PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Similar documents
PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

Can moral facts be an explanation? naturalism and non-naturalism is whether or not there are any moral explanations

Take Home Exam #1. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Take Home Exam #1. PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Are Scientific Theories True?

Human Nature & Human Diversity: Sex, Love & Parenting; Morality, Religion & Race. Course Description

Take Home Exam #1. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Ethics is subjective.

Virtue Ethics without Character Traits

Moral Explanations and Ethical Naturalism

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Asking the Right Questions: A Guide to Critical Thinking M. Neil Browne and Stuart Keeley

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

Realism and instrumentalism

Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social

Review of Erik J. Wielenberg: Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism

In his pithy pamphlet Free Will, Sam Harris. Defining free will away EDDY NAHMIAS ISN T ASKING FOR THE IMPOSSIBLE. reviews/harris

Must we have self-evident knowledge if we know anything?

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

Let s explore a controversial topic DHMO. (aka Dihydrogen monoxide)

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

It s time to stop believing scientists about evolution

A Quick Review of the Scientific Method Transcript

3. Knowledge and Justification


III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Some Templates for Beginners: Template Option 1 I am analyzing A in order to argue B. An important element of B is C. C is significant because.

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Lecture 1. The Science of Economics

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Ethical non-naturalism

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

The Cosmological Argument

The evolution of the meaning of SCIENCE. SCIENCE came from the latin word SCIENTIA which means knowledge.

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Naturalism vs. Conceptual Analysis. Marcin Miłkowski

FINAL EXAM REVIEW SHEET. objectivity intersubjectivity ways the peer review system is supposed to improve objectivity

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

In his book Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, J. L. Mackie agues against

"Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Video Reaction. Opening Activity. Journal #16

Darwinist Arguments Against Intelligent Design Illogical and Misleading

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

Epistemology. Diogenes: Master Cynic. The Ancient Greek Skeptics 4/6/2011. But is it really possible to claim knowledge of anything?

Chapter 2 Test Bank. 1) When one systematically studies being or existence one is dealing with the branch of metaphysics called.

Philosophy 1100 Introduction to Ethics. Lecture 3 Survival of Death?

Argument Writing. Whooohoo!! Argument instruction is necessary * Argument comprehension is required in school assignments, standardized testing, job

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Topic III: Sexual Morality

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:


SPRING 2014 UNDERGRADUATE COURSE OFFERINGS

Video: How does understanding whether or not an argument is inductive or deductive help me?

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

Chapter Six. Putnam's Anti-Realism

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Lecture 18: Rationalism

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

BERKELEY, REALISM, AND DUALISM: REPLY TO HOCUTT S GEORGE BERKELEY RESURRECTED: A COMMENTARY ON BAUM S ONTOLOGY FOR BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS

Philosophy 12 Study Guide #4 Ch. 2, Sections IV.iii VI

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

DR. LEONARD PEIKOFF. Lecture 3 THE METAPHYSICS OF TWO WORLDS: ITS RESULTS IN THIS WORLD

E L O G O S ELECTRONIC JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY/2008 ISSN Tracks in the Woods. F.A. Hayek s Philosophy of History.

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

Debate on the mind and scientific method (continued again) on

REVIEW: Marc Lange, Laws and Lawmakers: Science, Metaphysics, and the Laws of Nature.

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 4 : I M M A T E R I A L I S M, D U A L I S M, & T H E M I N D - B O D Y P R O B L E M

Theory of knowledge prescribed titles

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Characteristics of Science: Understanding Scientists and their Work (adapted from the work of Prof. Michael Clough)

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

1. What is Philosophy?

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

In today s workshop. We will I. Science vs. Religion: Where did Life on earth come from?

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

Lecture 7.1 Berkeley I

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 2017/18. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Transcription:

PHI 1700: Global Ethics Session 3 February 11th, 2016 Harman, Ethics and Observation 1

(finishing up our All About Arguments discussion) A common theme linking many of the fallacies we covered is that they make unwarranted, questionable assumptions. An assumption is a claim that is taken for granted, for which no proof is given or argument made. (Carroll 2015) Ø Every argument makes some assumptions. Ø These need not all be proven true, but they should should be warranted. A warranted assumption is... either known to be true or is reasonable to accept without requiring an argument to support it. Since a good argument must be based on true or reasonable assumptions, it follows that arguments based upon false or questionable assumptions are not good arguments. A questionable assumption is one that is controversial and one for which there is no general consensus among the vast majority of those with the appropriate knowledge or experience. Note that a claim does not become questionable just because you or anyone else questions it; otherwise all claims would be questionable. (ibid.) 2

Responding to Arguments If you identify a problem with an argument, you can raise an objection against it. For example: This argument is not convincing, since the author equivocates on the meaning of laws. This argument misleads readers by exhibiting Confirmation Bias in the selection of the sources for the defense of its conclusion. This argument fails to support its conclusion because its reasoning is an instance of the Post Hoc fallacy. An objection may motivate you to suggest a revision, where you give different premises in support of the same conclusion, and/or show that the original premises actually support a different conclusion. or it may motivate you to pose a counterargument, where you give your own premises in support of the opposite conclusion. 3

