John Hawthorne s Knowledge and Lotteries

Similar documents
Sensitivity hasn t got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior

Deductive Closure as a Sorites

The Assumptions Account of Knowledge Attributions. Julianne Chung

Modal Conditions on Knowledge: Sensitivity and safety

COMPARING CONTEXTUALISM AND INVARIANTISM ON THE CORRECTNESS OF CONTEXTUALIST INTUITIONS. Jessica BROWN University of Bristol

In Defence of Single-Premise Closure

INTRODUCTION. This week: Moore's response, Nozick's response, Reliablism's response, Externalism v. Internalism.

External World Skepticism

Critical Appreciation of Jonathan Schaffer s The Contrast-Sensitivity of Knowledge Ascriptions Samuel Rickless, University of California, San Diego

Nozick and Scepticism (Weekly supervision essay; written February 16 th 2005)

Topics in Philosophy of Mind Other Minds Spring 2003/handout 2

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

KNOWING AGAINST THE ODDS

LOTTERIES, INSENSITIVITY, AND CLOSURE

Seigel and Silins formulate the following theses:

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

Introduction: Paradigms, Theism, and the Parity Thesis

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

Why Have Consistent and Closed Beliefs, or, for that Matter, Probabilistically Coherent Credences? *

Sensitivity has Multiple Heterogeneity Problems: a Reply to Wallbridge. Guido Melchior. Philosophia Philosophical Quarterly of Israel ISSN

Inductive Knowledge. Andrew Bacon. July 26, 2018

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

Varieties of Apriority

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

BLACKWELL PUBLISHING THE SCOTS PHILOSOPHICAL CLUB UNIVERSITY OF ST ANDREWS

Transmission Failure Failure Final Version in Philosophical Studies (2005), 126: Nicholas Silins

KNOWLEDGE AND SKEPTICISM

what you know is a constitutive norm of the practice of assertion. 2 recently maintained that in either form, the knowledge account of assertion when

Notes for Week 4 of Contemporary Debates in Epistemology

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

Some Thoughts on the JK-Rule 1

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Skepticism and Internalism

Nozick s defense of closure

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

This discussion surveys recent developments

How to Mistake a Trivial Fact About Probability For a. Substantive Fact About Justified Belief

Is Moore s Argument an Example of Transmission-Failure? James Pryor Harvard University Draft 2 8/12/01

Follow this and additional works at: Part of the Philosophy Commons

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

CLASSIC INVARIANTISM, RELEVANCE, AND WARRANTED ASSERTABILITY MANŒUVERS

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University

Matt Weiner Does Knowledge Matter? 1. [This is a draft version of a talk given in Nov. 2005, with slight revisions from April

NO SAFE HAVEN FOR THE VIRTUOUS. In order to deal with the problem caused by environmental luck some proponents of robust virtue

The Skeptic and the Dogmatist

Lucky to Know? the nature and extent of human knowledge and rational belief. We ordinarily take ourselves to

Inquiry and the Transmission of Knowledge

ON JESUS, DERRIDA, AND DAWKINS: REJOINDER TO JOSHUA HARRIS

Coordination Problems

REVIEW OF DUNCAN PRITCHARD S EPISTEMIC LUCK

Can the lottery paradox be solved by identifying epistemic justification with epistemic permissibility? Benjamin Kiesewetter

Epistemic Freedom HUMANITIES

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Believing Epistemic Contradictions

Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators. Christopher Peacocke. Columbia University

Beliefs, Degrees of Belief, and the Lockean Thesis

DOUBT, CIRCULARITY AND THE MOOREAN RESPONSE TO THE SCEPTIC. Jessica Brown University of Bristol

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

Conditionals IV: Is Modus Ponens Valid?

Recursive Tracking versus Process Reliabilism

The Externalist and the Structuralist Responses To Skepticism. David Chalmers

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Martin s case for disjunctivism

Hume s emotivism. Michael Lacewing

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Stout s teleological theory of action

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

UNIVERSITY OF CALGARY. Contextualism and the Reference Class Problem. Masashi Kasaki A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES

A Puzzle about Knowing Conditionals i. (final draft) Daniel Rothschild University College London. and. Levi Spectre The Open University of Israel

On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University

Vagueness Without Ignorance

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

Penultimate Draft: Final Revisions not included. Published in Philosophical Books, 1995.

