Sin after the Death of God: A Culture Transformed?

Similar documents
6AANA032 Nineteenth-Century Continental Philosophy Syllabus Academic year 2013/14

March 10, 2014 Description of Images

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

The progression and regression of slave morality in Nietzsche s Genealogy: The moralization of bad conscience and indebtedness

Romans: The Revealing of Righteousness (part 6 of 9) The Law and Judgment

Nietzsche s Insight: Conscience as Amoral

Political Writings of Friedrich Nietzsche

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

NIETZSCHE CIRCLE SUBMISSION POLICY AND FORMAT. Circle (essays, reviews, interviews) and HYPERION (essays on current

Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke. M.A. Thesis Proposal. Department of Philosophy, CSULB. 25 May 2006

Epistemology and sensation

The Human Deficit according to Immanuel Kant: The Gap between the Moral Law and Human Inability to Live by It. Pieter Vos 1

A study guide in the doctrine of justification by faith. by Roger Smalling, D.Min

NIETZSCHE S NATURALISM

Naturalism, Minimalism, and the Scope of Nietzsche s Philosophical Psychology. Paul Katsafanas

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

[MJTM 15 ( )] BOOK REVIEW

Review on Heidegger and Philosophical Atheology

A Multitude of Selves: Contrasting the Cartesian and Nietzschean views of selfhood

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Ivan and Zosima: Existential Atheism vs. Existential Theism

- Nietzsche, Daybreak Introduction

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

True Empathy. Excerpts from the Workshop held at the Foundation for A Course in Miracles Temecula CA. Kenneth Wapnick, Ph.D.

UNIVERSITY OF EAST ANGLIA School of Politics, Philosophy, Language and Communication Studies Main Series UG Examination

The Restoration of God-consciousness in the Person and Work of Jesus of Nazareth

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Friedrich Nietzsche and European Nihilism Paul van Tongeren

Afraid of the Dark: Nagel and Rationalizing the Fear of Death

Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM. Section III: How do I know? Reading III.

Thus Spake Zarathustra (Dover Thrift Editions) By Friedrich Nietzsche, Thomas Common READ ONLINE

TO D D C. REAM. VER THE COURSE OF THE PAST FIFTEEN YEARS, intellectual historians have

The Meaning of Judgment. Excerpts from the Workshop held at the Foundation for A Course in Miracles Temecula CA. Kenneth Wapnick, Ph.D.

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte

KINGSBOROUGH COMMUNITY COLLEGE of The City University of New York. Common COURSE SYLLABUS

All equals many, but many does not equal all By John G. Reisinger, [edited by JAD]

Gospel Christianity. know that a man is not justified by observing the law, but by faith in Jesus Christ. Leaders Guide Course 1. Galatians 2: 11-16

It is with deep respect that the author of Hebrews compares and contrasts the Old Covenant practices with the final work of Jesus Christ.

Religious Studies. Name: Institution: Course: Date:

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

CONSCIOUSNESS. Joseph S. Benner. PAPER No. 33 SEPTEMBER, 1931

The Will to Power. Benjamin C. Sax 1

Liberal Theology Friedrich Schleiermacher ( ). The Father of Liberal theology. Pastored the large and influential Trinity Church

Individual and Community in Nietzsche s Philosophy

F. Rachel Magdalene Universität Leipzig Leipzig, Germany

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7

The Cosmological Argument: A Defense

NIETZSCHE AND THE RECIPROCAL RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN ART AND SCIENCE: A QUESTION OF PHILOSOPHICAL METHODOLOGY

True Empathy. Excerpts from the Workshop held at the Foundation for A Course in Miracles Temecula CA. Kenneth Wapnick, Ph.D.

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

The Things Freely Given Us of God. Complete in Christ

Man Alone with Himself

Eric Schliesser Philosophy and Moral Sciences, Ghent University ª 2011, Eric Schliesser

Behavior and Other Minds: A Response to Functionalists

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma

World-Wide Ethics. Chapter One. Individual Subjectivism

Discuss whether it is possible to be a Christian and in a same sex relationship.

What It Means to Be a Teacher of God. Excerpts from the Workshop held at the Foundation for A Course in Miracles Temecula CA. Kenneth Wapnick, Ph.D.

