Feminist Epistemology Feminism in Analytic Philosophy Week One, MT 2012, Oxford

Similar documents
Dr. Evangelia Papadaki. Curriculum Vitae

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Theories of epistemic justification can be divided into two groups: internalist and

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

What Does Islamic Feminism Teach to a Secular Feminist?

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Course Organiser and Lecturer: Dr. Aidan McGlynn DSB 6.12)

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

Saying too Little and Saying too Much. Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

Cosmopolitan Theory and the Daily Pluralism of Life

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

Saying too Little and Saying too Much Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

The Assurance of God's Faithfulness

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

The Earth Charter and Global Ethics. Nigel Dower

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

PRÉCIS THE ORDER OF PUBLIC REASON: A THEORY OF FREEDOM AND MORALITY IN A DIVERSE AND BOUNDED WORLD

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

Huemer s Clarkeanism

UNIVERSITY OF WATERLOO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHY 110A,

Kantianism, Liberalism, and Feminism: Resisting Oppression // Reviews // Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews // University of Notre Dame

Replies to critics. Miranda FRICKER

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

SYMPOSIUM ON FEMINISM AND REASON

EXAM PREP (Semester 2: 2018) Jules Khomo. Linguistic analysis is concerned with the following question:

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Kantian Constructivism, the Issue of Scope, and Perfectionism: O Neill on Ethical Standing

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

Secularization in Western territory has another background, namely modernity. Modernity is evaluated from the following philosophical point of view.

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Jacob Martin Rump, PhD Symposium: Contemporary Work in Phenomenology Boston Phenomenology Circle Boston University, 1 April 2016

145 Philosophy of Science

Nagel, T. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.

Christian Evidences. The Verification of Biblical Christianity, Part 2. CA312 LESSON 06 of 12

Philosophy and Ideology*

Human rights, universalism and conserving human rights practice

O Neill and Korsgaard on the Construction of Normativity

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

ARE YOU READY? Lecture 2 Loss of Truth

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Bioethics and Epistemology: A Response to Professor Arras t

Moral Communities in a Pluralistic Nation

[MJTM 14 ( )] BOOK REVIEW

DEMOCRACY, DELIBERATION, AND RATIONALITY Guido Pincione & Fernando R. Tesón

THE MORAL FIXED POINTS: REPLY TO CUNEO AND SHAFER-LANDAU

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

What Counts as Feminist Theory?

Philosophical Review.

Review of Erik J. Wielenberg: Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism

Terence CUNEO, The Normative Web. An Argument for Moral Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008, 263 pp., 46.99, ISBN

the paradigms have on the structure of research projects. An exploration of epistemology, ontology

Psychological and Ethical Egoism

Reply to Brooke Alan Trisel James Tartaglia *

THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia ISSN:

READING REVIEW I: Gender in the Trinity David T. Williams (Jared Shaw)

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

The Catholic intellectual tradition, social justice, and the university: Sometimes, tolerance is not the answer

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Philosophy 102 Ethics Course Description: Course Requirements and Expectations

On Popper, Problems and Problem-Solving: A Review of Cruickshank and Sassower's Democratic Problem-Solving

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

Harman s Moral Relativism

Assertion and Inference

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Critical Scientific Realism

A Framework for the Good

UNDERGRADUATE STUDIES CERTIFICATE IN PHILOSOPHY (CERTIFICATES)

Brandom s five-step program for modal health

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas

ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY

appearance is often different from reality, and it s reality that counts.

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Mark Schroeder s Hypotheticalism: Agent-neutrality, Moral Epistemology, and Methodology

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

Tolerance in French Political Life

Transcription:

Feminist Epistemology Feminism in Analytic Philosophy Week One, MT 2012, Oxford Readings: 1. Langton, Rae, Feminism in epistemology: Exclusion and objectification 2. Fricker, Miranda, Feminism in epistemology: Pluralism without postmodernism 3. Richard Rorty, Feminism and Pragmatism 1. How can feminism contribute to philosophy? The framing question of this reading group is: what can feminism contribute to analytic philosophy? But prior to this question lurks, we might think, a more fundamental question: why should we think that feminism has anything to contribute to analytic philosophy? One might worry, after all, that the discourses of analytic philosophy and feminism are simply so different in aim that thinking one has something substantive to contribute to the other is to commit a sort of category error. If feminism is merely the political project of alleviating women s oppression and exclusion, then what can feminism really offer philosophy? It can of course diagnose and make recommendations about the practice of philosophy, and thus make a sociological contribution to philosophy. And of course feminist concerns could also provide fodder to those areas of philosophy, like ethics and political philosophy, that are already concerned with issues of oppression and discrimination. But this wouldn t really constitute a feminist perspective contributing to philosophy itself. But to understand feminism as I have described it as the political project of alleviating women s oppression is to not fully grasp it. For feminists don t merely advocate for women s equality in terms of life chances, but also for public recognition and inclusions of women s voices, perspectives and experiences. Or, put another way, feminism sees women s exclusion not merely as consisting in having worse life chances than men, but also in having had their voices, perspectives and experiences systematically denied, marginalised, undervalued, and vilified. Alleviation of discrimination of this sort results in much more than changes in how our societies and professional communities are organised. It changes how we think and talk and theorise about the world. Which is to say, it changes how we do philosophy. But this isn t to say that the relationship between feminism and analytic philosophy is not vexed. For there are some feminists who see the values and methods of analytic philosophy as being the mere tools of male oppression; these feminists think that philosophy is rotten at its core, irredeemable. As such, the 1

challenge for someone who considers herself or himself both an analytic philosopher and a feminist, is how to reconcile their feminism with the values and methods of analytic philosophy. In other words, how to make a feminist contribution to philosophy without thereby destroying philosophy. The two main readings from today Rae Langton s Exclusion and objectification and Miranda Fricker s Pluralism without postmodernism address just this challenge. Both pieces endeavour to show that feminism can make a contribution to philosophy, and epistemology in particular, without destroying it. And both pieces do this first by offering examples of ways feminism can contribute to first-order questions in epistemology, and second by attempting to defuse common feminist critiques of epistemology in Langton s case, the feminist critique of objectivity as inevitably leading to objectification, and in Fricker s case, the critique of reason as a mask for coercion. I m going to focus on how Langton and Fricker respond to these antiepistemological critiques of objectivity and reason. But I ve created a little taxonomy with examples of the ways they suggest that a feminist perspective can unproblematically contribute to first-order questions in epistemology. So, first, feminism can contribute to epistemology by creating new questions and concepts, second by offering novel answers to traditional questions, and thirdly by discrediting traditional answers by showing how they tacitly employ a gendered perspective. While Langton and Fricker are happy with these kinds of feminist contributions to epistemology, they want to defend against the more radical feminist contribution which seeks to destroy or deconstruct epistemology. And they share a common strategy for defusing these anti-epistemological critiques. Langton argues that only sometimes does objectivity lead to objectification, and Fricker that only sometimes does reason mask coercion. Their motivation for so arguing is not merely their attachment to epistemology qua analytic philosophers, but also their view that the anti-epistemological stance of some feminists is in fact unhelpful for feminism. Feminism, they think, needs epistemology. 2. Langton on Objectivity and Objectification Langton takes as her target the radical feminist view, exemplified by Catharine Mackinnon, that the practice of epistemic objectivity is itself ethically problematic: Objectivity is the epistemological stance of which objectification is the social process, of which male dominance is the politics, the acted out social practice. That is, to look at the world objectively is to objectify it (Mackinnon, as quoted in Langton, 135). Langton, largely rehearsing an argument made by Sally Haslanger, argues that what is correct in Mackinnon s claim is that the epistemological norm of assumed objectivity can sometimes lead to objectification. 2

