TRADITIONAL VALUES AND HUMAN RIGHTS:

Similar documents
Question : Reform's Position On...Homosexuality

RESOLUTIONS BEFORE THE ANNUAL CONFERENCE

Homosexuality and The United Methodist Church. A Brief History Lesson

Bishop s Report To The Judicial Council Of The United Methodist Church

EXAMINING THE REFORMED CHURCH IN AMERICA'S STAND ON HOMOSEXUALITY

Seth Mayer. Comments on Christopher McCammon s Is Liberal Legitimacy Utopian?

COACHING EMPLOYMENT APPLICATION

DISCUSSION GUIDE DISCUSSION GUIDE PREPARED BY RYAN KIMMEL

Political Science 103 Fall, 2018 Dr. Edward S. Cohen INTRODUCTION TO POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

Motion from the Right Relationship Monitoring Committee for the UUA Board of Trustees meeting January 2012

JUDITH BUTLER AND THE VIRTUE OF TROUBLEMAKING. feminist ethics. The predominate understanding of troublemaking is that it is bad,

v o i c e A Document for Dialogue and Study Report of the Task Force on Human Sexuality The Alliance of Baptists

Same-Sex Marriage, Just War, and the Social Principles

Can you be a Mormon and a Democrat?

Templates for Writing about Ideas and Research

Saftey In Our Conflict-Government Church

Aquinas & Homosexuality. Five Dominicans Respond to Adriano Oliva

Testimony on ENDA and the Religious Exemption. Rabbi David Saperstein. Director, Religious Action Center of Reform Judaism

Articles of Incorporation SOLITUDE BAPTIST CHURCH (ORIGINAL)

Islam-Democracy Reconciliation in the Thought/Writings of Asghar Ali Engineer

Preserving the Family in a Disintegrating Society (1) Written by Jack Westerink

Kedoshim - Torah, Holiness, Sexual Ethics...and the Library Minyan. By Rabbi Gail Labovitz

BEHIND CARING: THE CONTRIBUTION OF FEMINIST PEDAGOGY IN PREPARING WOMEN FOR CHRISTIAN MINISTRY IN SOUTH AFRICA

If Everyone Does It, Then You Can Too Charlie Melman

The Case for. Change

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

The First Church in Oberlin, United Church of Christ. Policies and Procedures for a Safe Church

The sermon this morning is the beginning of a sermon series entitled, The Way Forward: What God Says to the Church on Human Sexuality.

Page 1 of 16 Spirituality in a changing world: Half say faith is important to how they consider society s problems

Do we still have universal values?

Tolerance in Discourses and Practices in French Public Schools

READING REVIEW I: Gender in the Trinity David T. Williams (Jared Shaw)

'Ears to hear'? Mark C. Chavez, vice president. September 15, 2009

Debating Bible Verses on Homosexuality JUNE 8, 2015

Religion in the Public Square Rev. Bruce Taylor October 27, 2013

DEBATING the DIVINE #43. Religion in 21st century American Democracy. Edited by Sally Steenland

The Holy See APOSTOLIC JOURNEY TO THE UNITED KINGDOM (SEPTEMBER 16-19, 2010)

AMERICAN CENTER FOR LAW AND JUSTICE S MEMORANDUM OF LAW REGARDING THE CRIMINAL TRIAL OF ABDUL RAHMAN FOR CONVERTING FROM ISLAM TO CHRISTIANITY

Constitution First Baptist Church Camden, Arkansas. Preamble. Article I. Name. Article II. Purpose Statement (amended May 10, 2006)

Concerns with the PCUSA

Diocese of San Jose Guidelines for The Catholic LGBT Ministry Council Patrick J. McGrath Bishop of San Jose

Student Engagement and Controversial Issues in Schools

The Vocation Movement in Lutheran Higher Education

REASONS AND ENTAILMENT

World On Trial: Headscarf Law Episode

instrumentalize this idea for the suppression of women or to compel them to wear a veil in order to frighten them, so they will not use makeup or

In defence of the four freedoms : freedom of religion, conscience, association and speech

The Bible s Yes to Same-Sex Marriage

90 South Cascade Avenue, Suite 1500, Colorado Springs, Colorado Telephone: Fax:

Teacher-Minister Contract

September 19, Dear Members of the Candler Community,

Discuss whether it is possible to be a Christian and in a same sex relationship.

Meta-Debate: A necessity for any debate style.

LAW04. Law and Morals. The Concepts of Law

Interfaith Marriage: A Moral Problem for Jews, Christians and Muslims. Muslim Response by Professor Jerusha Tanner Lamptey, Ph.D.

THE CONSTITUTION LAKEWOOD CONGREGATIONAL CHURCH

Presentation by Task Force on Christian Marriage Presbyterian Church of the Cross April, 2016

UNITED STATES CONFERENCE OF CATHOLIC BISHOPS DOCUMENTATION COMMITTEE ON PRIORITIES AND PLANS

Bylaws Of The Sanctuary A Georgia Non-Profit Religious Corporation

Right and Wrong: A review of recent surveys on values and religion

Mount Olive Evangelical Lutheran Church th Ave NW Rochester, MN (507)

ELEMENTARY SCHOOL TEACHER EMPLOYMENT APPLICATION

Democratic Enlightenment

THE CHALLENGE OF RACISM TODAY

A CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS OF SECULARISM AND ITS LEGITIMACY IN THE CONSTITUTIONAL DEMOCRATIC STATE

Uganda, morality was derived from God and the adult members were regarded as teachers of religion. God remained the canon against which the moral

VIEWING PERSPECTIVES

Ralph K. Hawkins Averett University Danville, Virginia

What We Believe DOCTRINAL BELIEFS

Compromise and Toleration: Some Reflections I. Introduction

TITLE: Full Respect for Your Employer, Supervisors, And Other Authority Persons Over You

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

Exploring Deep Ecology as a Religion. Christine Jauernig BIOL 510

Tool 1: Becoming inspired

Mitt Romney, BYU, and Abortion Rights

COMMENTS ON THE PROPOSED 2016 GENERAL SYNOD CONSTITUTIONAL CHANGES Written By Howard Moths October 1, 2016

BY-LAWS. of the Islamic Community. of North American Bosniaks

Bowring, B. Review: Malcolm D. Evans Manual on the Wearing of Religious Symbols in Public Areas."

UNIVERSAL PERIODIC REVIEW JOINT SUBMISSION 2018

The Chicago Statement on Biblical Inerrancy

How can I learn to love myself when I have been told by mom, dad, grandparents and teachers that I am worthless?

Human Rights: Both Universal and Relative (A Reply to Michael Goodhart)

INTERVARSITY CHRISTIAN FELLOWSHIP ORGANIZATION CONSTITUTION

THE CHICAGO STATEMENT ON BIBLICAL INERRANCY A Summarization written by Dr. Murray Baker

Dutchess County Loving Education At Home By-Laws September 11, 2012

Frequently Asked Questions

2015 IFCA International Statement on Biblical vs. Same-Sex Marriage

John Locke s Politics of Moral Consensus

From the ELCA s Draft Social Statement on Women and Justice

Buddhism and homosexuality

Freedom to Marry 101: What s it all about?

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

PRESENTMENT II. IN THE COURT FOR THE TRIAL OF A BISHOP. JAMES C. STANTON, BISHOP OF DALLAS, et. al., PRESENTERS WALTER C. RIGHTER, RESPONDENT,

JEREMY BENTHAM, PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION (1780)

Authority in the Anglican Communion

Widespread Middle East Fears that Syrian Violence Will Spread

Same-sex Marriage and the role of Religion By William Duncan 2010 FAIR Conference

Apostasy and Conversion Kishan Manocha

Harman s Moral Relativism

Transcription:

CICERO FOUNDATION GREAT DEBATE PAPER No. 13 / 06 December 2013 TRADITIONAL VALUES AND HUMAN RIGHTS: WHOSE TRADITIONS? WHICH RIGHTS? MICHAEL BLAKE Professor of Philosophy and Public Policy University of Washington Seattle, Washington, USA

Cicero Foundation Great Debate Paper No. 13/06 Michael Blake, 2013 All rights reserved The Cicero Foundation is an independent pro-atlantic and pro-eu think tank. www.cicerofoundation.org The views expressed in Cicero Foundation Great Debate Papers do not necessarily express the opinion of the Cicero Foundation, but they are considered interesting and thought-provoking enough to be published. Permission to make digital or hard copies of any information contained in these web publications is granted for personal use, without fee and without formal request. Full citation and copyright notice must appear on the first page. Copies may not be made or distributed for profit or commercial advantage. The Cicero Foundation FRANCE THE NETHERLANDS 13, rue Washington Hondertmarck D 45 75008 PARIS 6211 MB MAASTRICHT Tel. +33 145620590 Tel. +31 433260602 Fax +33 145620530 Fax +31 433260828 Email info@cicerofoundation.org cicerofoundation@gmail.com 2