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

Anti-intellectualism and the Knowledge-Action Principle

G.E. Moore A Refutation of Skepticism

Indexical Reliabilism and the New Evil Demon *

The Dreamer. Does Descartes know what he is doing when he shakes his head and stretches out his hand? Descartes, Meditations, 1641

Intuition as Philosophical Evidence

Rational Self-Doubt and the Failure of Closure *

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Speaking of Knowing PATRICK RYSIEW 1. INTRODUCTION

Outsmarting the McKinsey-Brown argument? 1

Comments on Lasersohn

Comments on Carl Ginet s

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

Probability and Danger timothy williamson

Rationality and Truth

SOLVING THE SKEPTICAL PROBLEM

Klein on the Unity of Cartesian and Contemporary Skepticism

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Transcription:

John Hawthorne s Knowledge and Lotteries Chapter 1: Introducing the Puzzle 1.1: A Puzzle 1. S knows that S won t have enough money to go on a safari this year. 2. If S knows that S won t have enough money to go on a safari this year, then S is in a position to know that S will not win a major prize in a lottery this year. 3. Hence, S is in a position to know that S will not win a major prize in a lottery this year. We have the intuition that [1] and [2] are true, but in spite of the fact that [3] follows from [1] and [2], we have the intuition that [3] is not true. Other Instances of the Puzzle 1. I know that I will be living in Syracuse for part of this summer. 2. I don t know that I will not suffer a fatal heart attack in the next week. 3. I know that my car is now parked in location x. 4. I don t know that my car has not been stolen in the last few minutes. 5. I know that George W. Bush is now the President of the United States. 6. I don t know that Bush hasn t been assassinated in the last few minutes. 7. I know that my refrigerator is running. 8. I don t know that there hasn t been an electrical outage in my neighborhood in the last few minutes. 9. I know that the Lakers won last night. 10. I don t know that there wasn t a misprint in this morning s paper. 1

11. I know that there s a desk in front of me. 12. I don t know that the desk hasn t very recently developed into a desk façade. The Structure of Lottery Puzzles There is 1. an ordinary proposition, a proposition of the sort that we ordinarily take ourselves to know (p. 5). 2. a lottery proposition, a proposition of the sort that, while highly likely, is a proposition that we would be intuitively disinclined to take ourselves to know (p. 5). 1.2: The Lottery Proposition [T]he lottery proposition is highly likely relative to the person s evidence (p. 8). Why Do We Think That We Don t Know Lottery Propositions? 1. Our intuition does not depend on there being a guaranteed winner. 2. It doesn t depend on the fact that each ticket has an equal chance of winning. 3. It doesn t depend on the fact that the epistemic subject under consideration has merely statistical reasons for believing that he or she will lose the lottery. 4. It doesn t depend on any of the following epistemological theories: a. The justified true belief account of knowledge b. Reliabilism c. The true belief supported by good evidence account d. A sensitivity account, neither sensitivity simpliciter nor sensitivity*, i.e., a sensitivity condition that has been relativized to belief forming methods. (In the latter case, we sometimes have the intuition that S s belief that p is not sensitive*, along with the intuition that S doesn t know that p. At other times, though for example, in Vogel s hole in one case (see p. 12) and in Hawthorne s matchbox and mispronunciation cases we have the intuition that S s belief that p is not sensitive*, along with the intuition that S does know that p.) 5. It does depend on [s]omething in the vicinity of the presence of probabilistic thoughts (p. 14). Here s Hawthorne s proposal: 2

in the paradigm lottery situation, something like the following goes on: The ascriber divides the possibility space into a set of subcases, each of which, from the point of view of the subject, is overwhelmingly likely to not obtain, but which are such that the subject s grounds for thinking that any one of the subcases does not obtain is not appreciably different than his grounds for thinking that any other subcase does not obtain. Using DeRose s terminology, the relative strength of epistemic position with regard to each subcase is not appreciably different (pp. 14 15). We might put this as a principle in the following way: Parity Reasoning: One conceptualizes the proposition that p as the proposition that one particular member of a set of subcases (p1,, pn) will (or does) not obtain, where one has no appreciably stronger reason for thinking that any given member of the set will not obtain than one has for thinking that any other particular member will not obtain. Insofar as one reckons it absurd to suppose that one is able to know of each of (p1,, pn) that it will not obtain, one then reckons oneself unable to know that p. Applying the Parity Reasoning Proposal to Cases [O]n the picture I am advancing, one s willingness to [say one knows that there will not be sixty holes in one] depends on not having divided the Heartbreaker case into a set of subcases to which parity reasoning can apply (p. 17). 1.3: Assertion, Probability, Practical Reasoning Hawthorne maintains that we should pay especially careful attention to three phenomena that are closely tied to knowledge (p. 21): 1. Assertion a. We are not inclined to attribute to ourselves knowledge of a lottery proposition, L, and at the same time, we are not inclined to assert L. b. Perhaps we can account for the former fact by saying that we violate some conversational maxim when we attribute 3

knowledge of L to ourselves. In this case, we wouldn t need to say that we fail to know that L. (This is one strategy for denying a premise of the lottery argument.) c. Hawthorne argues, though, that this won t work. Still, there is a conversational maxim at work here, and it s the Knowledge Account of Assertion (KAA): I may assert that p only if I know that p. Thus, in the case of lottery propositions, my not knowing that L accounts perfectly well for my not being inclined to assert it. No conversational maxim allows us to know that L, but my not knowing that L, given KAA, gives us a fine explanation of the fact that we aren t inclined to assert that L. 2. Probability a. There is also a striking tie between our willingness to assert It might be that p and There is a chance that p on the one hand, and our willingness to assert I do not know that notp and I do not know whether or not p on the other (p. 24). b. (1) It is possible that p for S at t (There is a chance that p for S at t) iff p is consistent with what S knows at t (p. 26). c. (3) An utterance of It might be that p by S at t is true iff it is possible that p for S at t (p. 26). 3. Practical Reasoning a. That one does not know a lottery proposition seems to prohibit one from using it as a premise in one s deliberations about how to act (p. 29). b. Consider the following line of reasoning: The ticket is a loser. So if I keep the ticket I will get nothing. But if I sell the ticket I will get a penny. So I d better sell the ticket. c. such reasoning is unacceptable (p. 29). 4

1.4: Epistemic Closure d. Why is such reasoning unacceptable? Folks will respond by pointing out that the first premise was not known to be true (pp. 29 30). e. : one ought only to use that which one knows as a premise in one s deliberations (p. 30). Multi Premise Closure (MPC): Necessarily, if S knows that p1,, pn, competently deduces q (from p1,, pn), and thereby comes to believe that q, while retaining knowledge of p1,, pn throughout, then S knows that q. Single Premise Closure (SPC): Necessarily, if S knows that p, competently deduces q (from p), and thereby comes to believe that q, while retaining knowledge of p throughout, then S knows that q. something in the vicinity of the above closure principles is correct (p. 35). 1.5: Denying Single Premise Closure The intuitive consequences of denying Single Premise Closure seem to be extremely high (p. 38). 1. a denial of closure interacts disastrously with the thesis that knowledge is the norm of assertion. The premises of a modus ponens argument [e.g., the BIV skeptical argument, or the cleverlypainted mule skeptical argument] are stably adhered to, and yet the conclusion stably repudiated (p. 39). 2. In relinquishing SPC, we are forced to relinquish certain other principles Addition Closure and Distribution (or instead, Equivalence) that are very compelling (p. 41). 3. Let p be a heavyweight proposition just in case we all have some strong inclination to say that p is neither the sort of thing that one can know by the exercise of reason alone nor by the use of one s perceptual faculties (even aided by reason) (p. 42). But while the 5

views of some who deny closure are intended to align [themselves] with our instinctive verdicts about whet we can and cannot know by perception [they draw] the can cannot line in a very different place (p. 46). For example, I have conclusive reasons for believing that (I have a headache and it is not the case that I am a brain in a vat). But this seems to be a heavyweight proposition. 1.6: Multi Premise Closure The claim here is that we have reason to believe that (something in the vicinity of) MPC is true. 1. Kyburg s case: The case depends on the view that knowledge is reasonable true belief, but that view is unpromising. 2. Risk of falsity accrues: But [i]f there being a risk that not p amounts to there being a chance that not p, then knowing p is not compatible with there being any risk at all that not p (p. 48). So, we d fail to know (some of) the premises in this case. 3. The APA Case: it seems as if the setting in which one ascribes knowledge of the individual propositions to me is a setting in which (given that I have deduced and come to believe the conjunction) one is willing to ascribe knowledge to me of the conjunction (p. 49). 4. Misleading evidence against the truth of some premise: In this case, Hawthorne maintains that we might not want to abandon our claim to know any one of the premises, but that it would still be perfectly understandable if I was not inclined to believe the conjunction. But that fact hardly makes trouble for MPC (p. 50). Why? Because a conjunct in the antecedent of MPC namely, and [S] thereby comes to believe that q is false. 5. Believing that you don t know the conjunction: Her own belief that knowledge is absent explains well enough the dubious status of the assertion The conjunction is true in her mouth, without automatically impugning MPC (p. 50), since believing that one doesn t know that p is compatible with knowing that p. 6