Consider this argument: A*. Barack Obama is the best President the U.S. has ever had, given that he made affordable healthcare insurance available to all Americans. Ø Sample revisions to this argument might be: A+. Barack Obama is the best President the U.S. has ever had, given that he expanded marriage rights and made affordable healthcare insurance available to all Americans. A-. Barack Obama is not the best President the U.S. has ever had, given that he made affordable healthcare insurance available to all Americans. Ø A sample counterargument might be: B. Barack Obama is not the best President the U.S. has ever had, given that he has failed to curb police brutality against people of color. 4

Now, onto our unit on Meta-Ethics: the investigation of the nature of morality. Today s lecture will introduce some puzzles about: moral metaphysics (what kind of things moral facts, principles, and values are) Harman will motivate us to ask: Do any moral principles correspond to moral facts? Do moral facts even exist? moral psychology (what mental processes we go through in moral decision-making) Do we have an innate sense of right & wrong, or do we have to learn concepts of right & wrong? When we make moral judgments, do we use the rational part of our mind, or the emotional part? We will continue to consider various perspectives on each of these questions throughout this unit of the course. 5

Gilbert Harman s (1938 present) essay Ethics and Observation (from The Nature of Morality) investigates morality by comparing & contrasting it to science. Harman invites us to compare moral principles (e.g., It is wrong to harm innocent animals ) to hypotheses. (In science, a hypothesis represents an educated guess about what the world is like. One tests a scientific hypothesis through observation & experimentation, and thereby confirms or disconfirms it.) Harman asks, Ø can we determine whether or not moral principles are correct or incorrect using observation & experimentation? scienceschools.us/scientific-method/» He suggests that we cannot,» which implies that moral principles are significantly different in kind from scientific & mathematical facts. 6

Take a scientific principle, like DNA carries a cell s genetic code. Ø This can be tested by posing it as a hypothesis, constructing experiments, collecting data, and analyzing results. Now consider a moral principle, like if you are given a choice between five people alive & one dead or five people dead & one alive, you should always choose to have five people alive & one dead rather than the other way round. Ø How do we test whether or not this is correct? Constructing an experiment seems risky:» we don t want to make people do things that we end up concluding are morally unacceptable, just for the sake of confirming that such actions really are unacceptable. Ø When a real experiment is either unfeasible or undesirable, philosophers come up with thought experiments,» where a fictional scenario is used as a tool to help us draw conclusions about difficult issues. 7

Some thought experiments lend support to particular moral principles (confirming their correctness), but other thought experiments supply evidence against the same principles (disconfirming them with a counterexample). Harman says, It would seem that in this case you, the doctor, would be right to save the five and let the other person die. but in this case, surely you must not sacrifice this innocent bystander, even to save the other patients. (So, the principle that it s better to have five people alive & one dead is both confirmed & disconfirmed by particular cases.) 8

In using thought experiments to evaluate a moral principle, we compared an explicit principle with our feelings about certain imagined examples. (Harman 31) But as Harman s examples show, thought experiments are often inconclusive: different scenarios prompt different (and sometimes conflicting) conclusions. Another problem is that it s not clear what our feelings about these hypothetical cases represent: Ø Is your feeling that an action is wrong evidence that the action is objectively wrong (as a matter of fact, independent of anyone s belief system)? (This possibility is hard to defend, because it s clear that different people have different feelings about the rightness and wrongness of actions: How could each of these different feelings be taken as evidence for an objective moral fact?) Ø or is your feeling just evidence that the action is wrong according to the moral theory (set of beliefs about right & wrong) that you personally hold? 9

It seems more likely that: your feeling is just evidence that the action is wrong according to the moral theory (set of beliefs about right & wrong) that you personally hold. And if your feeling only indicates what is right & wrong within a particular moral theory, Ø you might believe that there can be discrepancies between one s moral theory & the moral facts:» moral realism = belief in the existence of objective moral facts, where objective means existing independently of all human thoughts & beliefs. Ø...or you might believe that there are no moral facts only moral theories.» moral anti-realism = belief that there are no objective moral facts Note that moral anti-realists don t necessarily deny the existence of moral facts altogether; they only deny that there are objective moral facts which leaves open the possibility of subjective moral facts. Moral relativism (which we will consider next class) is a view according to which communities produce their own subjective moral facts. 10

Lessons so far from Harman s discussion: Thought experiments can t necessarily help us determine whether a particular moral principle is correct or incorrect. Seems like we ought to rely on some other method to evaluate moral principles. Harman will next ask us to consider what we learn from moral observation (as opposed to experimentation). Our feelings about particular moral cases cannot help us determine which of two moral-metaphysical views (realism vs. anti-realism) is accurate. It s obvious that we all have feelings about whether particular actions are right or wrong, but it is far from obvious whether or not there are any moral facts, compared to which our individual feelings could be correct or incorrect. 11