The Norm of Assumed Objectivity tells us (roughly) to count observed regularities in an object (e.g. a planet, an animal, a person) as genuine regularities stemming from the nature of the object, and to constrain our action to accommodate the nature of that object. One objectifies an object (e.g. a planet, an animal, a person) when one (roughly) views it as an object for the satisfaction of one s desire, when one forces it to have the properties one desires of it, and one believes that it has those properties by nature. E.g. a man objectifies a woman when he desires and believes her to be submissive by her very nature, and forces her to behave submissively. The norm of Assumed Objectivity leads to objectification, Langton and Haslanger argue, in situations of extreme power differential. In such situations, what the powerful desire of the disempowered they typically believe is true (since the powerful tend to believe that the world is as they desire it to be), and what they believe of the disempowered because of their self-fulfilling belief becomes true. E.g. if (powerful) men desire that (disempowered) women be submissive, they will come to believe it, and then because they believe it, women will in turn behave submissively. If a man (or woman) then follows the norm of assumed objectivity, he will come to believe (truly) that women are submissive and (falsely) that they are so by nature. They will also accommodate their actions to the submissive nature of women, thereby making women behave more submissively. So, in situations of power differential, following the norms of objectivity can lead to objectification. So in these situations, the practice of objectivity is ethically problematic. But this is not to say, Langton argues, that objectivity always leads to objectification: [O]ne can be objective without being an objectifier. Following the norm of Assumed Objectivity in other everyday activities gardening, for instance will have no untoward results (Langton 142) Langton ends with the suggestion (more worked out in Fricker) that the radical feminist view that would jettison all of epistemology is in fact bad for feminism, leaving a mere pragmatic critique : The feminist critique is a practical one: Assumed Objectivity has bad consequences for women. A merely pragmatic critique has its shortcomings, though. For one thing, if feminists use pragmatic arguments, we can hardly complain when others do. Objectified women may complain, it s bad for us; and objectifiers may respond, yes, but it s good for us. We can add to this pragmatic critique a philosophical one: the norm of Assumed Objectivity is not just bad for women, it is simply bad. Applied in conditions of gender hierarchy, although it leads some objectifiers to self- 3

fulfilling true beliefs, it also reliably leads them to false beliefs (Langton 142, emphasis added). There are two questions I would like to raise about Langton s argument. First, what justifies her claim that Assumed Objectivity is bad in some cases, e.g. when it comes to women, but not others, e.g. gardening? The difference, according to Langton, is that when we follow the norms of Assumed Objectivity with regard to women, we re-inforce women s disempowered status and we end up with false beliefs about the naturalness of that disempowerment. But how are we meant to know this and to know that this is not true of, say, plants? For it seems the only way we can know that a seemingly natural phenomenon, like women s submissiveness, is actually the result of self-fulfilling construction, is by ceasing to engage in assumed objectivity and seeing what happens. For example, to stop treating individuals like women, or slaves, but equally perhaps children and animals, even plants as objects, and to see what happens. But then we cannot decide from the outset, as Langton wants to do, which of our practices of objectivity are bad, i.e. likely to lead to objectification, and which of them are fine, like being objective about gardening. The only way we can figure that out is to see all instances of objectivity as potentially leading to objectification which is to see the situation much as Mackinnon describes it, where all practices of objectivity are ethically suspect. The second question I want to ask Langton is about her comments on the limits of pragmatism: (2) Why isn t the pragmatic argument that the Norm of Assumed Objectivity can hurt women sufficient for feminism? Why does feminism need to argue against objectivity on philosophical grounds as well, i.e. by showing that it can lead to false beliefs? I ll return to this question in my discussion of Miranda Fricker s more extended argument that feminism needs epistemology. 3. Fricker on pluralism without postmodernism Fricker addresses the postmodern feminist claim that knowledge and reason are both metaphysically and politically suspect concepts: that they are social constructions designed by the powerful to reinforce their power. Epistemology, as the study of knowledge and reason, has no place within feminism. Fricker resists this claim by arguing that it presupposes a Kantian understanding of the conditions for the vindication of reason as a genuine source of authority. On a Kantian view, reason requires freedom either of the robust metaphysical kind or (according to a constructivist reading of Kant) of a political kind. On the latter interpretation, what is genuinely reasonable is what is acceptable to everyone 4

in an ideal discursive situation in which no alien authorities inhibit participation or expression of dissent. But if one believes with Foucault that all discursive situations are constituted by power relations, then there can be no discursive situations that are genuinely free. And thus appeals to reason are, by necessity, masked appeals to force. Fricker s proposal is to jettison the Kantian standard for the vindication of reason. Instead, she wants us to draw a commonsensical (Humean) distinction between authoritative and authoritarian appeals to reason. While power might be inescapable in human relations, Fricker argues that there are genuine appeals to reason. What we need to do is sort out those appeals to reason that are genuine and those that are coercive, on a case-by-case basis, rather than be suspicious of reason in general. Fricker then argues that the postmodern suspicion of reason per se is in fact detrimental for feminism: Any political inadequacy we may suspect of postmodernism is likely to flow from an epistemological source. That source is now in view. The insistence on the localness of all norms or judgement renders postmodernism incapable of sustaining ordinary judgements, such as the judgement that some forms of social organization are plain unjust, or that some beliefs are plain false. The question whether any particular critical judgement is reasonable cannot depend on the agreement of those who happen to be one s interlocutors their interests may be served very nicely by the discursive status quo Suppose someone protests Equal pay for equal work!, or Slavery is wrong!. And suppose the protest is met with a shrug of cynical insouciance from the powers that be. Postmodernism is unfit to characterize that response as unreasonable, or unjustified, or even inappropriate, for who is to say which language game the authorities may priviosionally have agreed to play? Of course, no other epistemological view can guarantee that dissenting voices are given their due What is at issue is the authority of the critical thoughts we may voice and of others response to them (150) If the powerful are merely expressing themselves when they tell others how the world is, then so too are the powerless only in the case of the powerless nobody is listening. The problem with the postmodernist charge of terrorism (or imperialism, or authoritarianism) against a practice of reason is that it is hopelessly indiscriminate (151) I have two questions for Fricker: (1) To what extent do we have an intuitive grasp of the authoritative/authoritarian distinction that is not boringly conservative? Is our commonsensical distinction really sufficient for a genuinely progressive politics? (2) How successful is Fricker s argument that feminism needs epistemology which is to say, a realist understanding of reason? 5

This is a version of the same question I wanted to raise about the Langton reading. To say something about this I will turn, finally, to our third reading, Rorty s Feminism and Pragmatism. 3. Does feminism need epistemology? Langton and Fricker vs. Rorty Both Langton and Fricker argue that the radical feminist critique of epistemology is bad for feminism: that, in an important sense, feminism needs a realist epistemology. Feminism needs universal reason and objectivity. But in what sense needs? Let s briefly canvas some options. First, one might think that feminism needs epistemology in the sense that a discourse of epistemic realism is instrumentally useful, and perhaps necessary, for achieving political ends. So one is more likely to be able to get things to change if one talks about, say, universal human rights or the demands of justice. While I think this is probably true, this cannot be the full extent of Langton and Fricker s claim. For Rorty is himself happy to acknowledge that feminists must sometimes speak in what he calls the universalist vulgar. Something deeper seems to be at stake for Langton and Fricker when they claim that feminism needs epistemology. Perhaps they mean that, as a psychological matter, feminists would be better off being epistemological realists. Fricker suggests that there is something psychologically difficult about being a feminist who is not also an epistemic realist. She writes: We may well doubt our prospects for psychological health in a life where we cannot quite take seriously even our most deeply held beliefs and values (Fricker 152). I find myself unconvinced by Fricker s claim. People who are committed to forms of postmodern or poststructural anti-realism seem perfectly capable of simultaneously advocating for real progressive change: just think for example of Catharine Mackinnon s longstanding advocacy against pornography and sexual harassment. And, as Rorty argues, it might even be the case that an anti-realist self-conception might be, as a psychological matter, beneficial to the political radical, for it can liberate one from the need to build up one s political programme from first principles or to embed it within a general theory of oppression or injustice. A third way in which I think we can interpret the putative need feminism has for epistemology is what I call the metaphysical or authoritative sense of need. What is at stake for Fricker and Langton, it seems, is whether feminists have genuine authority on their sides, or whether they are just expressing dissatisfaction. If there is no universal reason and there is no objective standpoint, then feminism is just another outcry from just another perspective. 6

What does Rorty have to say to this worry? I take his main point to be this. He suggests that we must liberate ourselves from the myth that there are any authorities external to ourselves, any authorities which can be on our side in the way that Fricker and Langton desire: whether that authority be God, or History, or Reason or Justice. But this does not mean that we have to collapse into the view that our normative claims are mere expressions of preference. For the alternative to external authority is not, on Rorty s view, mere expression of dissatisfaction, but rather creative, political prophecy. Just as the artist does not worry about whether he has an external authority on his side that justifies his creation, the political prophet need not worry about whether she has an external authority that justifies imagined Utopia. And to the extent that the artist or political prophet does have what we might call authority, it comes from the liveliness and force of their creation, not the relationship of that creation to something outside of it that validates or justifies it. Thus Rorty thinks that feminism, understood as a prophetic political movement, has no need of epistemology and is indeed better off without it. Langton and Fricker, I take it, would be quite unconvinced. For them, the relationship between feminism and epistemology is symbiotic: epistemology needs a feminist perspective as a corrective to its sometimes gendered tendencies, but equally, feminism needs epistemology to anchor and legitimate it. Just what the relationship between feminism and epistemology is, or perhaps should be, is something I will now turn over to the group for discussion. 7

Feminism in Analytic Philosophy MT Thursdays 10.30-12.30 Email Affiliation (BPhil, DPhil, etc.) 8