Kierkegaard and Socrates

Similar documents
DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE

Søren Kierkegaard Philosophical Fragments, Concluding Scientific Postscript excerpts 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/10/13 12:03 PM

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

T he Paradox in Fear and Trem bling

Wittgenstein, Kierkegaard and the Unspeakable

Fear and Trembling Chapter Summaries

A few words about Kierkegaard and the Kierkegaardian method:

The Human Deficit according to Immanuel Kant: The Gap between the Moral Law and Human Inability to Live by It. Pieter Vos 1

Fear and Trembling: The knight of faith and movement. (Lecture 3 accompanying notes for reading of the Preamble from the heart )

Understanding the burning question of the 1940s and beyond

A Backdrop To Existentialist Thought

Kierkegaard s amphibolous conjunction of joy and sorrow and his literary theory

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Chapter 24. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Concepts of Being, Non-being and Becoming

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

Investigating the concept of despair and its relation with sin in Kierkegaard's view

Liberal Theology Friedrich Schleiermacher ( ). The Father of Liberal theology. Pastored the large and influential Trinity Church

obey the Christian tenet You Shall Love The Neighbour facilitates the individual to overcome

Week 4: Jesus Christ and human existence

Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

EXISTENTIALISM. Wednesday, April 20, 16

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Chapter Summaries: Three Types of Religious Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

EXISTENTIALISM EXISTENTIALISM - METAPHYSICS EXISTENTIALISM - METAPHYSICS

Kierkegaard As Incomplete Ironist

Moriah. Sacrifice him there as a burnt offering on one of the mountains I will tell you about." -Genesis 22:1-2

Kierkegaard s Allusions to Abraham and Socrates in Practice in Christianity

Previous Final Examinations Philosophy 1

Origin of the Idea of God. TEXT: Acts 17:22-31 THESIS:

The Power of Critical Thinking Why it matters How it works

Chapter 25. Hegel s Absolute Idealism and the Phenomenology of Spirit

Philosophy 1100 Honors Introduction to Ethics

Philosophy 1100 Introduction to Ethics

IS YOUR FAITH THE FAITH THAT GOD IS LOOKING FOR. bodily form, 10 and in Him you have been made complete, and He

Philosophy and the art of questioning - Plato s Euthyphro

Platonic Idealism: Too High a Standard for Political Activity. As I have re-read Plato s Republic, and read for the first time Eric Voegelin s

An Analysis of Freedom and Rational Egoism in Notes From Underground

Knowledge and True Opinion in Plato s Meno

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

EXISTENTIALISM AND FILM. LECTURE NOTES:

AKC Lecture 1 Plato, Penrose, Popper

Modern Perspectives on Faith: Abraham s Case in Kant and Kierkegaard. Reconstructions and Critical Remarks

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Baha i Proofs for the Existence of God

Chapter Summaries: A Christian View of Men and Things by Clark, Chapter 1

THE DOCTRINE OF CHRIST Chapter 9 Dr. Danny Forshee. See Systematic Theology, p , and Christian Beliefs, p

CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION. A. Research Background. being as opposed to society as a one organism (Macquarrie, 1973). Existentialism mainly finds

FACULTY OF THEOLOGY AND RELIGION. Final Honour School. Book List for Paper 10 Further Studies in History and Doctrine.

The 6 th Sunday of Ordinary Time Year B Readings, Lectionary #77

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

1/12. The A Paralogisms

BOOK REVIEW: THE FREE MARKET EXISTENTIALIST: CAPITALISM WITHOUT CONSUMERISM

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

The Age of the Enlightenment

Heraclitus found one Logos in all things and found all reality and all understanding in the hidden depths of the unfathomable soul.

Kant and his Successors

Wednesday, April 20, 16. Introduction to Philosophy

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

Being healed - your divine right

486 International journal of Ethics.

Week 3: Christology against history

UNIVERSITY OF MALTA THE MATRICULATION EXAMINATION ADVANCED LEVEL

Interview. with Ravi Ravindra. Can science help us know the nature of God through his creation?

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

EXISTENTIALISM AND FILM

Objectively there is no truth Wittgenstein and Kierkegaard on Religious Belief

Sacrificing Our Future (Genesis 22)

The Other Half of Hegel s Halfwayness: A response to Dr. Morelli s Meeting Hegel Halfway. Ben Suriano

The Sacrifice of Isaac (Genesis 22:1-19)

Christian Evidences. The Verification of Biblical Christianity, Part 2. CA312 LESSON 06 of 12

Reading Euthyphro Plato as a literary artist

CHRISTIAN MORALITY: A MORALITY OF THE DMNE GOOD SUPREMELY LOVED ACCORDING TO jacques MARITAIN AND john PAUL II

SØREN KIERKEGAARD AND THE CHALLENGE OF EXISTENCE

Biblical Inerrancy - Part 2 Authority and Accuracy of the Bible

From Robert Stern, Understanding Moral Obligation: Kant, Hegel, Kierkegaard (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), pp.

