-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

Similar documents
Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

THE SEPARATION OF LAW AND MORALS

PHL271 Handout 2: Hobbes on Law and Political Authority. Many philosophers of law treat Hobbes as the grandfather of legal positivism.

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

Kant, Deontology, & Respect for Persons

HUME AND HIS CRITICS: Reid and Kames

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

Why Creation Science must be taught in schools

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 2017/18. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

We recommend you cite the published version. The publisher s URL is:

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 20118/19. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Social Rules and Legal Theory

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

The Making and Breaking of Promises

The ontology of human rights and obligations

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

5 A Modal Version of the

SARI KISILEVSKY. wholly explained by social facts. Orthodox natural law challenges this position: a rule is

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood

Mark Greenberg, UCLA 1

NOT SO PROMISING AFTER ALL: EVALUATOR-RELATIVE TELEOLOGY AND COMMON-SENSE MORALITY

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Varieties of Apriority

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Part II: The Nature of Law and Natural Law

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

A moral law for the jungle: a Kantian exploration in corporate environmental ethics

Jeffrey, Richard, Subjective Probability: The Real Thing, Cambridge University Press, 2004, 140 pp, $21.99 (pbk), ISBN

Citation: 59 Notre Dame L. Rev. xv

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

The Prospective View of Obligation

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Brian Leiter (ed), Objectivity in Law and Morals, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, xi pp, hb

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Oxford Scholarship Online

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Templates for Research Paper

Accounting for Moral Conflicts

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

Genre Guide for Argumentative Essays in Social Science

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

1/8. Reid on Common Sense

Legal Subjectivity and the Basis of Citizenship in Aristotle's Philosophy of Law

Naturalism and is Opponents

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Apostasy and Conversion Kishan Manocha

A Priori Bootstrapping

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Transcription:

Citation: 21 Isr. L. Rev. 113 1986 Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org) Sun Jan 11 12:34:09 2015 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and Conditions of the license agreement available at http://heinonline.org/hol/license -- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. -- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your HeinOnline license, please use: https://www.copyright.com/ccc/basicsearch.do? &operation=go&searchtype=0 &lastsearch=simple&all=on&titleorstdno=0021-2237

No. 1, 1986] BOOKS THE UNITY OF LAW AND MORALITY: A REFUTATION OF LEGAL POSITIVISM. By M. J. Detmold [Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1984, 264 pp.]. One of my conclusions about this book is that it defies reviewing. It is an ambitious, condensed and extremely hierarchical study. It is not the kind of book one will consult on a particular question, since it is impossible to grasp the meaning of positions on particular questions without understanding the background, the terminology and the writer's presuppositions. The breadth of these background conditions is such that no one can do justice to the book without digesting it in its entirety. As a book, it is a "take it whole or leave it" proposition. In these days of an explosion of writing, this is a risky way to write. I think Detmold has succeeded in building an integrated and challenging analysis of law (together with an analysis of morals, rules, authority and the functions of these in life). Parts of the picture are very attractive to me. Others seem to me wrong and misleading. But in the seamless web of Detmold's analysis it is difficult to find a suitable and manageable point of departure. I shall thus try to give the general contours of Detmold's thought, and deal in particular with his alleged refutation of positivism. I repeat that such a sketch cannot do justice to the work. In addition, it fails to capture the special structure and style of Detmold's argument. Two unique features are worth mentioning. First, the book is structured in chapters and sections. It opens with a synopsis, containing a one-sentence abstract of each section. Not surprisingly, the synopsis cannot always even suggest the main argument, but this structure (popular in the last century) has obvious advantages. Secondly, the breadth of Detmold's field is amazing. All philosophers of law write about rules, judges, legislatures. Many of them write about morals and practical reasoning as well. Detmold is the first contemporary theorist I have read who feels that the analysis of law cannot be complete without talking of life, death, beauty, tragedy, love and the mystery of existence. Reference to these themes is inserted in most crucial points of the analysis. 1. General Background Legal decisions are, for Detmold, a sub-class of practical decisions. Moral positions are, ultimately, passionate responses of individuals to the conflicting reasons for action present in each case. Only facts can be reasons for action, so that there is nothing inherently normative about moral norms. Ideally, the 'correct' way of making any practical decision is by making it as a single-case decision, balancing all the first-order unconditional reasons for

