Another Scandal of Philosophy *

Similar documents
FIL 4600/10/20: KANT S CRITIQUE AND CRITICAL METAPHYSICS

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE. Graduate course and seminars for Fall Quarter

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Immanuel Kant. Great German philosophers whose influence was and continues to be immense; born in Konigsberg East Prussia, in 1724, died there in 1804

1/5. The Critique of Theology

COURSE GOALS: PROFESSOR: Chris Latiolais Philosophy Department Kalamazoo College Humphrey House #202 Telephone # Offices Hours:

Kant and his Successors

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

Kant s Criticism of Rational Psychology and the Existential Aspect of His Ego Theory

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

Philosophers in Perspective. Kant: The Philosophy of Right

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

The Non-spatiality of Things in Themselves for Kant*

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have

The Coherence of Kant s Synthetic A Priori

1 Therapy for metaphysics

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Critical Discussion of A. W. Moore s Critique of Kant

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Kant s Critical Thoughts on Freedom from a Contemporary Perspective -

Kant s Freedom and Transcendental Idealism

Kant s Transcendental Idealism

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

DEONTOLOGY AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Lecture 4: Transcendental idealism and transcendental arguments

Kant s theory of concept formation and the role of mind

Modern Philosophy II

James Hebbeler. Curriculum Vitae

Some Pragmatic Themes in Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

Kant's Public Construction of Reason

PH 329: Seminar in Kant Fall 2010 L.M. Jorgensen

KANT'S PROLEGOMENA TO ANY FUTURE METAPHYSICS CHICAGO DR. PAUL CARUS THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY

This paper serves as an enquiry into whether or not a theory of metaphysics can grow

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

Kant s Transcendental Exposition of Space and Time in the Transcendental Aesthetic : A Critique

Pleasure and motivation in Kant s

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

INTELLECTUAL HUMILITY AND THE LIMITS OF CONCEPTUAL REPRESENTATION

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Immanuel Kant. Retirado de: (25/01/2018)

The Deistic God of the First Critique and Spinoza s God

Accessing the Moral Law through Feeling

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

THE EVENT OF DEATH: A PHENOMENOLOGICAL ENQUIRY

Introduction: Categories and the Question of Being

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

KANT S DOCTRINE OF TRANSCENDENTAL ILLUSION

7AAN2039 Kant I: Critique of Pure Reason Syllabus Academic year 2015/16

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Hegel on Fichte s Conception of Practical Self-Consciousness 1 A Fundamental Criticism of the Sittenlehre in the Differenz-Schrift (1801) 2

I. THE PHILOSOPHY OF DIALOGUE A. Philosophy in General

To link to this article:

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

No Dilemma for the Proponent of the Transcendental Argument: A Response to David Reiter

Chapter 24. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Concepts of Being, Non-being and Becoming

Real predicates and existential judgements

1 Little Newnham Corpus Christi College. United Kingdom

From Critique of Pure Reason Preface to the second edition

Free ebooks ==>

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Politics, history, critique: An interpretation of Kant's political philosophy in light of his critical-regulative method.

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

The Tempering of a Defense: Further Critiques Against Error Theory in Light of Russ Shafer- Landau s Ethical Nonnaturalism

Christian Evidences. The Verification of Biblical Christianity, Part 2. CA312 LESSON 06 of 12

John J. Callanan. Curriculum Vitae

MAIMON'S CRITICISM OF REINHOLD'S "SATZ DES BEWUSSTSEINS"

This is a repository copy of Does Ought Imply Can? And Did Kant Think It Does?.

Understanding How we Come to Experience Purposive. Behavior. Jacob Roundtree. Colby College Mayflower Hill, Waterville, ME USA

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Kant and McDowell on Skepticism and Disjunctivism. The Fourth Paralogism of the first edition of the Critique of Pure Reason aims

Practical Reason and the Call to Faith: Kant on the Postulates of Immortality and God

INTENTIONALITY, NORMATIVITY AND COMMUNALITY IN KANT S REALM OF ENDS

Chapter 25. Hegel s Absolute Idealism and the Phenomenology of Spirit

Kant on Biology and the Experience of Life

Critique of Practical Reason

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan

Online version of this review can be found at:

1/9. The First Analogy

Kant and the Nature of Doctrine: A Rule-Theory Approach to Theological Reasoning. Jacob L. Goodson Southwestern College.