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

Book Review: From Plato to Jesus By C. Marvin Pate. Submitted by: Brian A. Schulz. A paper. submitted in partial fulfillment

The Role of Love in the Thought of Kant and Kierkegaard

The Early Church worked tirelessly to establish a clear firm structure supported by

THE RELIGION OF IMMANUEL KANT'

The Outcast Individual: Abraham and Affliction in the Broader Society

I. THE PHILOSOPHY OF DIALOGUE A. Philosophy in General

Logical Puzzles and the Concept of God

This Message In Christ Alone We Take Our Stand

National Cursillo Movement

EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY

SUBJECT GOD GOLDEN TEXT: JOHN 4 : 24. God is a Spirit: and they that worship him must worship him in spirit and in truth.

LODGE VEGAS # 32 ON EDUCATION

Kierkegaard is pondering, what it is to be a Christian and to guide one s life by Christian faith.

The task of becoming a Christian is the problem and the

Doctrine of God. Immanuel Kant s Moral Argument

Thirty - Eight Ways to Win an Argument from Schopenhauer's "The Art of Controversy"...per fas et nefas :-)

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

Transcription:

Prefatory note Kierkegaard and Socrates by D.R. Khashaba On November 11, 2005, one hundred and fifty years will have passed since the death of Soren Kierkegaard at the age of 42. Kierkegaard's philosophy dissertation was entitled On the Concept of Irony with constant reference to Socrates. He may have seen himself as continuing the Socratic mission of freeing people of passively received dogmas and making them turn inwards into themselves. But in this paper I find more contrasts than similarities between these two differently exceptional personalities. I try to bring out this contrast, or rather opposition, by examining Kierkegaard's exposition of his notion of the 'teleological suspension of the ethical.' But first let us try to get an overview of the intricate relations between their outlooks. Kierkegaard and Socrates Greek thought and Hebrew thought do not make a good mix. Christianity of course is such a mix and that is one source, perhaps the major source, of its difficulties. You can either think in Greek terms or in Hebrew terms without experiencing internal discord, but when you try to weld the two together you cannot be true to yourself all the way through; at some point you have either to forget about the rationality of Greek thought or throw overboard the sanctified presuppositions of Hebrew thought. Kierkegaard, like many old and present-day theologians and Christian thinkers, was trapped between the horns of this dilemma, but unlike many who found themselves in that predicament, Kierkegaard was willing to save his skin by sacrificing the rationality. That is why Kierkegaard, while seeking to emulate Socrates, could not proceed Socratically. Socrates sought to free people of received preconceptions by examining, disentangling, clarifying ideas, by shedding a flood of light. Kierkegaard sought to pull people out of their quiescent, lukewarm acceptance of dogma by shocking them. As Professor William McDonald puts it, 'He used irony, parody, satire, humor, and deconstructive techniques in order to make conventionally accepted forms of knowledge and value untenable.'[1] But when he made 'conventionally accepted forms of knowledge and value untenable' his intention was not that people should discard them but that they should hold them with heightened fervency. He did not want people to reject dogma but to hold it in 'fear and trembling'. The title of Chapter II of Kierkegaard's Concluding Unscientific Postscript, 'The Subjective Truth; Inwardness; Truth is Subjectivity', sounds so deceptively Socratic that we may be excused if we are shocked by the revelation that the positions of the two men are in fact totally opposed. While both Socrates and Kierkegaard found the proper being of humans in subjectivity, the subjectivity Socrates valued was a subjectivity of reason, its essence was intelligibility, while the subjectivity of Kierkegaard was a subjectivity of feeling, its essence was a state of agitation. He asserts that 'passion is the culmination of existence for an existing individual', and again that 'passion is also the highest expression of subjectivity.'[2]