ISRAEL LAW REVIEW [Is.L.R. Vol. 21 and against the alternative choices. Detmold thinks that there are no inherent difficulties in this procedure, since the world in which we act is one, and there is commensurability of all reasons of action. The moral priority of this procedure rests on the fact that it gives full weight to the particularity of events and people. This particularity, according to Detmold, is what makes life unique and important. Nonetheless, Detmold concedes that in most practical cases we must decide by rules - i.e., decide the case by applying a norm, covering a class of cases, which we assume to be binding. Moreover, Detmold accepts and even justifies the fact that people usually are motivated not only by unconditional reasons for action, but by reasons which are contingent on their own projects or commitments. He further accepts that there may be good strategic reasons for adopting rules, for appropriating the infinite mystery of the world into a manageable structure. Yet Detmold refuses, in morals as well as in law, to let any agent give up his freedom (or duty) to look at the particular reasons of action in 'hard cases', defined as non-rule cases. Even if there is a persuasive set of reasons for adopting an absolute rule requiring, e.g., promise-keeping, an agent may still argue that he should not apply this rule in a given particular case. At times, Detmold insists, this is the only position which is morally permissible. In more conventional moral terminology, Detmold seems to hold that rule-utilitarianism may justify binding rules for most cases, but that there is a residue of cases in which it must be still open to make act-utilitarian judgments. Detmold does not say much to help us identify hard cases, but it seems that such cases are those in which the application of the rule will yield seriously unacceptable consequences, which cannot be justified by a first-order balancing of moral reasons. These tools and theses enable Detmold to present his analysis of law, of discretion, of the obligation of judges and of the principle of binding precedent. Law is a game-like normative context in which judges mainly apply norms to rule-type cases. The centrality of norms to the law is acknowledged by Detmold. Nonetheless, the judges are moral agents, and they must be able to justify th eir decisions by moral, not legal, criteria. In hard cases, the mere invocation of a legal norm is not enough to justify the decision. In this sense, every legal decision must be justifiable by moral standards, hence the refutation of positivism. 2. The Defence of Positivism Many of Detmold's theses about morality and the nature of practical reasoning are controversial. I do not have to deal with those, however, since I

No. 1, 1986] BOOKS think his attack on legal positivism fails even if you accept all his other theses. In fact, Detmold's background description gives credence to a sophisticated form of legal positivism. it is no accident that Detmold never defines positivism. What he challenges is the idea that it is conceivable that the decision required by law may be immoral. The example Detmold relies on is that of the judge who sentences a defendant to death, arguing that this is what the law requires, but admitting that the decision may not be morally justified. Detmold analyses a few possible attempts to resolve the contradiction between these two normative statements and concludes that they all fail. Hence, he argues, a judge can only justify his decision by invoking a moral norm. No legal decision may be justified unless it is morally justifiable. It follows, Detmold argues, that legal positivism is refuted. I am willing to agree with Detmold that judges are agents, and that they are morally responsible for their decisions. I agree with him further that a judge who sentences a criminal to death without being convinced that this particular result is morally justified is acting wrongly. But these concessions do not affect positivism as a theory about the law. They affect one's analysis of the duties imposed on agents acting within the law. I agree with Detmold that the law is a partial normative order, which can be evaluated in moral terms. But Detmold himself recognizes that we need partial normative orders of various sorts, and that for most practical purposes we are entitled to treat them as determining the issue. The essence of all partial normative orders claiming autonomy is precisely the fact that they enable us to make practical judgments without opening, in each case, the long and uncertain process of balancing of first-order moral reasons for action. Moreover, single-case decisions may have many moral virtues, but they have formidable moral risks, in addition to the fact that such practical reasoning is highly impractical. Detmold even recognizes that it is important to have law and to be willing to make most decisions within it. He concedes that there are systemic reasons for following rules in some cases in which first-order balancing might suggest thatnot following the rule might be better in the instant case. This is all that is and seeks to justify it by invoking the legal norms is failing in his moral duty. If I believe that there are acceptable legal ways to arrive at the 'correct' decision, I may argue that he has failed in his duty to the law as well. But the very ability to make these judgments presupposes, for me, a positivistic theory of law. In this continuing debate it has been said that in addition to the fact that positivism (a theory about the nature of law, not a theory about what people should do) cannot dictate anyone's actions, positivism may have the