Transcription:

Another Scandal of Philosophy * Introduction Kant in a footnote in the Critique of Pure Reason famously called it a scandal to philosophy that philosophy remained at a loss to refute the epistemic sceptic about the external world (Ak. 3:23 n.). This phrasing is met with Heidegger s rejoinder that the scandal is not so much that philosophy falls short of proving the existence of the external world as that such proofs are time and again expected and attempted (Heidegger 1993 205). In this paper it is argued that an obvious reaction to this rejoinder would be inadequate, both in terms of its understanding of Heidegger s point and of the vulnerability of Kant s system to it. 1. Kant s transcendental discourse Against Heidegger s point one might argue that in Kant s discourse (concerning the problem of the possibility of synthetic a priori judgments) the transcendental distinction (between phaenomena and noumena), which, incidentally, is also a critical distinction to avert the scandal of the contradictions speculative reason would inevitably encounter without it (Ak 3:21) is used adverbially, as pertaining to two ways of considering empirical objects: either as they appear [to us] or as they are in themselves (rather than adjectivally, as pertaining to two ontologically * Paper accepted for the 23rd World Congress of Philosophy, Athens, August 4-10 2013 (section 22 Metaphilosophy) - 1 -

distinct sets of entities ) (Allison 2006 112). Taken thus, the distinction is epistemological with transcendental idealism warranting the objective reality of the empirical objects to which synthetic a priori judgments qua epistemological are applied and does not entail a metaphysical position concerning the external world, the existence of which should be considered as problematic, let alone proved. Kant, moreover, only signalled this scandal in the Critique s second edition to appease Garve s conflation of transcendental with Berkeleian idealism (Rockmore 2007 136). In terms of such a reaction, Heidegger s rejoinder seems relatively innocuous because it is illegitimately bound up with an unobvious reading of the transcendental distinction. Heidegger s point, however, if it is applied to Kant s system challenges the epistemological enterprise as such for its metaphysical import (and thus renders the above reaction irrelevant) by proposing a conception of being of its own, namely being-in-the world (Dasein). Heidegger contends that rather than it is to be proved that and how the external world exists it is to be elucidated why being as being in the world tends to bury the external world epistemologically in vanities only to resurrect it subsequently (Heidegger 1993 206). The thrust of Heidegger s point, therefore, is that it denies the proponent of a transcendental discourse about the world the competence of analysing Dasein in a relevant way (fundamental-ontologically), accounting for its existential aspects (e.g. anxiety, death, temporality). The vulnerability of Kant s system to Heidegger s point is due to this system s architecture, in which the metaphysics of morals is claimed to contain the principles of morality being the only - 2 -

conformity with a law of actions which can fully a priori be deduced from those principles, and thus has no anthropological foundation (Ak. 3: 544). This claim presupposes that an intelligible transition can be construed from the (rational) metaethic principles of the metaphysics of morals which are topically equivalent to the principles of the metaphysics of nature to its (deontological) normative content (for this distinction, e.g. Forschler 2013). This is questionable however, because differently from the metaphysics of nature, the normativity of the moral law, i.e its objective reality, cannot be deduced from its principles but is inferred from a metaethical assumption, the postulate of freedom. Accordingly, an abyss [Kluft] between the domains of the concepts about nature [Naturbegriff] and about freedom [Freiheitsbegriff] as the domains of the sensible and the supersensible (Ak 5:175) separates every descriptive sentence [phrase], including the critical metalanguage of the deduction, from the prescriptive sentence [such that w]hen the latter is taken as referent of the former it must slip away. Due to the heterogeneity of the cognitive and the ethical sentence Kant s system, therefore, manifests an absence of a homogeneous language (Lyotard 1983 174ff; 180). 2. Cosmopolitical metaphysics Kant s worry with the intelligibility of the transition from metaethics to deontology might be assumed from his effort to cope in Gemeinspruch with another scandal of philosophy as which he labels the scepticism about this transition from theoretical rightness to practical validity in his discussion of Garve s (again) objections (Ak. 7:277 ff). The mild ironic undertone of this text - 3 -

combined with its popular style (a common feature of his historico-political texts after 1781), compared with the severity of the critical style of his canonical oeuvre indicates, to follow Vorländer s suggestion (cp. Mom 2006 64ff), that Kant is here aiming at persuasion rather than exposition. Kant self-consciously expresses his concern with this stylistic diversity as he confesses that the Critique never can become popular and this not to his disliking. For, as Kant submits, the people [Volk] prefer to entertain practical truths instead of the fine-grained arguments of speculative reason and do not possess the capacity to critically appreciate the arguments and to invent the subtle objections in this field (Ak 3:21). The same with the Metaphysics of Morals (Ak 6:206). Compare in this respect (to anticipate what will be said in the next section) the exposition of the moral classification of suicide at (Ak 6:422ff) with, say, Camus literary-styled philosophical reflections on a myth-historical topic in Le mythe de Sisyphe. By contrast, Kant is confident that his Anthropologie is due to the examples it offers both systematically designed and yet popular (Ak 7:121). And he professes explicitly his persuasive intent in the Prolegomena (Ak 4:255). In view of this contrast it is not unproblematic to consider Kant's oeuvre as a consistent complex of ideas, tendencies, methods, themes, styles etc., let alone as manifesting a linear development. The contrast rather seems to indicate that in Kant's personal trajectory of reflection and belief-forming there is an undercurrent of contrasting philosophical, aesthetic, political, and religious motives which express themselves in a more or less salient diversity in styles of writing. - 4 -