Kierkegaard's project Kierkegaard sought to rescue Christians from the tepidness, the superficiality, and the matter-of-fact adherence that is the bane of institutionalized religions. On this point his position was unequivocal: 'If one who lives in the midst of Christendom goes up to the house of God, the house of the true God, with the true conception of God in his knowledge, and prays, but prays in a false spirit; and one who lives in an idolatrous community prays with the entire passion of the infinite, although his eyes rest upon the image of an idol: where is there most truth? The one prays in truth to God though he worships an idol; the other prays falsely to the true God, and hence worships in fact an idol.'[3] He wanted to restore individuals to their individuality. Hence his watchword was 'become who you are', which we may designate as his version of the Apollonic/ Socratic gnothi sauton. Kierkegaard and mysticism Although Kierkegaard saw his work as a continuation of Socrates' mission to free people of thraldom to unexamined preconceptions and received notions, he stopped short of questioning the tenets of Christian theology. His contemporaries may have seen his positions as unorthodox and it pleased him to make a show of his unorthodoxy, perhaps the better to assert his individuality, yet he was too deeply immersed in traditional doctrine to shed away its basic tenets. The unreasonableness of those tenets rather than affording ground for their overthrow was seen as a virtue, heightening the intensity of the sentiment engendered by the desperate, blind grasping at nothingness. This is perhaps more akin to the drug-addict's grasping at the phantom of bliss than to the mystic groping for an undefinable, unfathomable something. The mystic's experience comes closest to pure subjectivity; Kierkegaard's paradoxical faith mars the subjectivity by reaching out towards an unreachable heaven. With Kierkegaard, in place of the mystic identification with the ultimate source we have a constant assertion of the otherness of the power which constitutes the self. Since Kierkegaardian faith is neither the experience of mystic identification nor the selfevidence of phronetic intelligibility, it has repetitively to be renewed in anxiety, fear, and trembling. Kierkegaard and existentialism Kierkegaard's purpose was to shock Christians into revitalizing their faith. It was his representation of the religious experience as an inward passionate anxiety that earned him the title of 'father of existentialism' and that led to the re-assertion of the connection between philosophy and life, a connection which had often been lost sight of and which has now once more been obliterated in many professional and academic circles. Unfortunately, Kierkegaard's emphasis on the inwardness of the spiritual life was clouded and marred by entanglement with Kierkegaard's acceptance of the Christian dogma and by the consequent insistence on the absurdity and paradoxicality of faith. I suggest that, if Kierkegaard could have broken free of the fetters of dogma, he would have arrived at a purer conception of faith as the immediacy of spiritual inwardness.

Kierkegaard and dogma The assertion of the absolute transcendence of God was pivotal to Kierkegaard's position, but what is that but to equate God with the area of our ignorance? If God is what I don't know and can never know, then what is he to me? At most the illusion of somehow knowing something that I know I don't know. And it is this illusion that is meant to give us the intense subjective feeling of knowing what is unknown and unknowable: the height of absurdity, but then absurdity is just what Kierkegaard was after. 'Without risk there is no faith. Faith is precisely the contradiction between the infinite passion of the individual's inwardness and the objective uncertainty.' [4] In Professor McDonald's succinct formulation, 'Christian faith, for Kierkegaard, is not a matter of learning dogma by rote. It is a matter of the individual repeatedly renewing h/er passionate subjective relationship to an object which can never be known, but only believed in. The belief is offensive to reason, since it only exists in the face of the absurd (the paradox of the eternal, immortal, infinite God being incarnated in time as a finite mortal).'[5] Let us try to understand what is supposed to lie outside the sphere of understanding. Christian faith, we are told, is a matter of a passionate subjective relationship to an object which can never be known: yet that which 'can never be known' is distinctly presented in that closing parenthetical clause: the eternal, infinite God incarnated in time as a finite mortal. All of Kierkegaard's circuitous subterfuges end in the requirement to embrace unquestioningly this absurdity not in spite of its absurdity but precisely because of its absurdity. Kierkegaard never wanted to free us of dogma: he was opposed to 'learning dogma by rote' but he was all for imbibing dogma with our eyes wide open. The teleological suspension of the ethical To give some substance to my generalities I will comment briefly on Kierkegaard's examination in Fear and Trembling of the question 'Is There Such a Thing as a Teleological Suspension of the Ethical?'[6] In advancing the notion of the 'teleological suspension of the ethical' Kierkegaard's immediate target was the refutation of Hegelianism. Following the plan he devised for that purpose, Kierkegaard (in the persona of Johannes de Silentio) starts from Hegel's definition of the ethical as the universal and of the single individual as a 'moral form of evil', and proceeds to show that, on these terms, Hegel had to condemn Abraham as a murderer. This conclusion would, according to Kierkegaard, be absurd. Why absurd? Because 'correct' Christian doctrine tells us to revere Abraham as the 'father of faith'. We have to choose between Hegelian rationalism and justifying Abraham by faith. In his treatment of this question, Kierkegaard provides a most flagrant example of the utter sottishness we can fall into when we allow ourselves to be enslaved by a given theology. After distinguishing clearly between the tragic acts of Agamemnon in sacrificing his daughter, Jephthah, also sacrificing his daughter, and Brutus, ordering the execution of his son, on the one hand, and Abraham's sacrificing his son, on the other hand, and after arguing that Agamemnon, Jephtha, and Brutus, all remain 'within the ethical' and that there is no 'teleological suspension of the ethical' in their case, he goes on to justify the act of Abraham. (Parenthetically I would say that ranging Jephthah along with Agamemnon and Brutus as a tragic hero is an enormity: I cannot see how Jephthah can be said to remain 'within the ethical',[7] but I will not go out of my way to discuss this point at length.) Kierkegaard asks, 'Why then did Abraham do it?', and he answers, 'For God's sake and (in complete identity with this) for his own sake. He did it for God's sake because God required this proof of his faith; for his own sake he did it in order that he might furnish

the proof.' I must confess I find no sense in this. Why would God 'require this proof of Abraham's faith'? Could he not find a less barbarous test? And if he could not, and allowing that his omniscience failed him in just this one instance, could he not opt for giving the man the benefit of the doubt instead of putting him to this cruel test? And why would Abraham find it so important to furnish the proof? To find favour in the eyes of God? To earn the rewards of subservient obedience? Prometheus proved himself nobler than Zeus; why could not Abraham aspire to that kind of nobility? Kierkegaard continues, 'Here is evident the necessity of a new category if one would understand Abraham. Such a relationship to the deity paganism did not know. The tragic hero does not enter into any private relationship with the deity, but for him the ethical is the divine...' He concludes: 'The story of Abraham contains therefore a teleological suspension of the ethical. As the individual he became higher than the universal: this is the paradox which does not permit of mediation.' And this is faith as Kierkegaard understands it, an absurd paradox or a paradoxical absurdity. The final conclusion of Kierkegaard's discussion of the teleological suspension of the ethical is that faith transcends the ethical. Here we find the final and ineradicable contradiction between the position of Kierkegaard and that of Socrates. In the Euthyphro Socrates poses the question: Is what is righteous righteous because it is favoured by the gods or is it favoured by the gods because it is righteous? Although the Euthyphro does not spell it out, the Socratic answer rings loud and clear in the works of Plato as a whole and finds its clearest expression in the Republic: the Idea of the Good is the fount of all reality, all truth, and all value. Kierkegaard advances the category of the 'religious' as a new category, a category higher than the ethical, not known to the Greeks or to Hegel. In fact it is nothing but the naive 'piety' of the soothsayer Euthyphro that Socrates finds unsatisfactory, piety as that which is pleasing to the gods. Concluding remarks Sin and guilt loom large in Kierkegaard's thought. It is the sense of sin that instils in us the idea of the transcendent God towards whom we are 'always in the wrong', and it is the anxiety arising from our consciousness of guilt that impels us to seek salvation by the absurdity of faith. Kierkegaard holds that the life-work which God judges in a person is that person's fulfilment of the task of becoming a true self. This would constitute a very fine philosophy indeed and it has in fact been a source of inspiration to many[8] except that for Kierkegaard that fulfilment could only be achieved through that necessarily absurd faith which alone secured salvation. Kierkegaard's theoretical position was largely a reaction against Hegelianism. Against Hegel's hubristic logicalism Kierkegaard set up the irrationality of a paradoxical faith. Saner than either was Socrates' rationalism that valued understanding freed of the illusion of knowledge. Kierkegaard discovered the deceptiveness of the dream that promised to lead humanity to its highest goals (however defined) through scientific knowledge. Had he been more consistently Socratic he might have spared us something of the scientism that in our day poses as the sole way to understanding.

Footnotes 1. McDonald, William, 'Soren Kierkegaard', The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2005 Edition), Edward N. Zalta(ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2005/entries/kierkegaard/. 2. Concluding Unscientific Postscript, translated by David F. Swenson and Walter Lowrie, Princeton, 1944. 3. Concluding Unscientific Postscript. 4. Concluding Unscientific Postscript. 5. McDonald, William, 'Soren Kierkegaard', The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2005 Edition), Edward N. Zalta(ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2005/entries/kierkegaard/. 6. 'Is There Such a Thing as a Teleological Suspension of the Ethical?' (reproduced in Approaches to the Philosophy of Religion, edd. Daniel J. Bronstein and Harold M. Schulweis, New York, 1954). 7. See Book of Judges, 11. 8. See, for instance, Richard Schain, In Love With Eternity, 2005, passim. D. R. Khashaba 2005 E-mail: dkhashaba@hotmail.com Web site: http://www.back-to-socrates.com