Who Do You Accept? Romans 15:07a. Sermon Transcripts by Rev. Ernest O'Neill

Plato's Allegory of the Cave

Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington

Bare Life and Political Fiction: Nietzsche, Agamben, and Biopolitics

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Rebellion, Revolution, and Religion

SPINOZA, SUBSTANCE, AND SUBJECTIVITY IN HEGEL S LECTURES ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION

Kant s Copernican Revolution

revealed as Christ the Lord and He is the Son of the Most High. In other words, the Lord God is

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Nietzsche on human greatness

The Meaning of Judgment. Excerpts from the Workshop held at the Foundation for A Course in Miracles Temecula CA. Kenneth Wapnick, Ph.D.

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

Open Research Online The Open University s repository of research publications and other research outputs

Section I : Freedom Now from the Bonds of Sin Review:

Phil 2303 Intro to Worldviews Philosophy Department Dallas Baptist University Dr. David Naugle

Bonhoeffer: Discipleship Towards the World. Dr. Robert Saler Lutheran House of Studies Christian Theological Seminary, Indianapolis

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

The Guardian of Our Souls May 14, 2017 Dr. Frank J. Allen, Jr., Pastor First Presbyterian Church of Kissimmee, Florida

Christopher Janaway, Beyond Selflessness: Reading Nietzsche s Genealogy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xi

Guilt And Thankfulness

Thinking in Narrative: Seeing Through To the Myth in Philosophy. By Joe Muszynski

Genesis 3C (2011) The fall of man and woman, and the curses of God. They knew they were naked and made effort to clothe themselves

This paper serves as an enquiry into whether or not a theory of metaphysics can grow

A MATTER OF THE HEART Romans 2:11-29

A Fundamental Thinking Error in Philosophy

PHIL10047: The Early Continentals: Hegel and Nietzsche

John Scottus Eriugena: Analysing the Philosophical Contribution of an Forgotten Thinker

What did Nietzsche think that it was possible to learn from the past?

Nietzsche, epiphenomenalism and causal relationships between self- affirmation and the internal constitution of the drives

Nietzsche s Critique of Morality and Revaluation of Values

J.f. Stephen s On Fraternity And Mill s Universal Love 1

GOD S JUDGEMENT ON SIN ROMANS 8:1-17

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Leibniz on Justice as a Common Concept: A Rejoinder to Patrick Riley. Andreas Blank, Tel Aviv University. 1. Introduction

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

Healing the Dream of Sickness. Excerpts from the Workshop held at the Foundation for A Course in Miracles Temecula CA. Kenneth Wapnick, Ph.D.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Transcription:

Sin after the Death of God: A Culture Transformed? By Renée Reitsma Paper presented at the 20 th European Conference on Philosophy of Religion (Münster) Introduction In recent years Nietzsche s On the Genealogy of Morals has been getting increasing attention in Anglo-American Nietzsche literature. Scholars such as Christopher Janaway, David Owen, Aaron Ridley and Lawrence Hatab have dedicated books to the work, and Brian Leiter s research on Nietzsche s moral philosophy draws heavily on the Genealogy. 1 However, there are important, if not essential, elements of the Genealogy that remain underexamined in contemporary scholarship. Today I will talk about one of these undervalued elements: namely Nietzsche s discussion of sin. I will argue that if we take his account of sin seriously, we find not only part of his critique of Christianity, but also a problematization of the separation of cultural and religious elements in a culture or society. The second and third essay of the Genealogy are of particular importance to this project in the second Nietzsche sets up his account of the origin of sin, and in the third essay this account is deepened by Nietzsche s analysis of the ascetic priest s role in the promotion of sin. In this paper I will first explicate Nietzsche s account of sin in the Genealogy, with a particular focus not on the historical narrative offered in the Second Essay but on the use and explanatory narratives of sin offered by the ascetic priest. I will also look in detail at Nietzsche s account of sin after the death of God, and in particular the relation between the Christian God and sin. I will then argue that Nietzsche s analysis of sin shows us that drawing 1 See Hatab, L.J., 2008, Nietzsche s On the Genealogy of Morality: An Introduction (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), Janaway, C., 2007, Beyond Selflessness (Oxford: Oxford University Press), Ridley, A., 1998, Nietzsche s Conscience (New York: Cornell University Press), Owen, D., 2007, Nietzsche s Genealogy of Morality (Stocksfield, UK: Acumen Press), Leiter, B., 2002, Nietzsche on Morality (London: Routledge). 1