In (Mom 2006) the ironic tropes in Zum ewigen Frieden are interpreted as expressions of the embarrassment of the philosopher who seeks to reconcile his cosmopolitical philosophical outlook, i.e. a comprehensive account of the world (Toulmin 1990 128; 2001 133) and the course of world-history with a narrative about the contingency of the disasters of war. As the stylistic disparity of account and narrative suggests, this reconciliation remains a problem for Kant. Indeed, the critique of political reason has not been written (Lyotard 1983 189). By extension, taking Kant s embarrassment as a hermeneutic clue, one could say, in a perhaps more charitable reading than Toulmin s (cf. Toulmin 2001 24), that Kant attempts to balance the rationality of the ethico-juridical and teleological metalanguage of the philosopher with the reasonableness of the normative object language of the political commentator. That Kant undertakes this attempt shows that he is open to the vicissitudes of a toilsome existence; that it is bound to fail, though, is due to the absence of a homogeneous language. The diversity of styles in Kant s work as a whole bears witness to this. It indicates that the problems Kant sees himself as facing are not necessarily fundamental philosophical problems but reflect a fundamental situation which has become a problem for [his] philosophy (Seligman 1975 9): Kant not only is the epitome of modernity but also a child of his time. The historicity of philosophy involves that its history is a succession of transformations of metaphysical vocabularies which are introduced and revised for their purported aptness to express cosmopolitical ideas e.g. humanity, world peace, environment and accomodate their inherent antinomies. To come to terms with problems thus conceived we may refer philosophy to its - 5 -

European tradition and retrace them back to the point at which a metaphysical vocabulary was first introduced. Thus, the Copernican revolution accomplished by Anaximander, i.e. the rephrasing of the problem of the world-order from the myth-historical to the theoretical level (Seligman 1957 117, 154) learns that the key metaphysical ideas were cast in a poetic language. Our task then is to investigate why and how these moral and juridical terms [viz. δίκη, τίσις, αδικία, διδόναι δίκην] are mixed in a picture of nature (Heidegger 1946 36; cf. Nietzsche 1872 4). To this effect we can observe (i), that these terms express the personal aspect, i.e. the interweaving of anthropogony and cosmogony thus, that the latter, however naturalistically formulated is anthropocentrically conceived ; (ii) that the key ideas which are expressed with these terms are separated from the natural area (Seligman 1957 84; 157) and do not belong to the vocabulary of the specialist disciplines (Heidegger 1946 327). Anaximander s metaphysics owes its revolutionary dimension to the fact that these ideas, differently from Thales, are not expressed in a physical language (cf. Nietzsche 1872 4). 3. Concluding remarks This paper has shown that if Kant was very much in the world (Zweig 2001 258f) this is apparent from the diversity of Kant s stylistic repertoire rather than from the transition from his transcendental to his moral discourse. Analogously, Anaximander s achievement indicates that if the quest for the unconditioned is to preserve its anthropological import and explicate cosmopolitical ideas it is to poetry rather than science that it could revert for its vocabulary. - 6 -

References Allison, H. E. (2006), Kant's Transcendental Idealism, in Gr. Bird (ed.), 'A Companion to Kant', Blackwell, Malden, MA, 109-124. Forschler, S. (2013), 'Kantian and Consequentialist Ethics: The Gap Can Be Bridged', Metaphilosophy 44 (1-2), 88-104. Heidegger, M. (1946), Der Spruch des Anaximander, in 'Holzwege', Vittorio Klostermann, Frankfurt am Main, 317-368. (1993), Sein und Zeit, Max Niemeyer Verlag, Tu bingen Kant, I. (1783), Prolegomena zu einer jeden künftigen Metaphysik, die als Wissenschaft wird auftreten können, in Kant, I.: Gesammelte Schriften, Preussische Akademie der Wissenschaften (vols. 1-22), Berlin 1900ff. (Ak 4). (1787), Kritik der reinen Vernunft. (Ak 3). (1788), Kritik der Praktischen Vernunft. (Ak 5). (1793), Über den Gemeinspruch: Das mag in der Theorie richtig sein, taugt aber nicht für die Praxis. (Ak 8). (1798), Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht. (Ak 7). (1798), Die Metaphysik der Sitten. (Ak 6). Lyotard, J.-F. (1983), Le différend, Editions de Minuit, Paris. - 7 -

Mom, K. (2006), 'Democratic and Perpetual Peace. Kant and contemporary peace politics', Theoria: A Journal of Social & Political Theory (110), 50-73. Nietzsche, F. (1872), Die Philosophie im tragischen Zeitalter der Griechen, in 'Friedrich Nietzsche Digitale Kritische Gesamtausgabe Werke und Briefe'. http://www.nietzschesource.org/#ekgwb/phg. Rockmore, T. (2007), Kant and Idealism, Yale University Press, New Haven. Seligman, P. (1975), The Apeiron of Anaximander, Greenwood Press, Westport. Toulmin, S. (1990), Cosmopolis, Free Press, New York. (2001), Return to reason, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass.. Zweig, A. (2009), Reflections on the Enduring Value of Kant's Ethics, in Th. Hill (ed.), 'The Blackwell Guide to Kant's Ethics', Blackwell, Chichester, 255-264. - 8 -