Traditional Values and Human Rights: Whose Traditions? Which Rights? Michael Blake *) Introduction In November of 2013, the Russian Federation was elected to the United Nation s Human Rights Council (HRC). Vitaly Churkin, the Russian representative to the UN, identified traditional values as a topic of special concern for the Russian delegation during their three-year term on the HRC. i This emphasis comes on the heels of Russia s tabling, in 2012, of a resolution asserting that traditional values, especially those shared by all humanity, can be practically applied in the promotion and protection of human rights. ii This resolution came on the heels of two previous resolutions endorsing traditional values as a legitimate part of human rights practice, both initiated by the Russian Federation. This third resolution passed, by a vote of 25 to 15, with seven member states abstaining. The resolution endorsing traditional values was immediately condemned by human rights practitioners. Article 19, a human rights NGO devoted to freedom of expression, described traditional values talk as synonymous with majoritarian, conservative, and mono-cultural conceptions of what some people think human rights should be. iii ARC International noted that traditional values would tend to legitimize the abuse and marginalization of those who are socially unpopular. iv The European Union, similarly, noted that traditional values surrounding gender and sexual 3

orientation have led to the marginalization and worse of individuals throughout history. v The HRC was made aware of concerns such as these in its own study of the topic, which it commissioned in response to the earlier Russian proposals: the study noted that traditional values were both ill-defined and likely to undermine support for human rights. vi Despite this report, and the chorus of disapproval, the HRC seems likely to be receptive to future proposals emphasizing the moral importance of traditional values. Protecting or Limiting Human Rights? The political danger of the proposal seems obvious: while traditional values are described as a vehicle through which human rights might be protected, they are more often presented as a means by which these rights might be interpreted and, thereby, limited. Graeme Reid, director of the LGBT Program at Human Rights Watch, notes in this context that gay men and lesbians are all too familiar with the use of tradition as a tool for marginalization and oppression. vii In the present context, though, I am not most concerned with what can be said about the political dangers of this proposal; I am more concerned with what arguments might be said in favor of this proposal. I do not want, I should emphasize, to endorse the proposal; I want, instead, to understand what sorts of arguments might be said in favor of such a proposal, so as to understand the limits of those arguments. We can begin, then, by asking a simple question: whose traditions, exactly, are at issue in the discussion of traditional values? There seem to be two ways in which one might answer this question. We might emphasize, as the 2012 resolution seems to do, that the traditions with which we are concerned are the traditions held by all societies. Alternatively, we might emphasize that the traditions in question are distinctively local traditions, held by only particular societies at particular times. We can consider each of these answers in turn. 4

So: let us say, with the resolution, that traditional values are those values that are held in all societies at all times, and that these values are rightful tools with which to understand human rights. One immediate problem presents itself: which values, exactly, are those that are held in all societies at all times? Those who are in favor of traditional values as a concept will undoubtedly want to emphasize the most noble of values patriotism, perhaps, or familial love but it is important to note that there are other, less welcome, values that are equally prevalent. Susan Okin notes, in this context, that the denigration of women and women s work is as close to a cross-cultural universal as anything social science has yet to find. viii All cultures, at all times, have had some traditions best described as marginalizing to the experience and lives of women. Our response to this, of course, is not and should not be to validate the marginalization of women as morally sacred. The response is, instead, to say that women s lives have traditionally been blighted, and that this should change. We are willing, I think, to say this about women; however badly our laws and our societies live up to what human rights would require for gender equality, we are willing to say that tradition should bow to the force of human rights and dignity. The problem, however, is that this result is more general; it tells us that sometimes there can be a traditional value held in all places and at all times that should be abandoned in face of the moral equality of persons. Once we have admitted that sometimes tradition should bow to dignity, it seems that tradition must submit itself generally to the tests of moral reasoning. A traditional norm must earn its status as rightful; it cannot assume it. Why Should Traditional Values Have a Special Moral Status? Why, though, should we even believe that there is anything morally special about traditional values in the first place? The argument here is hazy the Russian federation has been unwilling to make its terms or its arguments specific but we might think it resembles a more general conservative argument, one made popular in the previous century by the writings of Patrick Devlin. ix Society, on this argument, persists 5