ISRAEL LAW REVIEW [Is.L.R. Vol. 21 needed to accept positivism not merely as a description of law but also as a possible basis for justifying it as a social practice. Detmold's refutation of positivism is not based on claims that it is an inadequate description of the phenomenon of law. The refutation is based on the logical impossibility of arguing that the legal system dictates a solution, which the judge will in fact reach, which cannot be justified in moral terms. Empirically, Detmold must concede that such claim is not only possible, but that many judges have in fact made it. In the dramatic cases of life sentences and clearly unjust laws, most legal theorists will condemn the judges who have acted in this way. In less dramatic cases, many judges explicitly prefer systemic reasons for following rules to justice in the instant case. The practice of the law thus belies Detmold's descriptive claims. Moreover, this practice is not merely the way things are. It reflects deep and basic needs and desiderata of any public normative system seeking to guide behaviour for large and heterogenous populations. This would suffice to support the conclusion that Detmold's reasoning does not refute legal positivism. But clearly Detmold is motivated not mainly by theoretical concerns. He wants to argue that positivism distorts the picture of the moral responsibility of judges to their particular decisions. Positivism does that by suggesting that there are two kinds of justifications - legal and moral, and that the obligations of the judge is exhausted, according to positivists, by justifying his decision under legal norms. But positivism is committed to no such position, as is amply demonstrated by the many positivists who hold that there is no general obligation to obey the law. Positivists do claim (and I think Detmold does too) that there are indeed two distinct kinds of justification, legal and moral. The difference between them stems from the fact that the legal system is a partial normative order, claiming autonomy for most practical purposes. The judge, as an officer of the system, usually accepts this claim as binding. This habit is clearly one of the identifying features of any stable legal system. It explains the willingness of judges to prefer, in most cases, the dictates of the norms to their own attempt at balancing the merits of the case. This willingness may be justified when the moral implications of the decision required by the law are not clearly unacceptable. Good judges have many ways of interpreting the law to avoid blatantly immoral consequences. When a judge feels he cannot find a respectable way of doing so, he must make a moral decision whether to enforce the law, distort the law, or resign. Whatever he decides to do, positivism as a theory about the law tells the judge nothing. He will have to turn to his moral theory and consult it on the question whether the situation justifies or requires an action within the law or an action against it. I agree with Detmold that a judge who arrives at a clearly immoral decision

No. 1, 1986] BOOKS additional virtue of sensitizing judges to the fact that there is no built-in guarantee that legal norms will yield morally justifiable decisions. A denial of this fact, or a thesis that there is a unity between the two, may encourage judges to believe that whatever the law requires is in fact moral. If we are concerned, as Detmold clearly is, with minimizing the risk that judges will sacrifice innocent victims to immoral norms, our main job should be to see to it that judges will have moral integrity and will accept their moral responsibility to their decisions. The contribution of legal theories to this quest is direct and questionable. No one, Detmold included, has succeeded in refuting positivism on this ground. In a world of never-ending attempts to reach the 'truth' of the matter I dare to predict that no one ever will. Detmold has not even tried to show that accepting a positivistic theory of law (or rejecting any of his theses of morals) is conducive to a tendency in judges to see their responsibility as exhausted by legal standards. If he had tried, I think his case would not be strong. It might even be said that a book so heavily loaded with questionable meta-ethical propositions is less likely to make a contribution to this important practical goal than a more straightforward analysis, less dependent on Detmold's background. In this sense, the fact that Detmold's practical conclusions may be reached via more conventional routes, including contemporary versions of positivism, is a strong argument against his approach. But the fight between positivism and anti-positivism in law is one of those it is essential to understand, although it is unlikely to be won. It is a question we must deal with anew all the time. Detmold offers a stimulating and original opportunity for a reconsideration of the question. Some of his arguments are sharp and profound. He is not afraid to be radical, with interesting results. I would not recommend it as a beginner's book. It is challenging reading for those already initiated. Ruth Gavison* * Haim Cohn Professor of Human Rights, Faculty of Law, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem.