Contingency, irony, and solidarity

Similar documents
Notes on "Contingency, irony, and solidarity" by Richard Rorty (1989) Sunday, 21 March :23

The Philosopher as a Child of His Own Time

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

Course Text. Course Description. Course Objectives. StraighterLine Introduction to Philosophy

A Major Matter: Minoring in Philosophy. Southeastern Louisiana University. The unexamined life is not worth living. Socrates, B.C.E.

In this response, I will bring to light a fascinating, and in some ways hopeful, irony

Has Richard Rorty a moral philosophy? *

The Paradoxes of Education in Rorty s Liberal Utopia

Communicative Rationality and Deliberative Democracy of Jlirgen Habermas: Toward Consolidation of Democracy in Africa

Political Science 206 Modern Political Philosophy Spring Semester 2011 Clark University

Praxis and Pragmatism

READING RORTY POLITICALLY

A Defense of a Wittgensteinian Outlook on Two Postmodern Theories

Rorty on the Priority of Democracy to Philosophy

The Pragmatist Skepsis as a Social Practice

Contingency, Irony, Solidarity. Richard Rorty's position is as close to the inspired madness of some contemporary

Socratic and Platonic Ethics

Chapter Two: Two Cheers for Richard Rorty. I. Introduction

COURSE PLAN for Pol. 702, 20th and 21st Century Political Thought Dr. Thomas West, Hillsdale College, Fall 2014

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Creative Democracy: The Task Before Us

organized in a way that focuses on each thinker s proposal and possible criticisms. However there are

The Five Ways THOMAS AQUINAS ( ) Thomas Aquinas: The five Ways

Kant and his Successors

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Rorty, Davidson, and Metaphor. Greig R. Mulberry

Richard Rorty s Deep Humanism

Existentialism Willem A. devries

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

Anti-foundationalism and Liberal Democracy: Richard Rorty and the Role of Religion in the Public Sphere

Human rights theory as solidarity

Introduction to Kierkegaard and Existentialism

Course Syllabus Ethics PHIL 330, Fall, 2009

Richard Rorty (1931 )

The Three 'Rs': Reading/Rorty/Radically

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

PHIL 103 Introduction to Philosophy

UNITED NATIONS EDUCATIONAL, SCIENTIFIC AND CULTURAL ORGANIZATION. Address by Mr Federico Mayor

Small Group Assignment 8: Science Replaces Scholasticism

An Analysis of Freedom and Rational Egoism in Notes From Underground

Modern Intellectual History

Rorty s Elective Affinities. The New Pragmatism amd Postmodern Thought

Nietzsche and Truth: Skepticism and The Free Spirit!!!!

Alice Bailey Talks Talk given to Arcane School students on March 9, 1945

Galileo Galilei Sir Isaac Newton Laws of Gravity & Motion UNLOCKE YOUR MIND

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

The Death of God - a lecture on Friedrich Nietzsche - by Adam Lloyd Johnson

POL320 Y1Y Modern Political Thought Summer 2016

Theories of propositions

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

KINGSBOROUGH COMMUNITY COLLEGE of The City University of New York. Common COURSE SYLLABUS

A Contractualist Reply

Philosophic Classics: From Plato To Derrida (Philosophical Classics) Free Download PDF

Religion 12: In Search of the Good

DEMOCRACY, DELIBERATION, AND RATIONALITY Guido Pincione & Fernando R. Tesón

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE. Graduate course and seminars for Fall Quarter

Preliminary Remarks on Locke's The Second Treatise of Government (T2)

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

return to religion-online

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

Moral Communities in a Pluralistic Nation

Going beyond good and evil

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8

Teachur Philosophy Degree 2018

Radical Pluralism and Philosophy Education in Jesuit Universities

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

Course Description. Course objectives. Achieving the Course Objectives:

By the end of this course, students will be able to:

VIEWING PERSPECTIVES

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Outcomes Assessment of Oral Presentations in a Philosophy Course

1) Weekly Reading Responses (25% of final grade)

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

TABLE OF CONTENTS. A. "The Way The World Really Is" 46 B. The First Philosophers: The "Turning Point of Civilization" 47

(Review) Critical legal positivism by Kaarlo Tuori

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton

What Is Existentialism? COPYRIGHTED MATERIAL. Chapter 1. In This Chapter

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Challenges to Traditional Morality

Revolution and Reaction: Political Thought From Kant to Nietzsche

Reading a Philosophy Text Philosophy 22 Fall, 2019

Morally Adaptive or Morally Maladaptive: A Look at Compassion, Mercy, and Bravery

Marriage. Embryonic Stem-Cell Research

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT David Hume: The Origin of Our Ideas and Skepticism about Causal Reasoning

Reading Euthyphro Plato as a literary artist

CONSTRUCTIVISM IN ETHICS

Prentice Hall. Conexiones Comunicación y cultura North Carolina Course of Study for High School Level IV

Gelassenheit See releasement. gender See Beauvoir, de

I, for my part, have tried to bear in mind the very aims Dante set himself in writing this work, that is:

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Philosophy 102 Ethics Course Description: Course Requirements and Expectations

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Course Syllabus Political Philosophy PHIL 462, Spring, 2017

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Transcription:

Contingency, irony, and solidarity RICHARD RORTY University Professor of Humanities, University of Virginia 'The righ,,>f rhc Vniwr~rrv of Comhricip,",,,it,, "!,,I <,./i oli n,.nn,r,,i'b>,,i, lvo, prunfcrl b? Ncory b111 in 1534. mc LL'ni>rr,r,~ I,"! pnn,n1 and publ~~h~nnl n,nrr,!rrvurlv rincr 1588 CAMBRIDGE UNlVERSITY PRESS (.:AN B R I D G E NEW YORK PORT CHESTER. M E L R O l. l K N E SY1)iL'liY

Contents Preface Introduction page xi... Xlll I The contingency of language Part I: Contingency 2 The contingency of selfhood 3 The contingency of a liberal community 4 Private irony and liberal hope Part 11: Ironism and Theory 5 Self-creation and affiliation: Proust, Nietzsche, and Heidegger G From ironist theory to private allusions: Derrida Part 111: Cruelty and Solidarity 7 The barber of Kasbeam: Nabokov on cruelty 8 The last intellectual in Europe: Orwell on cruelty 9 Solidarity

Introduction The attempt to fuse the public and the private lies behind both Plato's attempt to answer the question "Why is it in one's interest to be just?" and Christianity's claim that perfect self-realization can be attained through service to others. Such metaphysical or theological attempts to unite a striving for perfection with a sense of community require us to acknowledge a common human nature. They ask us to believe that what is most important to each of us is what we have in common with others - that the springs of private fulfillment and of human solidarity are the same. Skeptics like Nietzsche have urged that metaphysics and theology are transparent attempts to make altruism look more reasonable than it is. Yet such skeptics typically have their own theories of human nature. They, too, claim that there is something common to all human beings - for example, the will to power, or libidinal impulses. Their point is that at the "deepest" level of the self there is no sense of human solidarity, that -. this sense is a "mere" artifact of human socialization. So such skeptics become antisocial.~h$ turn their backs on the very idea of a community larger than a tiny circle of initiates. Ever since Hegel, however, historicist thinkers have tried to get beyond this familiar standoff. They have denied that there is such a thing as "human nature" or the "deepest level of the self." Their strategy has been to insist that socialization, and thus historical circumstance, goes all the way down - that there is nothing "beneath" socialization or prior to history which is definatory of the human. Such writers tell us that the question "What is it to be a human being?" should be replaced by questions like "What is it to inhabit a rich twent~eth-century democratic society?" and "How can an inhabitant of such a society be more than the enactor of a role in a previously written script?" This historicist turn has helped free us, gradually but steadily, from theology and metaphysics - from the temptation to look for an escape from time and chance. It has helped us substitute Freedom for Truth as the goal of th~nking and of social progress. But even after this substitution takes place, the old tension between the private and the public remains. Historicists in whom the desire for self-creation, for private autonomy, dominates (e.g.. Heidegeer and Foucault) still tend to see socialization as Nietzsche did - '

as antithetical to something deep within us. Historicists in whom the dcsirc for a more iust and free human community dominates (e.g., Dewey and Habermas) are still inclined to see the desire for private perfection as infected with "irrationalism" and "aestheticism." This book tries to do justice to both groups of historicist writers. 1 urge that we not try to choose between them but, rather, give them equal weight and then use them for different purposes. Authors like Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, Baudelaire, Proust, Heidewer, and Nabokov are useful as exemplars, as illustrations of what private perfection - a self-created, autonomous, human life - can be like. Authors such as Marx, Mill, Dewey, Habermas, and Rawls are fellow citizens rather than exemplars. They are engaged in a shared, social effort - the effort to make our institutions and practices more just and less cruel. We shall only think of these two kinds ofwriters as oppnreii if we think that a more comprehensive philosophical outlook would let us hold self-creation and justice, private perfection and human solidarity, in a single vision. There is no way in which philosophy, or any other theoretical discipline, will ever let us do that. The closest we will come to joining these two quests is to see the aim of a just and free society as letting its citizens be as privatistic, "irrationalist," ant1 aestheticist as they please so long as they do it on their own time - causing no harm to others and using no resources needed by those less advantaged. There are practical measures to be taken to accomplish this practical goal. Rut there is no way to bring self-creation together with justice at the level of theory. The vocabulary of self-creation is necessarily private, unshared, unsuited to argument. The vocabulary of justice is necessarily public and shared, a medium for argumentative exchange. If we could bring ourselves to accept the fact that no theory about the nature of Man or Society or Rationality, or anything else, is going to synthesize Nietzsche with Marx or Heidegger with Habermas, we could begin to think of the relation between writers on autonomy and writers on justicc as being like the relation between two kinds of tools - as little in need of synthesis as are paintbrushes and crowbars. One sort of writer lets LIS realize that the social virtues are not the only virtues, that some people have actually succeeded in re-creating themselves. We thereby become aware of our own half-articulate need to become a new person, one whom we as yet lack words to describe. The other sort reminds us of the failure of our institutions and practices to live up to the convictions to which we are already committed by the public, shared vocabulary we use in claily life. The one tells us that we need not speak only the language of the tribe, that we may find our own words, that we may have a responsibility to ourselves to find them. The other tells us that that INTRODUCTION responsibility is not the only one we have. Both are right, but there is no way to make both speak a single language. This book tries to show how things look if we drop the demand for a theory which unifies the public and private, and are content to treat the demands of self-creation and of human solidarity as equally valid, yet forever intommensurable. It sketches a figure whom I call the "liberal irozst." I borrow my definition of "liberal" from Judith Shklar, who says that liberals are the people who think that cruelty is the worst thing we do. I use "ironist" to name the sort of person who faces u p t o the contingency of his or her own most central beliefs and desires - someone sufficiently historicist and nominalist to have abandoned the idea that those central beliefs and desires refer back to something beyond the reach of time and chance. Liberal ironists are people who include among these ungroundable desires their own hope that suffering will be diminished, that the humiliation of human beings by other human beings may cease. For liberal ironrsts, there is no answer to the question "Why not be cruel?" - no noncircular theoretical backup for the belief that cruelty is horrible. Nor is there an answer to the question "How do you decide when to struggle against injustice and when to devote yourself to private pr~jzcts of self-creation?" This question strikes liberal ironists as just as hopeless as the questions "Is it right to deliver n innocents over to be tortured to save the lives of m x n other innocents? If so, what are the correct values of n and m?" or the question "When may one favor members of one's family, or one's community, over other, randomly chosen, human beings?" Anybody who thinks that there are well-grounded theoretical answers to this sort of question - algorithms for resolving moral dilemmas of this sort - is still, in his heart, a theologian or a metaphysician. He believes in an order beyond time and change which both determines the point of human existence and establishes a hierarchy of responsibilities. The ironist intellectuals who do not believe that there is such an order are far outnumbered (even in the lucky, rich, literate democracies) by people who believe that there must be one. Most nonintellectuals are still committed either to some form of religious faith or to some form of Enlightenment rationalism. So ironism has often seemed intrinsically -.- - hostile not only to democracy but to human solidarity - to solidarity with the mass of mankind, all those people who are convinced that such an order must exist. But it is not. Hostility to a particular historically conditioned and possibly transient form of solidarity is not hostility to solidarity as such. One of my aims in this book is to suggest the possibility of a liberal utopia: one in which ironism, in the relevant sense, is univenal. \ xv 1 1

j ' A postmetaphysical culture seems to me no more impossible than a postreligious one, and equally desirable. In my utopia, human solidarity would be seen not as a fact to be recognized by clearing away "prejudice" or burrowing down to previously hidden depths but, rather, as a goal to be achieved. It is to be achieved not by inquiry but by imagination, the imaginative ability to see strange people as fellow sufferers. Solidarity is not discovered by reflection but created. It is created by increasing our sensitivity to the particular details of the pain and humiliation of other, unfamiliar sorts of people. Such increased sensitivity makes it more difficult to marginalize people different from ourselves by thinking, "They do not feel it as we would," or "There must always be suffering, so why not let them suffer?" This process of coming to see other human beings as "one of us" rather than as "them" is a matter of detailed description of what unfamiliar people are like and of redescription of what we ourselves are like. This is a task not for theory but for genres such as ethnography, the journalist's report, the comic book, the docudrama, and, especially, the novel. Fiction like that of Dickens, Olive Schreiner, or Richard Wright gives us the details about kinds of suffering being endured by people to whom we had previously not attended. Fiction like that of Choderlos de Laclos, Henry James, or Nabokov gives us the details about what sorts of cruelty we ourselves are capable of, and thereby lets us redescribe ourselves. That is why the novel, the movie, and the TV program have, gradually but steadily, replaced the sermon and the treatise as the principal vehicles of moral change and progress. In my liberal utopia, this replacement would receive a kind of recognition which it still lacks. That recognition would be part of a general turn against theory and toward narrative. Such a turn would be emblematic of our having given up the attempt to hold all the sides of our life in a single vision, to describe them with a single vocabulary. It would amount to a recognition of what, in Chapter I, 1 call the "contingency of language" - the fact that there is no way to step outside the various vocabularies we have employed and find a metavocabulary - - which somehow takes account of an possihle vocabularies'~ all possible ways of judging and feeling. A historicist and nominalist culture of the sort I envisage would settle instead for narratives which connect the present with the past, on the one hand, and with utopian futures, on the other. More important, it would regard the realization of utopias, and the envisaging of still further utopias, as an endless process - an endless, proliferating realization of Freedom, rather than a convergence toward an already existing Truth.