and perpetuates itself only when individuals are bound together by a shared set of social norms. These norms, we might argue, bind individuals to one another so that shared sacrifice for a common ideal is made possible. A society that refuses to promote and protect these norms, in sum, is setting the stages for its own disintegration a result that would spell disaster for the human rights, which are impossible outside the legal and political structures of society. The argument, however, assumes too much, especially about what actually must be the case for a society to flourish. Take, in connection with this, the Russian concern with homosexual conduct: the Russian Federation has criminalized propaganda in favor of non-traditional sexual relationships. x Devlin agreed: laws against homosexuality preserved the willingness of persons to sacrifice themselves for their society, by enforcing and preserving the traditions that individuals found morally sacred. If homosexual conduct were permitted, Devlin argued, the bonds of society might indeed disintegrate. The problem with the argument, of course, is that a more open attitude to homosexual conduct in the West has not led to widespread anarchy or social disintegration; it has, instead, led simply to a slightly changed social world, in which same-sex relationships are no longer quite so anathema. Devlin s argument like that of the Russians seems to mistake a different social world for a destroyed social world as if gay sex, if not legally prohibited, would prove so attractive that society itself would collapse! Society can, once again, survive the alteration of a tradition, and the claim that social flourishing requires the legal protection of those norms and values currently most popular seems entirely without merit. An Updated Version of the Asian Values Debate? We might, then, switch gears, and look at the more local version of the argument. On this analysis, what matters about a tradition is not that it is universally held, but that it is held around here; each individual society is possessed of its own tradition and history, and each society should have the right to promote human rights with reference to its 6

own, unique traditional values. This version of the argument would present the modern Russian proposal as an updated version of the Asian values debate of a previous generation; as in that argument, the chief contention to be considered is whether or not human rights should be modified in light of the local traditions of the local community. xi The argument of the proponent, here, is an argument against human rights universalism that begins with the same terms used by human rights practitioners: tolerance, respect, and dignity. It is, on this view, an affront to the dignity and selfrespect of the traditional society to have human rights presented to them as crossculturally valid absolutes. Human rights documents emerge from parochial conversations: from distinctively Western institutions and trajectories, which are insufficiently inclusive of the thoughts and traditions of other societies. To respect these traditional societies, though, is to respect the social worlds they have built together, and the traditions they endorse. If Western societies are to live up to the mutual respect they endorse, they must do so in light of these traditional values and modify or curtail their human rights absolutism in face of the traditions of other societies. I suspect something like this is at the heart of the Russian emphasis upon traditional values. I think the argument is powerful; I do not think it is right. I want to emphasize three distinct reasons to worry about this argument; each of these tells us something about why we should be worried about traditional values, as defended by this proposal. Three Reasons to Worry The first of these worries stems from simple empirical facts: there has never been a society that was not enormously complex in what actual traditions could be ascribed to it. We understand this as a matter of course about our own societies; one living in the United States, or France, would hesitate before saying definitively what the American or French traditions demanded in any particular social issue. Each society is, instead of a 7

set of distinctive values, something more like a distinctive kind of argument one in which certain threads and contentions might recur, but never with a final resolution or simple conclusion. xii Each society, moreover, tends to have both universal and particularistic strands within it; democratic notes were sounded in the history of the East, and communitarian ideas have flourished in the West. xiii Under these circumstances, to make a claim that a certain value is ours seems simply impossible; instead of describing an empirical reality, it tends instead to describe the will of the most dominant parts of society. Those who care about human rights, of course, should be enormously hesitant before taking the will of the strongest as a good reason to ignore the dignity of the weak. The second of these worries comes about in a consideration of the idea of mutual respect. A society that begins its argument with an ideal of respect is, wittingly or not, deploying a pattern of argument that commits it to a moral framework in which agents are worthy of respect; this framework, however, can end up demanding universal human rights, rather than limiting them. We can think of it this way: one who insists that their way of life is worthy of respect is saying, whether they want to or not, that people and what they build together are generally worthy of respect. Someone who says this, though, cannot consistently claim that the dignity of other persons is not a matter of moral gravity. If respect for agency is the start of the argument, then that respect is owed to all agents whether or not tradition would tend to endorse that respect. A society that uses the language of respect to mandate the legal protection of tradition, then, engages in something very much like self-contradiction when it cites that respect as a reason to dismiss the dignity or agency of others. I am reminded, here, of a relativist student of mine who refused to condemn even genocide; who are we, he said, to say that genocide isn t demanded by the value system they have developed over there for themselves? Maybe we disrespect them by insisting that genocide is wrong! His argument was flawed in a number of ways, of course, but it was most importantly flawed because it used the language of respect for agency to defend acts and practices that denied agency; we cannot think that we respect people, though, by respecting 8

those acts and practices that degrade them. So it is with traditional values ; respect for persons requires us to speak out against the marginalization of the weak, rather than simply defend the traditions of the strong. The final worry I want to address begins with a disquiet many of us will feel at this juncture. If the defender of traditional values has a point, I think it is this: we ought to be hesitant before we think we adequately understand the practices and values of another society. We ought to be careful, that is, that our reactions to the actions or policy taken by another society do not reflect our own ignorance and unwillingness to take seriously the agency of those outside our own social context. xiv The defender of traditional values invokes the legacy of colonial conquest and warfare, to note that the traditions we condemn are often those of societies more marginal than our own, and that their marginalization is related to historical patterns of atrocity and evil. Should we not, therefore, feel some historically grounded hesitancy, before insisting that another society s traditional values should be eliminated? The response to this worry, though, is to simply insist that modesty is not the same as deference. To be modest in one s claims is to acknowledge that evidence might change one s perspective; to defer, in contrast, is to say that the other party is and always will be in possession of some authority to define what that evidence shall say. The response to the legacy of colonialism should be, I think, to be modest in our willingness to say that the traditions of a given society are necessarily in conflict with the universal human rights we prize. We should, in other words, be willing to engage in discourse with the other party, to hear what it is like to be a part of their social world, before we condemn what they do. But to say this is not to endorse a deference, in which that other party is always able to define right simply with reference to their own form of life to their own traditional values. In the Russian context, we can certainly endorse a willingness to listen to the other party, to hear grievances that stem from the lack of respect shown to their particular acts and institutions. All this is true. Nothing in this, however, precludes us from saying that even after this conversation the 9

traditions in question ought to be overcome or eliminated. Modesty demands the willingness to hear; it does not demand that we agree. Conclusion My conclusion in this paper is simple: there is very little that can be said in favor of traditional values as a vehicle for the promotion or interpretation of human rights. The emergence of this framework within the HRC is to be lamented; the states of the world that prize human rights have a reason to work for a world within which human rights, unmodified by the considerations of traditional values, are more widely respected. If that conclusion seems to fly in the face of either social well-being or respect for societies, that is only because we often misunderstand what these concepts actually require. Traditional values would be, if integrated into human rights practice, a political disaster, gutting the core of what human rights demands; they would also be, I think, a moral disaster, in that there are no good arguments in favor of such integration. Traditions, for their value, must respect human rights; we should not let the former influence or override the latter. *) Michael Blake is author of Justice and Foreign Policy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013). 10

ENDNOTES i Nikolay Surkov, Russia to rejoin the UN Council on Human Rights, Russia Beyond The Headlines, 18 November 2013. ii A/HRC/21/L.2, Promoting human rights and fundamental freedoms through a better understanding of traditional values of mankind: best practices, 21 September 2012. iii Human Rights Council States Must Reject Traditional Values, Statement of 11 September 2013. Available at http://www.article19.org/resources.php/resource/37236/en/human-rights-council:- states-must-reject- traditional-values v Contribution of the European Union: Traditional Values, Statement of 15 February 2013. Available at http://www.ohchr.org/documents/issues/hrvalues/eu.pdf vi A/HRC/22/71. Study of the Human Rights Council Advisory Committee on promoting human rights and fundamental freedoms through a better understanding of traditional values of mankind, 6 December 2012. Available at http://www.ohchr.org/documents/hrbodies/hrcouncil/advisorycom/session10/a.hr C.22.71_en.pdf iv ARC International, Traditional Values: Fact Sheet. Available at http://arcinternational.net/global-advocacy/human-rights-council/hrc12/tv-fact-sheet vii Graeme Reid, Traditional Values code for human rights abuse? 17 October 2012, commentary for cnn.com. Available at http://globalpublicsquare.blogs.cnn.com/2012/10/17/traditional-values-code-forhuman-rights-abuse/ 11

viii Susan Okin, Justice, Gender, and the Family (New York: Basic Books, 1989). ix Patrick, Lord Devlin, The Enforcement of Morals (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965). x David M. Herszenhorn, Propaganda by Gays Faces Russian Curbs Amid Unrest, New York Times, 25 January 2013. xi See, on this, Daniel A. Bell, East Meets West: Human Rights and Democracy in East Asia (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000). xii I discuss this in my Justice and Foreign Policy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013). xiii Jack Donnelly, The Relative Universality of Human Rights, 28(6) Human Rights Quarterly (2007) 281-306. xiv On this, see Azizah Al-Hibri, Is Western Patriarchal Feminism Good for Third World/Minority Women? in Joshua Cohen et al., eds., Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women? (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999). Michael Blake Professor of Philosophy and Public Policy University of Washington Box 353350 Seattle, WA 98195 12