fact that Russell himself acknowledged an indispensability argument can be launched for metaphysical vagueness. In this paper I outline such an argument. 1 Introduction Like his contributions elsewhere in philosophy, Bertrand Russell s contribution to the vagueness debate is original, insightful, and important. Indeed, his 1923 article Vagueness, appearing in the first volume of The Australasian Journal of Philosophy and Psychology (later to become simply The Australasian Journal of Philosophy), serves to mark the start of modern debates about vagueness, its treatment and its nature. I wish to focus on one aspect of Russell s article: his claim that vagueness is a feature of our language (or more correctly, a feature of the connection between our language and the world); vagueness is not, according to Russell, a feature of the world. He is School of Philosophy, University of Tasmania, GPO Box 252-41, Hobart, Tasmania, 7001, Australia; and Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science, University of California, Irvine, California, USA. Email: mark.colyvan@utas.edu.au. 1

thus opposed to the view that is sometimes called ontological or metaphysical vagueness. I will argue that Russell was a bit quick to reject metaphysical vagueness and that an interesting argument can be mounted in favour of metaphysical vagueness an argument, I claim, Russell ought to have been at least sympathetic to. 2 What is Metaphysical Vagueness? First, it is important to understand what we mean by vagueness in the context of this debate. The standard definition is that an expression is vague iff it gives rise to borderline cases. The prime examples here are predicates such as is red, is tall, and rather famously is a heap. We must be careful to distinguish vagueness in this technical sense from generality, imprecision, ambiguity, and various form of indeterminacy (such as open texture). 1 As stated, the definition leaves it open as to whether the vagueness in the linguistic expressions are features of the expressions alone or this linguistic vagueness arises from a deeper metaphysical vagueness. Exactly what metaphysical vagueness amounts to is an interesting topic in its own right but, presumably, it is the view that reality itself is (in some sense) vague. There are at least two different accounts to be entertained though: the first is that there are vague properties; the second that there are vague objects. The former seems less controversial in that it is committed to an ontology of sharp objects though some of these objects have vague properties. The latter view that there are vague objects is usually thought to be more controversial. For the most part, I will focus on this latter, more radical thesis. So, for present purposes, I take metaphysical vagueness to be the view that the world itself is vague in the sense that it consists of vague objects such as galaxies, neutron stars, human beings and so on. 2 As Mark Sainsbury [21] points out, there are different ways in which an 1 I should note that it is not clear that Russell fully distinguished vagueness from all of these (though see [9]). Nothing I have to say in this paper depends on this though. See [22] for details of the various distinctions. 2 There is much debate over the coherence of vague objects and the related issue of whether there can be vague identity. Most notably here is Gareth Evans famous one page Analysis article [5] and the literature it spawned especially [14]. Meanwhile, others have defended the notion of vague objects [10], [12], [15], [23], [25]. I won t enter into the Evans debate directly; as it turns out, I think it is coherent to posit vague objects. Indeed, later in this paper I will provide an argument for ontological vagueness. 2

object might be thought to be vague. It might be compositionally vague, temporally vague, individuatively vague and so on. 3 For the most part, I ll focus on compositional vagueness where an object x is compositionally vague if x is such that for some y it is vague whether y is a part of x. 4 I should point out that I concentrate on compositional vagueness just to focus the discussion and to help get a grip on what a vague object might be like I do not think that the other ways an object might be vague are any less interesting or that they are any more or less controversial. 3 The Fallacy of Verbalism Russell was of the view that vagueness was essentially a linguistic matter. 5 That is, he thought it a mistake to attribute vagueness to the world. (He called this mistake the fallacy of verbalism.) I can do no better than to quote Russell at this point. There is a certain tendency in those who have realized that words are vague to infer that things also are vague. We hear a great deal about the flux and the continuum and the unanalysability of the Universe, and it is often suggested that as our language becomes more precise, it becomes less adapted to represent the primitive chaos out of which man is supposed to have evolved the cosmos. This seems to me to be precisely a case of the fallacy of verbalism the fallacy that consists in mistaking the properties of words for properties of things. Vagueness and precision alike are characteristics which can only belong to a representation, of which language is an example. They have to do with the relation between a representation and that which it represents. Apart from representation, whether cognitive or mechanical, there can be no such thing as vagueness or precision; things are what they are, and there is an end of it. Nothing is more or less what it is, or to a certain extent possessed of the properties which it possesses. [19, p. 62] It is important to be clear about what Russell means here. His claim that attributing vagueness to the world is to mistake features of the language for 3 See [21] for details. 4 I take this definition from [21]. 5 Actually, he took vagueness to be a property of representations (generally), of which language was but one example. 3