Maybe gathering observational data (by observing real-life moral situations) can help us to confirm or refute moral principles. But Harman raises a concern about this approach: You can observe someone do something, but can you ever perceive the rightness or wrongness of what he does? The idea here is that rightness & wrongness are not part of the data we gather through observation, but rather judgment calls we make about actions, or features that we attribute to actions, depending upon how our moral theory shapes our interpretation of what we see. (Compare this to the common idea that beauty is in the eye of the beholder :» i.e., beauty is not something that objectively exists in objects, but rather is a feature that we ascribe to things we value in a certain way.) 12

Harman elaborates: If you round a corner and see a group of young hoodlums pour gasoline on a cat & ignite it, you do not need to conclude that what they are doing is wrong; you do not need to figure anything out; you can see that it is wrong. Ø But is your reaction due to the actual [objective] wrongness of what you see, Ø or is it simply a reflection of your moral sense, a sense that you have acquired perhaps as a result of your moral upbringing? Two things to note here: Moral judgments are often quick, & don t seem to involve much deliberation, which raises a question for moral psychologists: how we can arrive at something as complex as a moral judgment so rapidly? Are moral judgments innate or learned? Moral nativists believe that we have inborn, instinctual mechanisms for judging right & wrong actions. Moral empiricists believe that we learn how to judge right & wrong actions during our lifetimes, either by imitating others or through explicit training. 13

Harman says that it s hard to tell on what basis we perceive burning a cat to be wrong. This is because there are no pure observations, unimpacted by our existing set of beliefs about how the world works. Instead, observations are always theory laden. What you perceive depends to some extent on the theory you hold, consciously or unconsciously. (Harman is endorsing a view about perception, widely-held among philosophers, psychologists, and neuroscientists: that it doesn t just involve taking in sensory information from the outside world, but rather requires interpretation of that information, in light of our previously-acquired knowledge & beliefs.) 14

Harman thinks that (unlike thought experiments) observation can be used to confirm or disconfirm moral theories. Say you believe that It is wrong to harm innocent animals, because your moral theory prohibits unnecessary harm: If you then see burning the cat as wrong, then your moral theory has been confirmed by your observation (they are consistent with one another). If instead you see burning the cat as morally acceptable (in conflict with your moral theory): then you either can doubt your observation and continue to hold your moral theory, or you can take your observation as evidence that your moral theory was wrong and needs to be revised, (perhaps to something like In some circumstances it is ok to harm innocent animals ) 15

Sometimes a change in our moral theories can change the apparent rightness or wrongness of the actions we witness. E.g., Lisa Simpson began to see eating meat as wrong, after many years of viewing it as perfectly normal and acceptable. video: bit.ly/1xgpsie (2:45 3:17, 4:20 7:41) 16

Harman thinks there is a crucial difference between moral & scientific observation, though: there are different standards by which scientific hypotheses and moral principles are confirmed as correct. A scientific hypothesis is confirmed when what you observed is explained by a fact about the world, corresponding to your hypothesis. E.g., the hypothesis that DNA carries a cell s genetic code is confirmed when the fact that DNA carries a cell s genetic code explains why scientists observed certain puzzling phenomena» (like that one strain of bacteria gained the traits of another strain when both strains were put into contact; bacteria can trade DNA with one another via horizontal transfer) A moral principle is confirmed when what you observed is explained by a psychological fact about you, the observer (namely, that you hold certain moral beliefs). Ø Facts about the world are irrelevant to explaining why you saw x as right or wrong. 17

So, just as thought experiments couldn t help us settle whether or not any objective moral facts exist (the debate between moral realists & anti-realists), Ø whether or not there are objective moral facts cannot be settled through moral observation. We can only see in accordance with our moral theory, and can never make pure observations about human actions, through which we could see things objectively. As Harman puts it, a person s observation that setting the cat on fire is wrong can be explained without assuming that there is such a thing as wrongness:» Indeed, an assumption about moral facts would seem to be totally irrelevant to the explanation of your making the judgment you make.» It would seem that all we need assume is that you have certain more or less well-articulated moral principles that are reflected in the judgments you make, based on your moral sensibility. (33) 18

Harman explains, The fact that you made a particular moral observation when you did does not seem to be evidence about moral facts, only evidence about you and your moral sensibility. Facts about protons can affect what you observe, since a proton passing through the cloud chamber can cause a vapor trail that reflects light to your eye in a way that, given your scientific training and psychological set, leads you to judge that what you see is a proton. But there does not seem to be any way in which the actual rightness or wrongness of a given situation can have any effect on your perceptual apparatus. Ø In this respect, ethics seems to differ from science. (33) 19

Final lessons from Harman s essay: Moral principles don t help us make sense of human actions. Unlike scientific principles, they don t explain what we see: It is wrong to harm innocent animals certainly doesn t explain why hoodlums would burn a cat. Instead, moral principles have a different purpose: presumably, to capture how we want to the world to be, or how we think people should behave in order to achieve certain objectives (like justice, community stability or survival, etc.) It s hard to say how we could determine whether or not there are objective moral facts. Neither thought experiments nor moral observation seem to help us with this puzzle. Maybe looking more concretely at the possibility of moral relativism will help us figure this out. 20