(Review) Critical legal positivism by Kaarlo Tuori

Similar documents
Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

McCOUBREY & WHITE S TEXTBOOK ON JURISPRUDENCE

Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that

10. The aim of a theory of law is to reduce chaos and multiplicity to unity. legal theory is science and not volition. It is knowledge of what the

1. The basic idea is to look at "what the courts do in fact" (Holmes, 1897). What does this mean?

Bowring, B. Review: Malcolm D. Evans Manual on the Wearing of Religious Symbols in Public Areas."

FACULTY OF LAW UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA LAW 300 JURISPRUDENCE AND CRITICAL PERSPECTIVES. Fall 2015

Why Legal Positivism?

The multifaceted leadership of R. J. Chambers: a personal reflection

Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law

Communicative Rationality and Deliberative Democracy of Jlirgen Habermas: Toward Consolidation of Democracy in Africa

PROFESSOR HARTS CONCEPT OF LAW SUBAS H. MAHTO LEGAL THEORY F.Y.LLM

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

UNDERSTANDING FUNDAMENTAL SECONDARY RULES

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid?

When is philosophy intercultural? Outlooks and perspectives. Ram Adhar Mall

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

Chapter 1 Introduction

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

Briefing Paper. Modern Jurisprudence Dworkin s Deadly Attack on Legal Positivism. November 2012

Seminar assignments Contemporary Jurisprudence

Habermas and Critical Thinking

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

Legal Positivism: Still Descriptive and Morally Neutral

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

Comparative Legal History & 4-5 June The pros and cons of legal positivism (H L A Hart s version)

Book Review: Hugh Jackson: Australians and the Christian God: An Historical Study

JUDICIAL OPINION WRITING

Hans Kelsen. 1. Kelsen s life ( )

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

EXECUTION AND INVENTION: DEATH PENALTY DISCOURSE IN EARLY RABBINIC. Press Pp $ ISBN:

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Kelsen s Legal Monism and the Future of the European Constitution

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Executive Power and the School Chaplains Case, Williams v Commonwealth Karena Viglianti

ASKING THE LAW QUESTION

Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review

Review: The sacredness of the person: a new genealogy of human rights

LEGAL PHILOSOPHY AND EVALUATIVE CONSIDERATIONS

THE GERMAN CONFERENCE ON ISLAM

Face-to-face and Side-by-Side A framework for inter faith dialogue and social action. A response from the Methodist Church

Promoting British Values at St Joseph s Catholic Primary School

DEFERENCE AND DIFFÉRANCE: JUDICIAL REVIEW AND THE PERFECT GIFT* J de Ville **

Apostasy and Conversion Kishan Manocha

The Nature of the Judicial Process and Judicial Discretion

In Search of a Political Ethics of Intersubjectivity: Between Hannah Arendt, Emmanuel Levinas and the Judaic

National Seminar on THE ROLE OF RELIGION IN PROMOTING PEACE AND HARMONY: CONTRIBUTION OF CHRISTIANITY February 2015

LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

Attfield, Robin, and Barry Wilkins, "Sustainability." Environmental Values 3, no. 2, (1994):

LEGAL TRADITIONS (WESTERN IDEAS OF LAW (LAW 303)) Course Outline - Spring 2017 Professor Dennis Pavlich. Course Description.

Emotions in law: psychological theory of law by Petrażycki (and Olivecrona)

SPIRITUALITY IN EDUCATION: ETHICS AT WORK

Eichrodt, Walther. Theology of the Old Testament: Volume 1. The Old Testament Library.

Jeffrey Stout s Secular and the Liberal Arts Jonathon S. Kahn Vassar College March 2008

PHL271 Handout 2: Hobbes on Law and Political Authority. Many philosophers of law treat Hobbes as the grandfather of legal positivism.

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8

Undergraduate Calendar Content

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism

KELSEN'S THEORY OF GRUNDNORM

Philosophy. Aim of the subject

RELIGION OR BELIEF. Submission by the British Humanist Association to the Discrimination Law Review Team

Philosophy Courses Fall 2016

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

Guidelines on Global Awareness and Engagement from ATS Board of Directors

On the Origins and Normative Status of the Impartial Spectator

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

Ely, DeLillo, and the Distrusted Moments of Our Democracy

PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION A-Z

FARMS Review 19/1 (2007): (print), (online)

Theo-Web. Academic Journal of Religious Education Vol. 11, Issue Editorial and Summary in English by Manfred L. Pirner

POLITICAL SECULARISM AND PUBLIC REASON. THREE REMARKS ON AUDI S DEMOCRATIC AUTHORITY AND THE SEPARATION OF CHURCH AND STATE

Book Review: Jurisprudence: Readings and Cases, by Mark M. MacGuigan

A BRAVE NEW NETWORKED WORLD: VIRTUE ETHICS AND THE TWENTY- FIRST CENTURY MANAGER

Commitment and Qualification What Teachers Do We Need at Christian Schools?

The British Humanist Association's Submission to the Joint Committee of both Houses on the reform of the House of Lords

Kears, M. (2011) Review: Susan Lape, Race and Citizen Identity in the Classical Athenian Democracy. Cambridge University Press, 2010.

Tool 1: Becoming inspired

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

Moral Positivism and the Internal Legality of Morals

Systems Thinking as if People Mattered

Mika Ojakangas. A Philosophy of Concrete Life. Carl Schmitt and the Political Thought of Late Modernity.

Cover Page. The handle holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

Summary of Chapters. Chapter 1: Introduction and Overview

Discourse about bioethics is plagued by the appearance of simplicity. The

Philosophy at Reading

Citation British Journal of Sociology, 2009, v. 60 n. 2, p

FOR ANGLICAN SCHOOLS IN THE PROVINCE OF QUEENSLAND


The Trolley Problem. 11 Judith Jarvith Thomson Killing, Letting Die and the Trolley Problem (1976) 59 Oxford University Press 204-

all three components especially around issues of difference. In the Introduction, At the Intersection Where Worlds Collide, I offer a personal story

Theology and Society in Three Cities: Berlin, Oxford and Chicago, (Cambridge: James Clarke & Co., 2014), by Mark D.

A theory of adjudication is a theory primarily about what judges do when they decide cases in courts of law.

Becoming Buddhist: Experiences of Socialization and Self-Transformation in Two Australian Buddhist Centres

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE

THE JOY OF LOVE. THE CHURCH AS THE GUARDIAN OF HUMAN LOVE Maryvale, 21 May 2016

A conference on "Spirituality, Theology, Education"

Perspectives. Theme: Provide students with off-game opportunities to reflect on important themes that may influence their in-game decision making

Transcription:

University of Wollongong Research Online Faculty of Law - Papers (Archive) Faculty of Law, Humanities and the Arts 2003 (Review) Critical legal positivism by Kaarlo Tuori Richard Mohr University of Wollongong, rmohr@uow.edu.au Publication Details This book review was originally published as Mohr, R, (Review) Critical Legal Positivism by Kaarlo Tuori, Adelaide Law Review, 24(1), 2003, 141-144. Research Online is the open access institutional repository for the University of Wollongong. For further information contact the UOW Library: research-pubs@uow.edu.au

(Review) Critical legal positivism by Kaarlo Tuori Abstract Kaarlo Tuori, professor of law, judge, and counsellor to the Constitutional Committee of the Finnish Parliament, has embarked on an ambitious project. He aims to build on the positivism of Kelsen and Hart, but to discover a normative justification of law which goes beyond their limited validity claims. This is the critical element which he adds to legal positivism. Kelsen s basic norm and Hart s rule of recognition are irreducible underlying principles. The arbitrary nature of such principles is intellectually suspect, while their internal self referentiality renders them morally sterile. The law is the law because we recognise it as such or because it is founded on the basic norm and as such it is valid. This leads to a lack of critical purchase, which is the fundamental drawback of positivism when confronted by natural law or other ethically based theories. Classical mid-twentieth century positivism offers no ethical foundation outside the declared law from which we may criticise unjust laws. Disciplines Law Publication Details This book review was originally published as Mohr, R, (Review) Critical Legal Positivism by Kaarlo Tuori, Adelaide Law Review, 24(1), 2003, 141-144. This journal article is available at Research Online: http://ro.uow.edu.au/lawpapers/54

Richard Mohr * CRITICAL LEGAL POSITIVISM By Kaarlo Tuori Aldershot, Ashgate, 2002 364 pp ISBN 075462272X K aarlo Tuori, professor of law, judge, and counsellor to the Constitutional Committee of the Finnish Parliament, has embarked on an ambitious project. He aims to build on the positivism of Kelsen and Hart, but to discover a normative justification of law which goes beyond their limited validity claims. This is the critical element which he adds to legal positivism. Kelsen s basic norm and Hart s rule of recognition are irreducible underlying principles. The arbitrary nature of such principles is intellectually suspect, while their internal self referentiality renders them morally sterile. The law is the law because we recognise it as such or because it is founded on the basic norm and as such it is valid. This leads to a lack of critical purchase, which is the fundamental drawback of positivism when confronted by natural law or other ethically based theories. Classical mid-twentieth century positivism offers no ethical foundation outside the declared law from which we may criticise unjust laws. Theoretical developments since the time of Hart give Tuori the opportunity to propose a version of positivism which is open to ethical arguments and moral principles. Despite his emphasis on Dworkin and particularly on Foucault and his follower Ewald, it is MacCormick s development of positivism and the discourse ethics of Habermas which really give Tuori the boost he needs to open the law to broader validity claims. His theory develops a model of legal systems based on three levels of law and two versions of a legal community. What we normally think of as legal activity is at the surface of Tuori s three levels: it is the legislating, litigating and adjudicating which is carried out by the narrow legal community of legislators, lawyers and judges. Most of Hart s or Kelsen s subject matter exists at this uppermost level of visible law. What interests Tuori is all the paddling that goes on under the surface. A middle, mediating level in the law 1 consists of principles which guide interpretation of the law and which may, at times, invalidate or limit some of the * 1 BA, PhD (UNSW); Coordinator of Postgraduate Programs and Co-Director of the Legal Intersections Research Centre, Faculty of Law, University of Wollongong. K Tuori, Critical Legal Positivism (2002) 192.

142 MOHR CRITICAL LEGAL POSITIVISM legal activity at the surface. These principles may be those of Roman law such as pacta sunt servanda or principles of common law such as due process or duty of care. They are more enduring than the specific statute or individual case. The most stable level of all is the deep structure of law where we find, according to Tuori, both the most basic principles (eg human rights) and the habits of mind or forms of rationality by which we think and argue about the law. Yet change is possible even at this level: Foucault illustrates one such change from sovereignty to discipline, for instance. In a society subject to modern law, the dominant form of rationality at this deepest level is communicative rationality, as described by Habermas. To ensure mutual understanding, our arguments and discourse must be guided by truthfulness, normative rightness and authenticity (that we represent ourselves truthfully). This is the foundation of discourse ethics, which builds an ethos for civil society out of the strictures of the ideal speech situation. It is central to Tuori s argument, since law must be founded in a deep ethical community which is able to debate the validity of surface laws. This ethical community is Tuori s broad legal community. Instead of insulating law from ethical or moral debates in the style of classical legal positivism, Tuori s critical legal positivism opens itself to these debates. Yet this is an odd sort of openness which can only enter the law mediated by law s basic principles and its narrow legal community. This ethical democracy must operate, for Tuori s purposes, through the law itself as a means of limiting the extra-legal excesses of legislators and other members of the top level narrow legal community. Nowhere is Tuori explicit as to the mechanisms which allow this exchange between civil society and positive law. He emphasises the centrality of the legislature in the Continental legal system, compared to the power of the common law judiciary. We might think, then, that Tuori may allow an elected legislature to be open to the political debates of the electorate. Yet this sort of openness (unless it heeded demands for improved legal and communicative processes) would let politics into law and undermine its positive legal character which positivism requires in order to distance law from the state. On the other hand, Tuori s privileging of the legal might suggest that the courts could be open to civil society. Again, there is no indication of how this may occur, beyond exhorting the judges to explain their decisions in terms understandable to the citizens, who may then comment on them. 2 This looks like one way traffic unless the judges themselves are able to translate public debates into their judgments, which seems to go beyond positivism, even Tuori s. He does not canvass any other mechanisms to reverse the traffic flow back into the law from civil society, though it is tantalising to consider the ways in 2 Ibid 279.

(2003) 24 Adelaide Law Review 143 which civil society may enter the courts through juries or some European forms of lay judges. 3 The rigorous legal theory developed in this recent addition to Tom Campbell s Applied Legal Philosophy series is satisfying in a way that eludes Habermas s complex excursions into law. This may be despite and because of Professor Tuori s exuberant inclusiveness. He approaches his task in the first instance through a theoretical analysis of the most important strands of twentieth century legal sociology (Weber, Foucault, Ewald, Habermas) and synthesises these strands to show how each helps point the way toward a critical legal positivism. This is a particularly useful aspect of the book. Tuori s exposition of each of the major theorists to whom he devotes a chapter each, is clear and reliable. His leaps of synthesis to connect them to each other, or to other major theorists (eg Dworkin), are intriguing, even if they sometimes appear rather contrived. In addition to the greats of legal theory that I have already mentioned, Tuori introduces interesting though less well-known work of other European legal scholars, particularly from Scandinavia and Finland. The European locus of this book provides a convincing bridge across a channel that sometimes seems as wide as the Atlantic in separating civil and common law jurisprudence. Professor Tuori s totalising tendencies should get a rise out of a few common law eyebrows, particularly those used to beetling over post-modern suspicions of grand theory. However, he is equally convincing on common law as he is on civil law turf since his familiarity with the Anglo-American literature and legal systems matches his Continental scholarship. Although this book contains one or two interesting excurses on European law as a diverse and supranational phenomenon, it is at the level of international legal principles and pluralist practices that Tuori is least convincing. There is something strangely old-fashioned in the way he restricts his examples and the operation of his theory to the constitutions and legislatures of nation states. He sees human rights as typifying the deepest and most enduring layer of law, effecting its self-limitation by force of intellectual habit and common conviction. This suggests that considerations of human rights arise from civil society, the broad sub-stratum on which Tuori bases the democratic justification of law. And yet, particularly in Europe, such international principles, are applied by international courts which are very much a part of the surface activity of the narrow legal community. 3 The implications for further research are apparent. Postgraduate research suggesting some of these directions is already being carried out by Gerrit Franssen at the University of Antwerp and by Sian Leathem at the University of Wollongong. They have presented this work at, respectively, the conference of the Research Committee on the Sociology of Law (Oxford, 18 20 July 2003) and at a Legal Intersections Research Centre seminar (Wollongong, 8 September 2003).

144 MOHR CRITICAL LEGAL POSITIVISM To the extent that such examples refer to principles as an ethical foundation of positive law, they support Tuori s general theme. But while they reassert legal principles, they do not operate from the deep layers which bind law into the ethical life of a community. If the dynamism of European human rights law comes from the narrow (albeit international) legal community, it is hard to justify law s ethical foundation in democracy. Bureaucratic internationalism is at another pole from democratic ethical communities. If law is more at home in bureaucracy than in democracy, then Weber trumps Habermas and an ethics of law based in a communicative civil society gives way to a world dominated by judicial decisionmaking according to administrative principles. Habermas himself has expressed reservations about this process of juridification. Tuori s zeal for the ethical possibilities of law, including legal science (jurisprudence) as one of its deepest structures, constructs an alluring world of certainties. However, the satisfying completeness of this world is unsettled by the vagaries of democracy and civil society. In common with earlier exponents of positivism, Tuori has difficulty opening law to these ethical influences while maintaining its unshakable foundations.