a clear demarcation between cultural and religious elements of society is not as straightforward as is sometimes assumed in for example, mainstream discussions of secularism. Nietzsche s account of sin The desire for an explanation of suffering, which Schopenhauer refers to as the metaphysical need, takes a particular form in the third essay of the Genealogy; Nietzsche writes for every suffering man instinctively seeks a cause for his suffering: more precisely a doer, more definitely a guilty doer [ ] (GM 3:15). 2 There is a desire to know the reason for one s suffering in order to find some relief from this suffering, and more specifically this is a desire to find the cause, to find someone or something that one can blame this suffering on only this will bring relief. As opposed to merely desiring an explanation for suffering, the person desires someone to blame outside of herself. This desire is met by the explanations offered by the ascetic priest. This figure, who takes centre stage in the Third Essay of the Genealogy, appears as someone who can in fact point towards the guilty doer. As Nietzsche writes in section 20; Man, suffering from himself in some way [ ], uncertain as to why and wherefore, desiring reason [ ] and behold! he receives a hint [ ] from the ascetic priest, the first hint as to the cause of his suffering: he is to seek it in himself, in some guilt, in a piece of the past, he should understand his suffering itself as a state of punishment. [ ] (GM 3:20). We can see here that the guilty party the priest points to is not external to the person that is suffering. Instead, the ascetic priest changes the direction by telling the suffering person that she herself is to blame. This is an absolutely essential point in Nietzsche s discussion of the ascetic priest. Instead of being able to point blame outwards, the ascetic priest convinces people to turn it inwards, to find themselves guilty. By doing this, the ascetic priest offers a meaning to the suffering; he explains why people are suffering, he brings suffering under the 2 All quotations from Nietzsche s Genealogy of Morals are from the following edition; Nietzsche, F., 1998, On the Genealogy of Morals, trans. Smith, D. (Oxford: Oxford University Press). 2

perspective of guilt (GM 3:28). It is our fault that we suffer and we should understand it as a punishment. This explanation of suffering by pointing towards guilt is one in which human beings are sinful and unredeemable, and the only relief we may ever find will be in another world. The purpose and meaning that follow from these ideas are not aimed at our world, they involve a hatred of the human and result in an aversion to life (GM3:28). The story the ascetic priest tells us is not only that we are to blame for suffering but it also places the only hope of a better life, of a life without suffering after this life. The positing of an afterlife like that of the kingdom of heaven helps those who are suffering to deal with their current state, because they are given the vision and hope of a world without suffering. But that world is not the world in which they live now, which explains why an aversion to life now occurs and why they will nothingness in this world. This is what Nietzsche calls the will to nothingness. People want to accept the priests explanation for suffering, because finding yourself guilty and sinful is better than not having an explanation for suffering. Nietzsche thinks that this also illustrates what he calls the will to find oneself guilty. For example, he talks about the human will to misunderstand suffering, its reinterpretation into feelings of guilt. We desire an explanation of suffering over anything else, and considering yourself as inherently sinful is still preferable to not having an explanation of suffering. We will to misunderstand suffering as long as this misunderstanding provides us with some peace of mind, that it has other suffering as its consequence is not a problem; this is the suffering that we desire, the suffering that we will. We can see this idea expressed quite forcefully in section 22 of the Second Essay of the Genealogy. It is also in this section that we can begin to see the importance of God with 3

relation to the interpretation of suffering and sin the ascetic priest offers. Nietzsche writes that; In God he seizes upon the ultimate antithesis he can find to his real and irredeemable animal instincts, he reinterprets these self-same animal instincts as debt/guilt before God [ ]. We have here a sort of madness of the will showing itself in mental cruelty which is absolutely unparalleled: man s will to find himself guilty and condemned without hope of reprieve [ ]. This passage gives us a glimpse of the importance of the ideal of God in relation to guilt God functions here as the ultimate antithesis to our instincts, and we then feel a Schuld towards God. So what does Nietzsche mean when he talks about God? Nietzsche s Godconcept is not one where we can point at several attributes and add them altogether to make an accurate representation of God. Instead, he seems primarily concerned with the way that people relate themselves to God. When he importantly describes God as the uttermost example of godliness so far realized on earth this does not mean that the Christian God meets certain objective standards of what a God is and happens to just tick all the boxes. What is important, instead, is that people consider God to be the uttermost example of godliness in comparison to themselves. In some of Nietzsche s work there does seem to be an attempt to capture God; in Human, All-Too-Human, for example, he focuses on God as being nonegoistic, something that he says it is impossible for people to be yet is upheld as an ideal. We want to be non-egoistic yet are incapable of being so with the addition of a God who is actually only capable of non-egoistic actions, this failure is felt even more strongly. However, in later works concerning this relation between God and humans Nietzsche does not focus on specific aspects of God other than perfection. The question of course remains as to what this perfection refers to, but it is not the specific attributes that make this God so important, but the kind of perceived relation between God and humans. In Human, All-Too-Human 132 Nietzsche writes that people compare themselves with a being who is said to be capable only of those actions which are called un-egoistic, and to live 4

in the perpetual consciousness of an unselfish mode of thought and that it is because people gaze into this clear mirror that [their] image appears to [them] so dark, so unusually warped (HH 132). 3 What we can take from this is that our reflections would not look so warped if there were not this God to compare ourselves to, if there was not this ideal in place that we know we will always fall short of. We can see that in Nietzsche s story the kind of Godconcept one has effects people s own self-image: the more perfect a God is perceived to be, the less perfect humans will seem. In the Genealogy Nietzsche writes that the sense of guilt towards the divinity has continued to grow for several thousands of years, and always in the same proportion as the concept and sense of god has grown and risen into the heights (GM2:20). There is a very important relation for Nietzsche between how people view themselves, and in this context how corrupted, guilty or sinful people feel themselves to be, and the kind of God they uphold. Not only do we fall short in any attempt to live up to this ideal of God, but this same conception of God s nature allows sin and guilt, and a sense of indebtedness towards God to grow tremendously. We can see this especially in the narrative of the crucifixion. The narratives and imagery of Christianity, as well as the work of the ascetic priests, can be explained as being used to increase our feelings of indebtedness, our feelings of sin. Sin after the death of God If we understand sin to have grown because of the priest s explanation for suffering, then it should have become apparent that this is heavily reliant on a certain concept of God. It would therefore not be strange to think that once this specific notion of God is no longer important to most people that is, when God is dead - that sin would thereby disappear. This is however 3 All quotations from Human All- Too- Human and The Wanderer and His Shadow are taken from the following edition; Nietzsche, F., 2006, Human, All- Too- Human, trans. Zimmern, H., and Cohn, P.V. (Mineola, NY: Dover Publications). 5

not what Nietzsche tells us. Even though sin as it exists could not have become what it is without a certain notion of God, this does not mean that it can no longer exist without this notion of God. What was necessary for its origin may not be necessary for its continuation. We can see this thought in The Wanderer and His Shadow, where Nietzsche writes that [ ]it was Christianity which first brought sin into the world. Belief in the cure which it offered has now been shaken to its deepest roots: but belief in the sickness which it taught and propagated continues to exist (WS: 78). In sections 20 and 21 of the Genealogy we can find the same thought. In section 20 Nietzsche writes that "the prospect that the complete and definitive victory of atheism might redeem mankind entirely from this feeling of indebtedness towards its origins, its causa prima, cannot be dismissed" (GM2:20). This passage indicates a hesitation on Nietzsche s part: can sin, or "this feeling of indebtedness towards [ ] origins" be removed once God is out of the picture? However, he answers this question in section 21 where he tells us the following; [ ] at the end of the previous paragraph [I] even talked [ ] as if these concepts were from now on necessarily approaching their end, now that their pre-condition, the belief in our creditor, in God, has collapsed. The real situation is fearfully different. The moralization of the concepts guilt and duty, their being pushed back into bad conscience, actually represents a attempt to reverse the direction of the development just described, or at least to halt its movement. The goal now is the pessimistic one of closing off once and for all the prospect of a definitive repayment [ ]. (GM2:21). We see here that Nietzsche s hesitation has turned into an outright rejection of the thesis that sin might not continue to exist after the death of God. Nietzsche suggests in this passage that the moralization of guilt has resulted not in the demise of guilt, but in guilt turning back against the debtor now that the creditor, God, is out of the picture. This turning against the debtor leads to an irredeemability of guilt an impossibility of redemption, of repayment. (GM2:21). 6

This impossibility of redemption appears, because even though sin remains, we are no longer able to rely on the redemptive or explanatory narratives that Christianity offered us. The thought is that the metaphysical need for explanations for suffering does not go away with the death of God (even though I think for Nietzsche this might be the eventual goal). In fact, it is made all the more strong because suddenly we cannot appeal to the figure of God and the idea of an afterlife anymore. We are stuck with a feeling of indebtedness towards the world (a remnant of the Christian narrative) and also a feeling of indebtedness towards God who we have killed. And as a consequence of our murdering God, we can no longer have any hope of redemption. Nietzsche takes this very seriously he argues that our culture, and perhaps even our psychological instincts have changed since Christianity, and in particular since the ascetic priest s use of moralized guilt and sin. We can see this, for example, when contrasting it with Nietzsche s writings on ancient Greek culture. In that culture, Nietzsche says, bad conscience was kept at bay by the gods because it was the gods that took on guilt. In Christian culture, guilt is taken on by humans and Nietzsche tells us that this remains the case even when God is dead. This is perhaps one of the shadows he tells us about in The Gay Science, one of the shadows that linger even though God is no longer in the picture. This is why Nietzsche would not want to say, and I think he is right in this, that sin is no longer religious. It is so problematic for Nietzsche precisely because it is religious yet its grounding has disappeared. Conclusion If we take Nietzsche s analysis of sin after the death of God seriously, then definitions of secularism that focus special attention on belief in God or a self-identification of someone as being religious seem to fall short. There is the possibility that there are elements in our society or culture that are religious in some significant way without involving a belief in God. Of 7

course, one could argue that sin without God is no longer religious sin, or Christian sin, but I do not think that is convincing. Even without God sin is importantly Christian in the sense that the loss of God is immanently and importantly felt and experienced as a problem. It seems to preclude any possibility of redemption, precisely because it is both religious and does no longer involve God. This strikes me as a very important sense in which religion is felt and experienced, even if (or especially?) when belief in God has decreased. Nietzsche helps us conceptualize this experience, and shows us that when we want to analyse our culture, our experiences within this culture and its religious elements, there is much more to consider than belief in God or a self-identification as religious. By taking sin as an example we can see that there is a way in which people or culture has transformed since the emergence of Christianity. This change does not mean that ideas such as sin should no longer be considered religious, but religious ideals that have been taken up can still play a large part in our culture even when explicit belief in God or the self-identification of people as religious has significantly reduced. And these elements or psychological instincts can still only be understood with reference to religion, and Christianity in particular. This is why Nietzsche s potential solution, the reevaluation of all values, requires a radical change. Even if God is dead our thinking (perhaps even our psychological constitutions) is not only historically Christian but presently so. Nietzsche hereby helps us understand contemporary secularized (Western European) culture in a rich way that does justice to the complexities of the interplay between religion and culture. 8

Bibliography Berger, P.L., 1973, The Social Reality of Religion (Middlesex: Penguin Books) Girard, R., 1984, Dionysus versus the Crucified in MLN Vol.99, No.4, pp. 816-835 Hatab, L.J., 2008, Nietzsche s On the Genealogy of Morality: An Introduction (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press) Janaway, C., 2007, Beyond Selflessness (Oxford: Oxford University Press) May, S., 2011, Why Nietzsche is still in the morality game in May, S. (ed.), Nietzsche s On the Genealogy of Morality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 78-100 Nietzsche, F., 1980-88, Sämmtliche Werke: Kritische Studienausgabe, eds. Colli, G. and Montinari, M. (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter) Nietzsche, F., 1998, On the Genealogy of Morals, trans. Smith, D. (Oxford: Oxford University Press) Nietzsche, F., 2006, The Gay Science, trans. Nauckhoff, J. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press) Nietzsche, F., 2006, Human, All-Too-Human, trans. Zimmern, H., and Cohn, P.V. (Mineola, NY: Dover Publications) Reginster, 2011, The Genealogy of Guilt in May, S. (ed.), Nietzsche s On the Genealogy of Morality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 56-77 Ridley, A., 2005, Guilt Before God, or God Before Guilt? The Second Essay of Nietzsche s Genealogy in Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Issue 29, pp. 35-45 Risse, M., 2001, The Second Treatise in On the Genealogy of Morality: Nietzsche on the Origin of the Bad Conscience in European Journal of Philosophy 9:1, pp. 55-81 Risse, M., 2005, On God and Guilt: A Reply to Aaron Ridley in Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Issue 29, p. 46-53 Strong, T.B., 1988, Friedrich Nietzsche and the Politics of Transfiguration (Berkeley: University of California Press) 9