features of the world. More precisely, he is suggesting that the fallacy is that of attributing features of the relation between language and the world, to the world. So the mistake is not so silly as an English speaker attributing Englishness to the world or a Portuguese speaker attributing Portugueseness to the world. It is more like the mathematician who trusts her mathematical formalism too far. 6 She know that the mathematics represents the physical world in certain ways but she treats the formalism as though all features of it represent accurately. 7 To give a simpler example, the fallacy of verbalism is akin to looking at a map of Florianópolis and concluding that Florianópolis is made of paper. Although Russell doesn t provide another example of this fallacy (other than vagueness), I think he has something like the following in mind. Consider an ambiguous term such as Bahia. This term, as commonly used, is ambiguous between the Brazilian state Bahia and its capital, Salvador. Now surely, it is a mistake to conclude from this that this feature of our language reflects a feature of the world there simply isn t a single ambiguous object which is both the state of Bahia and the city of Salvador. Things are what they are: states are states and cities are cities (and, as Russell puts it, there is an end of it [19, p. 62]). An ambiguity is simply a defect in our language and we should draw no metaphysical conclusions from such defects. It is clear, I think, that Russell thought that both vagueness and ambiguity are defects in our language. But there is, perhaps, an important distinction to be made here. Now it seems to me that the fallacy of verbalism is only a fallacy if we have no reason to believe that the world is as our language would have it. The example of Bahia is a good illustration of this. Our best theory of Brazil will distinguish the state of Bahia from the city of Salvador. But what if it didn t? What would we say about ambiguity in the world then? Can we imagine such a case? Plausibly, the word electron is ambiguous between a particle and a wavelette. Moreover, our best theory of such things quantum mechanics does not resolve this ambiguity. In fact, quantum mechanics, arguable, requires such an ambiguity. In light of such cases, it would seem that it is not a fallacy to conclude that the world is 6 It s difficult to say what too far amounts to, because Dirac discovered anti-matter and Maxwell discovered electromagnetic radiation by trusting their mathematical formalisms where others would not have. See [2] and [4] for more on this. 7 Think of the use of continuous mathematics for discrete phenomena such as population growth. 4

ambiguous if our best theories say it is so. 8 Now getting back to vagueness, according to Russell (and many others), vagueness is ineliminable from our language. 9 Indeed, Russell was perhaps the first to fully appreciate both the extent of vagueness in our language and how entrenched it is. He argued that it pervaded all language including our scientific vocabulary and it even infected our logical connectives. He also believed that there was no hope of eliminating vagueness from our language: We can see an ideal of precision, to which we can approximate indefinitely; but we cannot attain this ideal. [19, p. 65] If vagueness is not eliminable from our language and if our best scientific theories are committed to vague objects, it would seem that it is no fallacy to attribute this vagueness to the world. Indeed, naturalistic philosophers, at least, must take their guidance on such matters from our best scientific theories. If those theories require ambiguous or vague terms, then not only do we have no reason to deny the existence of such ambiguous or vague objects, but a positive argument for the existence of such objects begins to emerge. I explore this argument in the next section. 4 An Argument for Metaphysical Vagueness There is a well-known argument in the philosophy of mathematics due to Quine and Putnam called the Indispensability Argument. 10 According to this argument, we ought to believe in the existence of mathematical objects (numbers sets, functions and such) because quantification over such objects is indispensable to our best scientific theories. There has been a great deal of debate about this argument, but I think it is fair to say that it is taken very seriously in philosophy of mathematics even by those who deny its conclusion. I won t go into the details of that argument here, except to say that the conclusion of the last section suggests that a parallel indispensability argument for metaphysical vagueness might be defended. Here is one version of such an argument. 11 8 See [6] for more on vagueness and ambiguity in quantum mechanics. 9 There are also some notable dissenters. For example, W.V. Quine [17] and Susan Haack [7]. 10 See [3] for a detailed presentation and defence of this argument. 11 A version of this argument was first (rather tentatively) put forward in [1]. 5

1. We ought to have ontological commitment to all and only the entities apparently referred to by terms that are indispensable to our (current) best scientific theories. Moreover, we ought to believe those entities to have the properties attributed to them by those theories. 2. Apparently referring terms such as species, neutron stars, and the like are indispensable to our (current) best scientific theories. Moreover, the entities apparently referred to by these terms, according to our best scientific theories, have vague properties. In particular, these theories attribute compositional vagueness to many of the entities in question. Therefore: 3. We ought to (presently) have ontological commitment to vague objects. The first thing to note about this argument is that it is epistemological its conclusion is about what we are licensed to believe; it is not a metaphysical argument about what exists. Still, the conclusion is that we ought to believe in vague objects and this is strong enough to construe it as an argument for such objects. Second, the epistemic normativity is time indexed to the present. That is, the argument is about what we ought to believe now. What we ought to take to exist, presumably, will change in the future as our best scientific theories change. Next, I note that the argument is valid (modulo some concerns about how the modal operator ought to believe behaves), so to resist the conclusion we must reject one or more of the premises. Let s start with the second premise. Not everyone accepts that our best scientific theories indispensably require vague language. Quine and Haack, for example, think that defects such as vagueness can be eliminated by precisifying our scientific vocabulary. It is fair to say, however, that such a precisification is yet to be performed and until such time as it has, it is not clear that we can rid our scientific language of vagueness in the way that Quine and Haack would like. In any case, our main focus here is Russell, and he certainly thought that vagueness was ineliminable. 12 Now it might be argued that, as it stands, there is an equivocation in the second premise of the argument. According to this objection, the equivocation is between (i) our best scientific theories describe certain entities as 12 Though, he might not like the examples of vague objects I give in the second premise. 6

being vague, and (ii) our best scientific theories vaguely describe those entities. Only (i) licenses the conclusion of the argument and yet it is (ii) that is plausible. Moreover, to assume that (ii) entails (i) is simply begging the question (or perhaps committing the fallacy of verbalism). 13 This is a very interesting and serious objection that raises many important issues. Ultimately, I think the objection fails because, with certain caveats in place, it is (i) that is true. Let me elaborate. According to the line of thought outlined in the objection of the previous paragraph, our best scientific theories merely describe certain features of reality vaguely; they do not describe reality as being vague. But to push this line is also begging the question in the other direction this time (i.e. begging it against the supporter of metaphysical vagueness). Have we thus reached a rather unsatisfying stand-off? Not quite. It seems to me that naturalistic philosophers, at least, take our best scientific theories to be describing the world. Moreover, we ought to take these theories at face value (unless we have good reason not to do so). Such attitudes towards science are central to the naturalistic approach to philosophy. 14 But our best scientific theories, when apparently attributing vague properties to certain entities, do not say but the vagueness is not in the world, it s in the representation. Nor, of course, do they say and the vagueness is really in the world, but the point is: they don t have to. The default, naturalistic position is that science is about the world. If we take our best scientific theories at face value they purport to be about vague objects as in (i) above. 15 Now there is much more that can (and should) be said on this important issue. But I will not do that here. My main aim is to present the indispensability argument for metaphysical vagueness, not to rigourously defend it. 16 I hope, however, that I ve at least suggested a way to advance the debate past mutual claims of question begging and, in particular, to lend some support to the plausibility of the second premise of the argument. Now to the first premise. This premise also depends on naturalism; indeed, it is supposed to be a consequence of (Quinean) naturalism and confirmational holism. Very roughly, Quinean naturalism rejects first philosophy and counsels us to turn to science for answers to epistemological questions. 13 I thank Dominic Hyde for raising this objection. 14 I ll have more to say about naturalism in relation to the first premise. 15 Of course we can reinterpret the theories, but without good reason to do this (and the reasons must come from within science), again we violate naturalism. 16 I intend to do that elsewhere. 7

Naturalism thus lies at the heart of the first premise. 17 Naturalism licenses at least the only direction of this premise (and perhaps both). If you think the reverse direction (the all direction) needs something else, confirmational holism is supposed to fit the bill. Confirmational holism is the thesis that we cannot confirm or disconfirm single hypotheses; rather, our statements about the external world face the tribunal of sense experience not individually but only as a corporate body [16, p. 41]. Now it is beyond the scope of this paper to defend these two doctrines here. 18 Suffice to say that I don t think that they are implausible. But in any case, returning to Bertrand Russell: the question is whether he would have accepted the argument above. In the next section, I speculate that he would have had some sympathy with it. 5 Why Russell Should have Embraced Metaphysical Vagueness Despite Russell s rejection of metaphysical vagueness, there is little in the argument of the last section that he would have taken issue with. After all, he saw vagueness as ineliminable from our language including our scientific language. Put slightly differently, he was committed to the view that vague expressions are indispensable to our best theories of logic, mathematics and physics. This is (more or less) premise two of the above argument. But what of premise one? Surely there s a lot of Quinean baggage packed into that premise: baggage that Russell would not accept. In fact, I don t think that there is too much in premise one that Russell would be unhappy with. Indeed, in certain respects, Russell anticipated many distinctive Quinean theses. For example, Russell seems to have been committed to something like the 17 There are, of course, many different kinds of naturalism and Haack [8, chap. 6] has suggested that there is even an ambiguity in the Quinean conception I have in mind. The ambiguity, she suggests, is between philosophy being continuous with science broadly or narrowly construed. She may well be right about this but it doesn t matter for present purposes: vague language seems to be a part of all of science, no matter how broadly or narrowly you construe science. 18 I ve done that elsewhere: [3] is a sustained defence of the mathematical indispensability argument with much of the focus on the defence of Quinean naturalism and confirmational holism. 8

Quinean naturalism (though he called the doctrine realism ). He described this view as the abandonment of the claim to a special philosophic method or a peculiar brand of knowledge to be obtained by its means [20, p. 69]. He went on to say that this new philosophy regards philosophy as essentially one with science and that [i]t conceives that all knowledge is scientific knowledge [20, pp. 69 70]. Moreover, such naturalism (or realism) is just what is needed to support at least one direction of premise one. I ve already suggested that the other direction of premise one may require some form of holism. But once again Russell was committed to at least a moderate degree of semantic holism. This is reflected in his argument for the vagueness of the logical connectives. In effect, he argued that one cannot define such terms independently of the truth conditions of the sentences in which they occur. This is somewhat short of Quine s semantic holism, according to which the unit of meaning is the whole language (or at least large chunks thereof). It is not clear, though, that the above argument requires anything so controversial as semantic holism. I ve argued elsewhere [3, chap. 2] that the mathematical indispensability argument requires the less controversial confirmational holism. Would Russell have accepted this? I m not sure, but at the very least, confirmational holism doesn t seem to be in serious tension with other aspects of Russell s epistemology. So while the indispensability argument presented above is certainly not an argument Russell endorsed (or even considered), it is not too much of a stretch to suggest that it is an argument he might have been persuaded to accept. If all this is right then Russell may have been a bit quick to reject metaphysical vagueness. Moreover, the fallacy of verbalism is only a fallacy when there is no reason to expect that our language truly represents the way the world is. When the language in question is indispensably part of our best scientific theories, things are different. We have every reason to believe that these theories (at least approximately) represent the world, so if these theories are committed to vague objects, then it is no fallacy to posit such objects. 19 19 An earlier version of this paper was presented at the Second Principia International Symposium in Florianópolis, Brazil in August 2001. I thank the participants at that symposium for their valuable contributions and the organisers for a very stimulating conference in a wonderful part of the world. I also gratefully acknowledge the help of Otávio Bueno and Dominic Hyde who read earlier drafts of this paper and gave me many constructive criticisms. I am particularly indebted to Dominic Hyde with whom I ve had many enlightening conversations about vagueness and whose paper [11] inspired me to write this 9

References [1] Beall, JC and Colyvan, M. Looking for Contradictions, The Australasian Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 79 (2001), forthcoming. [2] Colyvan, M. Confirmation Theory and Indispensability, Philosophical Studies, Vol. 96 (1999), 1 19. [3] Colyvan, M. The Indispensability of Mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press, 2001. [4] Colyvan, M. The Miracle of Applied Mathematics, Synthese, Vol. 127 (2001), 265 278. [5] Evans, G. Can there be Vague Objects?, Analysis, Vol. 38 (1978), 208. [6] French, S. and Krause, D. Vague Identity and Quantum Nonindividuality, Analysis Vol. 55 (1995), 20 26. [7] Haack, S. Philosophy of Logics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978. [8] Haack, S. Evidence and Enquiry: Towards Reconstruction in Epistemology. Oxford: Blackwell, 1994. [9] Hyde, D. Rehabilitating Russell, Logic et Analyse Vol. 137 (1992), 139 173. [10] Hyde, D. Vagueness, Ontology and Supervenience, The Monist, Vol. 81 (1998), 297 312. [11] Hyde, D. Supervaluationalism as Necessary and Sufficient for a Paracomplete Enlightened Representationalist Approach to Vagueness, paper delivered to the School of Philosophy, University of Tasmania, September 2000. [12] Hyde, D. Ontological Vagueness. Aldershot: Ashgate, forthcoming. [13] Keefe, R. and Smith, P. Introduction: Theories of Vagueness, in R. Keefe and P. Smith, Vagueness: A Reader. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1997, pp. 1 57. one. 10

[14] Lewis, D.K. Vague Identity: Evans Misunderstood, Analysis, Vol. 48 (1988), 128 30. [15] Parsons, T. Entities without Identity, in J.E. Tomberlin (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, 1: Metaphysics. Atascadero, California: Ridgeview, 1997, pp. 1 19. [16] Quine, W.V. Two Dogmas of Empiricism, in From a Logical Point of View, second edition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (Massachusetts), 1980, pp. 20 46. [17] Quine, W.V. What Price Bivalence?, Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 78 (1981), 90 95. [18] Quine, W.V. Five Milestones of Empiricism, in Theories and Things. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1981, pp. 67 72. [19] Russell, B. Vagueness, Australasian Journal of Philosophy and Psychology, Vol. 1 (1923), 84 92. Reprinted in R. Keefe and P. Smith, Vagueness: A Reader. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1997, pp. 61 68. (Page references are to the reprint.) [20] Russell, B. Philosophy in the Twentieth Century, reprinted in Sceptical Essays, Sixth impression. London: George Allen and Unwin, 1956, pp. 54 79 (first published in 1924). [21] Sainsbury, R.M. What is a Vague Object?, Analysis, Vol. 49 (1989), 99 103. [22] Sorensen, R.A. The Ambiguity of Vagueness and Precision, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 70 (1989), 174 83. [23] Tye, M. Vague Objects, Mind, Vol. 99 (1990), 535 557. [24] Williamson, T. Vagueness. London: Routledge, 1994. [25] Zemach, E.M. Vague Objects, Noûs, Vol. 25 (1991), 323 340. 11